# taz.de -- Eva Illouz zum Nachlesen: Mehr Emotion wagen? | |
> Wie viel Gefühl verträgt eine Gesellschaft, die nach Gerechtigkeit | |
> strebt? Dieser Frage ging Eva Illouz auf dem taz.lab 2015 nach. Ein | |
> Transkript. | |
Bild: Eva Illouz (re.) und Julia Encke während der Lecture auf dem taz.lab 201… | |
Am 25. April trafen die Soziologin Eva Illiouz und die Journalistin Julia | |
Encke auf dem taz.lab 2015 für eine Lecture, samt anschließender Diskussion | |
zusammen. Die Veranstaltung, kuratiert von und ermöglicht in Kooperation | |
mit der Heinrich-Böll-Stiftung, fand in englischer Sprache statt. Das | |
Transkript des Vortrags von Eva Illouz bilden wir im folgenden – ungekürzt | |
– ab. taz | |
Eva Illouz: Thank you very much for inviting me, I love to be in Berlin. | |
Your newspaper is a very important one I think and I'm always happy to | |
support it in one way or another. | |
And I'm also happy for the opportunity to think about a topic, about which | |
in fact I have not really thought and more have research as it was said | |
just previously, research emotions in the private sphere, trying to show | |
really how the private sphere is structured by public processes, I would | |
say, or at least institutional processes and so this is for me almost the | |
first time that I have to think about the presence of emotions in politics. | |
Let me start then. Modern politics displays a paradox. Or modern liberal | |
politics displays a paradox. It is fundamentally based on the assumption of | |
rationality. That is on the assumption that citizens must choose leaders | |
rationally. And on the assumption that the public sphere is the site of | |
deliberation and debate. | |
And yet, modern politics having become mediated by images, print media, | |
story-telling, an endless flow of media stories and media images. So, | |
modern politics is particularly proned to the display, the diffusion and | |
the manipulation of emotions. | |
Of course, there is a way in which we could say that this is not new and | |
that the ancients, Plato, and Aristotle even more obivously, long | |
understood the relationship between emotions and political discourse | |
between narrative and rhetoric. | |
But I would say that they probably cannot provide us as guides to analyse | |
what is happening today in modern polities. Because I think they had a | |
qualitatively different understanding of the role of emotions, since it | |
concerned mostly the effect which leaders, and charismatic leadership in | |
particular, had on the emotions of their listener. | |
Their view of emotions was that it constituted a kind of manipulation, of | |
effective manipulation of the speech, of the orator, of the leader. Whereas | |
I think that emotions, as I am going now to explain in fact, I think that | |
emotions in contemporary politics should be understood in structural terms | |
and we should really invent, this is what social sciences do, they try to | |
map out the reality what we do with new concepts that we do not necessarily | |
have in everyday in ordinary language. | |
## Emotions in the political process | |
So, what I am saying is, that, I am not saying that emotions are irrelevant | |
to modern politics, but I am saying that the politics that the emotions of | |
the politics of liberal polities demand maybe a qualitatively different | |
analysis of the process involved than the one usually used in the analysis | |
of rhetoric. | |
So just to give a very trivial example, the use of images of modern | |
politics surely changes something to the formation of political opinions | |
and attitudes, and most crucially to the process by which emotions are | |
diffused. Not only how I acquire emotions, but also to the process of | |
contagion of emotions inside the social body. | |
I am going to submit the following proposition: And it is that emotions not | |
only inhere in the political process, in the modern political process, but | |
also that they are not necessarily unwelcome or inimical to the political | |
process. Or rather, if they are, I think we should need new terms how they | |
are and when they are unwelcome. | |
So emotions inhere in the political process and are even sometimes, and we | |
need to start with that proposition, they are sometimes even beneficial to | |
it. What do I mean? | |
Let me take a very famous research by the neuropsychologist António Damásio | |
who has showed that deliberative rationality, that is the very kind of | |
rationality that is involved in decision-making must be, in order to be | |
functional and to be really rational, must be informed by emotions because | |
only through emotions can you form an attitude. An emotional attitude | |
towards objects. | |
That is, only through emotions can you hierarchise your preferences and | |
