(C) Common Dreams
This story was originally published by Common Dreams and is unaltered.
. . . . . . . . . .
John Brown’s “Madness” [1]
['Charles J. G. Griffin']
Date: 2024-12
This essay explores how divergent interpretations of John Brown’s alleged “madness” in the aftermath of the Harper’s Ferry Raid defined the meaning and import of his actions for the Republic’s increasingly unstable social and political order. It argues that popular characterizations of Brown illustrate that “madness” can serve a number of rhetorical functions in the civic sphere. The essay first explores the popular etiology of insanity in antebellum America. It then argues that prevailing views of insanity in the mid-nineteenth century invited three metonymic interpretations of the origins of Brown’s “madness”—and hence of the larger significance of his actions: Brown as pariah, Brown as pawn, and Brown as prophet. A concluding section discloses how these competing views may enrich our understanding of “madness” as a recurrent trope in American political and social controversy.
How admirable is the symmetry of the heavens; how grand and beautiful. Everything moves in sublime harmony in the government of God. Not so with us poor creatures. If one star is more brilliant than others, it is continually shooting in some erratic way into space. —John Brown, 1856
John Brown’s revelation to an eastern reporter as the two studied the night sky from a Kansas field one summer evening in 1856 proved uncannily prophetic.1 Three years later, the scourge of Bloody Kansas and a small group of followers briefly seized the Federal Arsenal at Harper’s Ferry, Virginia. The raiders hoped to rally slaves from nearby plantations and lead them on a campaign of liberation throughout the South. Brown’s audacious movement and its repercussions for a nation already teetering on the edge of civil war have been the subject of endless speculation and debate ever since.2 For many observers, the Harper’s Ferry Raid has come to symbolize the peril that fanatical [End Page 369] devotion to a cause, however noble, can pose to civil society. Others have seen it as a shining, principled moment in the nation’s history, a hammer blow that shattered the brittle veneer of civility and compromise that safeguarded slavery. In the storm of popular commentary that surrounded the event itself, everyone, it seemed, had an opinion about the strange, charismatic figure who, Samson-like, set out to pull down the Republic on his own head.
But on one point, at least, a great many of Brown’s contemporaries were agreed: Brown himself was almost certainly “mad.” In pulpits, public meetings, and a significant number of the nation’s 4,000 newspapers, North and South, Brown was routinely judged to be “deluded,” “fanatical,” “maniacal,” or “crazed.” The indefatigable diarist George Templeton Strong confided to himself that Brown’s foray was an “insane transaction” and feared it might lead to “grave results” if prominent northern abolitionists were found to be involved. Even abolitionist editor William Lloyd Garrison wondered at Brown’s “misguided, wild, and apparently insane” adventure.3 But although the fact of Brown’s “madness” was ceded by most contemporaries, its meaning was sharply disputed. Some pointed to heredity or personal tragedy as the source of Brown’s derangement, dismissing Harper’s Ferry as a frightening but isolated incident. Others saw Brown as a man driven to insanity by the words or deeds of others, arguing that the raid was representative of the increasingly chaotic and irrational state of the Union itself. And still others believed that Brown’s mania was divinely inspired, his raid a providential intervention into the nation’s affairs.
This essay explores how divergent interpretations of John Brown’s alleged “madness” in the aftermath of the Harper’s Ferry Raid defined the meaning and import of his actions for the Republic’s increasingly unstable social and political order. It argues that popular characterizations of Brown illustrate that political insanity can serve a number of rhetorical functions in relation to the civic sphere. The essay first explores the popular etiology of insanity in Antebellum America. It then argues that prevailing views of insanity in the mid-nineteenth century invited three metonymical interpretations of the origins of Brown’s “madness”—and hence of the larger significance of his actions: Brown as pariah, Brown as pawn, and Brown as prophet. A concluding section discloses how these competing views may enrich our understanding of madness as a recurrent trope in American public controversy.