figure out what is most urgent, what is most important to you. And it would | |
seem that this would be crucial for the process for example of voting or | |
forming a political attitude. So we cannot imagine, I mean if the voters | |
were entirely rational, what they would do, for loaning Antonio Damasio's | |
study, is that they would list attributes of each one of their candidates | |
and then they would try to figure out according to the list of attributes | |
they would try to decide who to vote for. | |
That does not help people vote. They vote with a kind of I would say rough | |
emotional complex that orients their political attitude. And that is good, | |
too, that is my point, that is good too because without it, we could not | |
form what we call rationality. | |
## Anxiety | |
That is something that people who study voting should really take into | |
consideration. This research in the neurophysiology of emotions and the | |
neurophysiology of rationality. Let me give you another example: Also what | |
I mean here, George Marcus has showed that moderate levels of anxiety | |
facilitate the search for and processing of political information among | |
voters. | |
Events that generate anxiety, for example, will make people who are | |
normally indifferent to the news look for information. And for people who | |
normally consume the news, it will make them read more than one newspaper, | |
read several newspaper, and therefore have a kind of more sophisticated | |
level of information. | |
So anxiety is entirely conducive, if you want here, to the process of the | |
formation of opinion and even to a better or more sophisticated, more | |
complete process of formation of opinion. | |
This, again, simply suggests that the traditional view that we should | |
separate emotion and rational opinion-making is simply not true in my | |
opinion. They do go in hand quite well. And I would say also, the same is | |
true about, for example anger that is expressed in the sentiment of | |
injustice. | |
We would view anger that denounces inustice, and that expresses itself as | |
moral indignation, in fact as entirely congruent with a good political | |
order. Therefore, if we have established that emotions are not necessarily | |
negative, that in fact they can even be positive and crucial to the | |
political process, I am going to ask, this is going to be the main purpose | |
of this very short presentation, I am going to ask then, when are emotions | |
negative in politics? When are they unwelcome? | |
Now, I do not have an extensive response, as I said I do not research this | |
topic at all, and I cannot review all the cases in which emotions are | |
unwelcome, but I am going to offer one proposition. I think one proposition | |
is enough in one paper just to think about. | |
But before I answer my question, I want to dispell another commonly held | |
view or opinion. Since the question I am asking is when are emotions | |
unwelcome in the political process, I think a fairly, I would say, well I | |
am going to use the word, a fairly lazy way to answer that question would | |
be to take the long list of negative emotions that we have, you know, envy, | |
contempt, anger, hatred etc. and say oh, well, we don't want those in the | |
political process. Again, I am sceptical of that strategy. Because the | |
reason why we view some emotions as negative is often from two stand | |
points. | |
One, it is from a moral stand point, from the stand point from the | |
moralists or the religious clergy, a very long religious and moral | |
tradition which has classified some emotions as more negative than others, | |
and i don't think that religion or morality are necessarily the area from | |
which we should get our normative guide lines. | |
Which does not mean they cannot inform politics, but I don't think they | |
should be the exclusive spheres of meaning providing our normative guide | |
lines to think about politics. That is my first thing to say. | |
## Socially useful emotions | |
And the second, also, the second main claim is that what can feel negative | |
from a subjective stand point is not necessarily negative at all from a | |
macrosocial, from a structural stand point. And let me give you just a few | |
examples of what I mean here, very quick examples of what I mean. | |
The 17th century philosopher Thomas Hobbes in his book De Cive famously | |
suggested that fear is constitutive of the state of nature. And that it is | |
fear that will make people enter in a social contract. And not the love of | |
others and not as we would say today the desire to help each other. | |
Not some altruistic motive, but some in fact contrarily self-interested | |
motive and the fear that someone is going to kill us. The fear of death is | |
extremely powerful in Thomas Hobbes' view of why and how people should get | |
together and form a covenant and a society. So here, obviously, fear is | |
able to be converted into something thas has good political status, which | |
is the formation of the social contract. | |
To take an even clear, and famous again, another famous example, of what I | |
mean here, in the 18th century, Bernard de Mandeville in his famous Fable | |
of the Bees argued that greed and envy could generate positive social goods | |
such as commerce and exchange. | |
And that these negative emotions which were certainly condemned by the | |
Christian church, greed and and envy, were converted in fact into socially | |
useful emotions, because they encouraged if you want economic activity. | |
They encouraged consumption and they encouraged production and work. | |
Or still, to use another very famous example, for Germans, as you remember | |
in the Weberian account of the development of capitalism, it is the anxiety | |
that is generated by the deus absconditus, the god that you do not see, the | |
god that is hidden. | |
So it is the anxiety that is generated by the deus absconditus that has not | |
revealed to us whether we have been elected or not. That anxiety is the | |
motivation, it is the motivational structure that brought a big macro | |
change in Europe, such as making labour into a worthy activity, into a | |
morally worthy activity. | |
You remember, this is the question that Weber asks, how it is that an | |
activity such as labour which is viewed entirely as contemptible becomes | |
actually a morally worthy activity. And what does that is the anxiety that | |
is produced by the protestant theology of the deus absconditus. | |
## Three possibilities | |
My point is clear here, and this is really I would say, theoretically this | |
should be my main point, we should really make a distinction between | |
individual and the structural analysis of emotions in politics. And without | |
that I think we will not be able to move very far. | |
What do I mean then by structural? This is what I want to describe briefly | |
before I move to answering the question I asked. So again, given that I am | |
not a specialist, I have separated three possibilities of a structural | |
analysis of emotions, there could be more. But I think these three seem to | |
be quite important, so even if there are more, I am happy to stay with | |
them. | |
One level of a structural analysis or structural existence of emotions | |
would be a level that I would call, which would be the aggregation of many | |
individual emotions. Such as, for example, take the example of the | |
collective anger. Which ends in demonstrations, mass protests, social | |
movements, social revolutions etc. | |
These movements are often the result of an individual emotion. Which, you | |
have many people having emotions, and I would say all kinds of emotions, it | |
could be anger, but not only, it could be disappointment, it could be | |
hatred, it could be many different people have different kinds of emotions | |
which we could label broadly and a broad label of opposition to or | |
dissatisfaction with or something like that. | |
These emotions are in turn, what sociologists say is that they are framed | |
by elite groups. Such as political leaders, head of social movements, | |
journalists, elite groups which then frame those emotions and transform | |
them into a coherent social movement. | |
Think for example of the French Revolution. Of the role of the bourgeoisie | |
and the intellectuals in framing, in providing what sociologists call a | |
cultural framing for social discontent. The framing effect of elites, of | |
newspapers, of intellectuals enable us to speak about structural emotions | |
that are located at the societal level and that are the aggregate effects | |
of many individual wills and emotions and that feed back into society. | |
## Individual anger becomes a collective or political anger | |
So for example, to take a very famous example in Germany, if you take | |
Michael Kohlhaas, famous character of a Kleist novel, you remember that he | |
is very angry, he is the victim of an injustice and his anger remains I | |
would say a private emotion until he starts, until he does two things: One | |
is to raise, to make a big discourse, a formal discourse, a moral discourse | |
that is listened by many when he goes to the court, when he appeals to | |
officials and he makes a principle discourse of justice. And two, when he | |
recruits others that are going to help him to attack the person who did big | |
injustice on him. | |
That individual anger becomes a collective or political anger, as soon as | |
Michael Kohlhaas is able to mobilize institutions, mobilize general | |
discourse, moral discourse and political discourse of injustice and to | |