A Popular Etiology of Madness in Antebellum America The debate over Brown’s “madness” must be understood within the context of the popular etiology of insanity in the mid-nineteenth century. Then, as now, the average American’s understanding of insanity was an amalgam of received wisdom, scientific study, and personal prejudice.4 As a result, public [End Page 370] attitudes toward the insane were confused and often ambivalent. They were frequently shunned, mocked, and persecuted as unwelcome object lessons in the perils of private or public sin. But they could be regarded with an almost superstitious veneration as well. After all, Western tradition has long associated madness with the genius of the poet and the foresight of the prophet.5 Whether they were kept at home, confined in institutions, or simply left to wander the streets, the “mad” maintained a tenuous relationship to civil society, at least as it was envisioned in Republican theory: they were agents of disruption in an ordered world, shooting stars within the symmetry of the heavens. The late eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries witnessed the first scientific efforts to study and treat insanity in Western Europe and the United States. Following the pioneering work of Philippe Pinel and William Tuke, and reformers such as Dorothea Dix, efforts to treat the insane on a more systematic and humane basis took hold in Western Europe and the United States by mid-century.6 Along with the penitentiary, public school, and temperance meeting, the insane asylum took its place at the vanguard of a new age of social reform.7 The origins, nature, and treatment of madness were fashionable topics in scholarly and popular journals of the period. In general, insanity was thought to result when severe stress was placed on a “constitutionally weak nervous system.”8 The stress itself could originate internally—the result of hereditary disposition, illness, injury, alcoholism—or externally from a sudden reversal in business, grief over the loss of a loved one, or religious agitation. By midcentury some observers found inducements to insanity just about everywhere, and especially in “the exceptionally open and fluid quality of American society” itself.9 To be sure, the era’s rough-and-tumble economic conditions, religious excitements, and political and social upheavals played havoc with long-established patterns of life. Sudden fortune and sudden financial ruin seemed ever-present possibilities and with them came constant pressure to get—and stay—ahead. As Toqueville, writing in the 1830s, had foreseen, if industrialized democracy opened new vistas for those with ambition, it also introduced new ways those ambitions could be frustrated. When all of the privileges of birth and fortune are abolished, when all professions are accessible to all, and a man’s own energies may place him at the top of any of them, an easy and unbounded career seems open to his ambition. . . . But this is an erroneous notion, which is corrected by daily experience. The same equality which allows every citizen to conceive these lofty hopes, renders all the citizens less able to realise them: it circumscribes their powers on every side, while it gives freer scope to their desires. . . . [T]his constant strife between the propensities springing from the equality of conditions and the means it supplies to satisfy them harasses and wearies the mind.10 [End Page 371] Mounting sectional tensions over slavery in the 1840s and 1850s only intensified the emotional turmoil and sense of crisis that were thought to foster insanity in the vulnerable. As David J. Rothman notes, “The style of life in the new republic seemed willfully designed to produce mental illness. Everywhere they looked, they found chaos and disorder, a lack of fixity and stability.”11 Medical authorities of the period held that insanity could manifest itself in a number of ways: melancholia, mania, monomania, dementia, and idiocy.12 Of these, the species of insanity most often associated with Brown by observers at the time was monomania. Monomaniacs were characterized by the ability to reason and behave normally in most situations accompanied by a tendency to “become irrational and obsessive on specific subjects.”13 The monomaniac was thus only “partially insane,” though perhaps all the more dangerous for this, because much of the time, he or she seemed an intelligent, reasonable person. But in pursuit of his or her obsession, the monomaniac could become implacable and ruthless, forsaking friends, family, even life itself in the headlong pursuit of a desired (and usually unrealistic) goal. One of the most compelling portraits of monomania produced during this period was that of Captain Ahab in Herman Melville’s 1851 novel, Moby Dick. Although the novel was not a commercial success, it vividly captures ideas popular at the time about the nature of monomania and its potential dangers to society. Melville’s antagonist, Ahab, is a competent and successful mariner, a man who has risen to the top of his profession. But he also bears grievous physical and psychological wounds, the legacies of an earlier encounter with the malevolent white whale, “Moby Dick.” After a tortuous convalescence, Ahab gradually regains his physical strength. He is fitted with a new leg and given command of the whaler Pequod. But, as Melville cautions readers, “Ahab, in his hidden self, raved on,” tormented by a compulsion to wreak vengeance on the white whale.14 At sea, Ahab’s behavior grows increasingly erratic. He broods alone in his cabin by day and paces the deck fitfully by night. “If such a furious trope may stand,” Melville writes of his tragic antagonist, “his special lunacy stormed his general sanity, and turned all its concentrated cannon upon its own mad mark; so that, far from having lost his strength, Ahab, to that one end, did now possess a thousandfold more potency than he ever had sanely brought to bear upon any one reasonable object.”15 Magnified by madness, Ahab’s virulent compulsion quickly infects the Pequod’s crew until they, too, are won over to his single-minded quest. It is, as every reader of the novel learns, the death of them all.