recruit others around him. Or to take still another example, the mass | |
protests in Israel of 2011 were, I think, the aggregate effect of many | |
different emotions which were framed by the media. | |
I mean there was a struggle between the political elites which said these | |
are very spoilt brats of rich neighbourhoods, which are simply whining over | |
the fact that they cannot have a nice appartment in Tel Aviv. There was | |
this interpretation and many other interpretations which says no, this is a | |
much more fundamental discontent and anger. | |
And so there was a struggle over the appropriate framing of these emotions, | |
until, at a certain point, the emotions involved in the discontent were | |
stabilized if you want, you had a kind of commonly received claim that this | |
was a social protest that protested the high costs of living. So that is | |
the first level of a structural existence of emotions in politics. | |
The second level is located at what Raymond Williams, the great british | |
literary theorist called structures of feeling, which designate to opposite | |
phenomena. Feelings points to, first, when we say structure of feeling, it | |
points to a kind of experience that is incohate, that defined who we are | |
without being able to just say what is this who we are. | |
And yet the notion of structure also suggests that this level of experience | |
has an underlied pattern that is systematic rather than half fathered. So | |
think for example of fear, I am going to go back to this example. Think of | |
fear as an underlying structure of feeling of liberal polities after 9/11. | |
Especially after the US. | |
This is a kind of, I would say free floating climate, a general atmosphere, | |
a feeling that exists in between media stories and in between our | |
relationship to our political representatives. It is an affective register | |
that is underlied and produced by media images, stories, international | |
relations, policy measures by the state etc. | |
## Hope or despair | |
So, I think here we can speak of emotional moods, climates or affective | |
registers, whatever terminology you want to use, which are created by media | |
images, by media stories, that are relayed by politicians and by policy | |
making. Which may or may not be related to one single event, but which then | |
settle, kind of settle in a society. | |
They crystallize and they settle in a society. I think that 9/11 is a good | |
example, we could speak also of the Cold War as being a very good example | |
of that structure of feeling in which fear and the fear of communism and | |
the fear of the Soviets was really structural to the American political | |
psyche. | |
But we can speak also of a climate, certainly this is relevant in Europe, | |
we can also speak of a climate of hope or despair. So I would say there are | |
dominant affective registers in the political vocabulary of a country. So | |
an affective register I would say is more diffuse and more enduring than | |
very precise emotions that can be short lived. | |
And I think that Dominique Moïsi who wrote a famous book on the geography | |
of emotions, trying to characterize the world with dominant emotions. So | |
his thesis that American culture and the culture of the Middle East differ | |
profoundly because one is a culture of fear and the other one is a culture | |
of humiliation, I think that what he is really telling us is that there are | |
different affective registers in each one of these societies. | |
And the third structural level of emotions in politics is what I would say, | |
the emotions that are produced by the strongest actor in liberal polities, | |
namely the state. Which initiates actions and events that have an emotional | |
meaning and emotional effects on the citizens. We can think for example of | |
what I would call policies of hope as when the American Federal government | |
gave hundreds of millions of dollars to save the mega insurance company AIG | |
from collapsing. | |
That was not only an economic measure but also an emotional measure. We can | |
think also of the politics of memorialization which is organized around | |
such feelings as grief or guilt or forgiveness. Politics of memory, which | |
is initiated by the state. And such politics takes place as I would say, I | |
would say what is the politics of memory, it is in fact a state-emotional | |
act. | |
## The political act is the emotional act | |
It is a state-emotional ritual. It is a state-emotional ceremony in which | |
what you display, if you want, is a grief, loss, guilt, forgiveness etc. | |
So, all these are emotions that exist at the structural level, they are | |
public, they are externalized, whether at the level of collective | |
movements, whether in public spheres, whether at state policies. | |
And I would say that in each one of these cases, the ways in which emotion | |
makes meaning or produces meaning in the political sphere, in each case, it | |
is different. | |
Movement or protest, for example a social movement or what we call a | |
protest vote, this is emotion as politics, the political act is the | |
emotional act and the emotional act is the political act. In the second | |
case of the public sphere, the affective registers that are produced by the | |
kind of collaboration between policy making and media images, I would say | |
this is a representational way of making emotions present in the body | |
politic. | |
And the third case of the state, I would say this is a perfomative way of | |
making or creating emotions. Performative means that when I say, when a | |
state says, I officially apologize to the Armenian population, to the | |
Jewish population, to the Palestinian population, the state is actually | |
doing, creating an emotion simply by saying it, and this is possible | |
because the state is the strongest actor, it has the possibility of doing | |
this emotional performative act. | |
So, let me summarize what I have said so far, I have said that an emotion | |
that is negative for the individual, from a moral psychological stand | |
point, is not necessarily so from a collective or social stand point. And I | |
have also said that political emotions should be thought of as structural | |
phenomena. Not as the rhetorical effect of politician's discourse which is | |
how it has been thought traditionally. But rather as entities that inhere | |
in the structure of liberal polities. | |
To that extent, there is no way to long for a rational emotion, unless | |
political sphere, I think this is something that derives quite clearly from | |
what I say. It means that from a normative standpoint, we should not | |
necessarily strive for a politics that has more reason in it. | |
## Liberal polity as an answer | |
And here, I think that the liberal, the traditional liberal theory of the | |
public sphere as a politics that is governed by reason, patchy Habermas, I | |
am sorry, I think that theory is simply wrong. Or, you know, if it is | |
right, I think it puts the philosopher, the political philosopher in the | |
absurd position of constantly bemoaning and whining the fact that the | |
politics is too emotional. And I don't think this is a very productive | |
fact. | |
If emotions are intrinsically, as I said, a part of politics, then we | |
should understand them as inhering in it and we should try to, having this | |
understanding, we should try to redirect emotions, these emotions, as | |
emotions. | |
So this is why, I mean Judith, I much more like the account of Judith | |
Shklar, the philosopher Judith Shklar, who presented liberalism, she said | |
liberalism is the political theory that abhors fear more than any other | |
thing. And what she meant by that is that in the 17th century, when people | |
had been persecuted and when there had been wars of religion, there is this | |
search, this collective search in Europe for new political order in which | |
people would not fear the people who governed them. | |
And liberal polity is really an answer to that, it is about creating a | |
framework in which no one is afraid. In that sense, so Judith Shklar I | |
think puts really an emotion, the lack of fear into the heart of | |
liberalism. And I think this is more convincing. | |
Martha Nussbaum's recent book on political emotions is also important and | |
follows in fact that strand because she also offers a model of the good | |
polity as based on emotions and not on reason. She continues Shklar's | |
intuition about the emotional condition of liberalism, namely saying that | |
what is at the heart of liberalism is a certain emotional condition. | |
But, I mean I frankly didn't find that Martha Nussbaum's response was very | |
satisfactory. She thinks that we should put compassion and love at the | |
center of liberal polities, and I don't know, I just didn't find it very, I | |
don't find it personally extremely interesting, to tell you the truth. So, | |
if that is the case, let me ask again how we are then to criticize | |
normatively the use of emotions in politics? | |
## Fear | |
If emotions per se are not a problem, if negative emotions cannot always | |
predict a negative societal outcome, then how shall we criticize emotions? | |
I just have one suggestion. Not more, again, because this is not my topic. | |
I am going to say that when an emotion covers, hides a self-interest, a | |
collective self-interest, when it is used to cover a self-interest, and | |
when that emotion blocks discussion and public debate and political | |
participation, it is actually a very negative emotion. | |
I try to think of what kind of emotion would qualify, would respond to | |
these criteria I just defined. And for me, the emotion that is most | |
dangerous, I would say, to the political process today, certainly viewed | |
from Israel and I will say a few words about it right now, is the emotion | |
of fear. The emotion of fear. So, i will just conclude, I have another five | |
minutes as a conclusion, five, seven minutes to conclude by reflecting, I | |
would like to reflect on fear. And its highly negative role in my opinion | |
in politics. | |
Thomas Hobbes, the author of the Leviathan famously declared that when he | |
was born, his mother gave birth to twins. Him and fear. Which may, you | |
know, it is interesting because he then went on to become the philosopher | |
of fear. And we may wonder similarly if Netanyahu's regime was not also | |
born as a Hobbesian twin, as a kind of very particular view of Jewish | |
history and as a regime based on fear. That is why I would call Netanyahu | |
really a regime. | |
What characterizes that regime is the constant invocation of fear. Just to | |
give you an example, renewing his intention to hold on his controversial | |
and by now very infamous speech before the American Congress, this was back | |
in February, Netanyahu summed up his political philosophy at a Likud | |
conference in February, just a few months ago. He said: “I went to Paris, | |
not just as the Prime Minister of Israel, but as a representative of the | |
entire Jewish people.” | |
I didn't know that. I don't know who appointed him exactly. “Just as I went | |
to Paris, so I will go any place I'm invited to convey the Israeli position | |
against those who want to kill us. Those who want to kill us are first and | |
foremost any Iranian regime that says out right it plans to destroy us. I | |
will not hesitate to say what is needed to warn against this danger and | |
prevent it.” | |
So I think we have here one of the secrets for Netanyahu's uncanny, one has | |
to say that it has been an uncanny political success. One is that his | |
self-appointment as the proud and forceful representative of world Jewry | |
and his constant apocalyptical invocations of imminent and overwhelming | |
danger for the Israeli nation and the Jewish nation as a home. | |
## A new type of fear | |
So, we usually think it is interesting, as Judith Shklar, like Judith | |
Shklar usually think of fear as being the prerogative of you know, rogue | |
regimes, premodern regimes, abusive regimes, terror regimes, anything that | |
is not democratic and that is bad, illicits fear. And illicits fear from | |
the rulers to the governees. But I think that we are witnessing is that | |
fear is becoming more and more democratic, that is a dominant feeling in | |
democracies as well, and it is an emotion that is manipulated by political | |
elites in order, I would say simply, quite often in order to justify | |
foreign policy. | |
As if political emotion, fear is theatrical. In regimes of terror, this is | |
obvious. Because there are show trials, we burn books in public, we set up | |
public executions and we spread terror to intimidate what we designate as | |
our internal enemies. This is what characterizes a terror regime, it is the | |
theatralization of fear. | |
In democracies, which were based on the absence of fear, I think we are | |
witnessing increasingly a new type of fear in which fear is present. It | |
might be a bit less theatrical although it is also sometimes theatrical, | |
you know, see Daish, the Islamic State. And it spreads often in a less | |
centralized way. | |
And it is provoked by often what we view as our outer enemies, not our | |
inner enemies. And it is conveyed often more indirectly through the | |
televised spectacle of the news. So during the Cold War, or when we look at | |
images of terror attacks, 9/11, the Islamic State, all of that create | |
disgust, panic, fear and, what they do is that they create also, they | |
reinforce a kind of solidarity within democracies. | |
Such fears can have a deep impact on the politics of democracies. For | |
example a poll that was taken after 9/11 in the USA showed that a majority | |
of those polled had become more conservative. Thus, suggesting a direct | |
link between fear and conservative political orientation. Another poll | |
taken in 2004 in the USA showed a strong connection between thinking that | |
civil liberties can be suspended for security purposes and watching a lot | |
of TV news, going to church and voting Republican. | |
Conversely, those who thought that civil liberties should not be sacrificed | |
for security also had a more diverse source of news than TV, were more | |
likely to be secular and more likely to vote Democrat. In other words, | |
fear, I would say fear has become a part of a political ecology in which | |
journalists who are hungry for very graphic images with high emotional | |
impact, we have here the journalists who are looking for something that | |
suits their professional ethos. | |
## A powerful political instrument | |
We have political and economic elites invested in security, all of these | |
reinforce mutually each other and create a conservative voter willing to | |
suspend civil liberties. Few democratically elected heads of government | |
have made fear as blatantly defining of their political discourse as | |
Netanyahu. And fear is his surest and closest companion, like Thomas | |
Hobbes' twin. | |
It is Iran's nuclear power, it is the Arab world as a whole, it is Europe | |
who hates the Jews, it is the Jews themselves who have forgotten to be real | |
Jews and presumably about to destroy Jewish civilization, it is Isaac | |
Herzog who has betrayed the nation in going to the Munich security | |
conference, it is the Leftists who want to sell the country to the Arabs, | |
it is all those in short who want to bring the demise of Israel and the | |
Jews outside and inside. | |
So what has perhaps gone unnoticed, is that Netanyahu has uniquely mixed | |
the invocation of fear, he has mixed the invocation of fear that is found | |
in democracies and that is found in also less democratic regimes by mixing | |
the enemies outside and the enemies inside and saying there is a straight | |
line between the twos. The enemies inside, the left wingers who have | |
forgotten to be Jews are serving directly the European boycotters who want | |
actually to bring the demise of Israel. | |
So, we may wonder and this is my conclusion now, we may wonder why is fear | |
so powerful a political instrument. Of course, it gives intense, immediate | |
political benefits. Why? I want to ask why is fear so powerful actually? | |
Well, I am going to offer three answers. | |
Fear, far more than anger, justifies the aggressiveness and violence that | |
are at the heart of a certain view of international relations. In other | |
words, today, I think that going to war out of sheer anger or sheer | |
self-interest is more problematic than if you did it out of fear because of | |
the immoral language in which foreign policy is shrouded. | |
That is, it is easier to justify military aggressiveness or domination by | |
invoking fear, rather than by proudly claiming to be a bully. And I think | |
this would be relevant to some of the decisions that the United States have | |
made in the last decade, two decades or so. That is one. Fear is more | |
compatible with our moral views of international relations than anger or | |
self-interest. Two: Fear overrides not only thinking, but most importantly | |
all other emotions. As evolutionary biologists suggests, fear is the | |
emotion of pure survival. It helped us flee or fight. | |
Fear invades the psyche and overrides all other emotional reactions. So, if | |
fear is well manipulated in the public sphere, it is the emotion that will | |
win all other emotions. Such as the desire to improve my life, the | |
compassion for the distress of others, a sense of shame at my leader's | |
embarassing mistakes etc. The desire for survival will always trump all | |
other desires. This was exactly what Thomas Hobbes said. It will always | |
trump all others. | |
Fear then, is likely to become dominant in order to override other | |
emotional claims of the kind I just mentioned, such as the desire for | |
happiness or compassion for others. It is the trump card of any political | |
game. And finally, fear demands immediate action. | |
Rather than vision of the future or a long-term strategy. Fear is the | |
emotion of the here and now, it is the emotion of not only those who lack a | |
vision, but those, who by temperament for example Bush, want to go in now | |
and do something about it. And that is required in fear. | |
So, Judith Shklar was right. A liberal polity abhors fear. She spoke about | |
the fear that divided the leaders, the rulers, from the subjects. But we | |
may wonder if we should not now, if we are not the witnesses of a fear she | |
did not see. She passed away 20 years ago, she did not see, which is the | |
fear that creates solidarity vis-à-vis enemies, some of which are real, | |
some of which are, if not imagined, at least used too often, too easily, to | |
suspend human and civil rights and I think fear should be particularly | |
feared because it creates either aggressiveness, fight, or apathy, flight, | |
and is not compatible, I think it is the emotion that is truly not | |
compatible with democratic policies. | |
Therefore, if we want to maintain liberal and democratic polities, what | |
really we should fear is fear itself. Thank you. | |
EVA ILLOUZ | |
Transkription von Audio: Marion Bergermann | |
8 May 2015 | |
## AUTOREN | |
Marion Bergermann | |
## ARTIKEL ZUM THEMA |