Madness and the Civic Sphere Melville could hardly have drawn a starker portrait of the monomaniacal leader willing to wreak havoc in pursuit of his mark. As Leland M. Griffin conjectured [End Page 372] of President Kennedy’s alleged assassin Lee Harvey Oswald, the turn to violence is all too seductive when ambition and heroic vision are unbridled from some internal “principle of self-restraint.” “The problem seems to be that the dreamer of Utopia—of all beings truly ‘rotten with perfection’—once convinced by an internal rhetoric of the virtue of his New Order, is tempted to bring it to power, to ‘round things out,’ by any means possible”16 But Ahab, at least, was a fictional character in a not very successful novel. On the other hand, John Brown, obsessed with slavery and willing to wreck the Union to secure its demise, was a figure all too real. What was the meaning of his “special lunacy” and what did it portend for the country? To appreciate the range of responses to Brown’s alleged monomania, it is important to understand late antebellum views of the nature and vulnerabilities of the civic sphere. Although Jürgen Habermas initially conceived of the “public sphere” as a space for enlightened debate and discussion, I use a variant of the term here to denote instead the collective norms operating at any one time to circumscribe the legitimate modes of civic expression. In American political culture, the civic sphere is both dynamic and contested; it can and does transform itself over time, conferring respectability on previously unknown or proscribed forms of expression while casting aside others that have become outmoded. Moreover, as James Darsey has argued persuasively, there is a long and honorable “prophetic tradition” in American culture that frequently tests the limits of civility and decorum in civic discourse.17 But the fundamental tendency of the civic sphere over time is toward coherence and stasis of some kind. Thus, although it can accommodate new forms of dissent, the civic sphere is also stable enough to enable parties that strongly disagree on the issues to concur nonetheless that certain types of (usually violent) protest behavior, such as assassination, kidnapping, insurrection, and mob actions, lie squarely outside its boundaries. For instance, historian Kimberly Smith argues that in the post-Revolutionary period, public rioting by aggrieved groups was a relatively common and legitimate vehicle of social and political protest, at least in certain circumstances. However, as less volatile avenues of civic expression opened up to a greater number of citizens in the early nineteenth century, mob action became less acceptable as a form of civic expression.18 When they do occur, breaches of something so essential to a democratic polity as the norms of public controversy are apt to occasion soul-searching concerning the integrity and resiliency of the civic sphere itself. An assassination or insurrection may in this way come to be viewed as a metonymic indicator of some disorder afflicting society-at-large.19 For example, in the aftermath of the Kennedy assassination, commentators anguished over the “climate of extremism” said to have been responsible for the president’s death. President Lyndon [End Page 373] Johnson’s frequent evocation of Isaiah 1:18 (“Come let us reason together.”) over the following months may be understood in this respect as a kind of “secular prayer” (“the coaching of an attitude”) aimed at restoring calm to the civic sphere.20 Three decades later, after Timothy McVeigh and an accomplice blew up the Murrah Federal Building in Oklahoma City in 1995, President Clinton voiced the concerns of many when he recognized the need to “purge ourselves of the dark forces which gave rise to this evil. They are forces that threaten our common peace, our freedom, our way of life.”21 In her recent study of political engagement during the antebellum period, The Dominion of Voice, Smith argues that the boundaries of appropriate public discourse remained unusually fluid in the half century following the American Revolution. Having rejected a traditional society in which the norms of public expression were clear, if highly deferential and restrictive, Americans adopted competing ideas about how they should participate in democratic society. Similarly, John M. Murphy asserts that the founders anticipated the difficulty of establishing a stable public sphere in a nation of competing interests and loyalties. In response, he urges, they sought to inculcate through precept and example a model of citizenship that was “cool, prudent, disciplined and deferential,” and willing to sacrifice self-interest to the public good. And historian Peter Knupfer contends that, ever-conscious of the potential for single interest factions to tear apart the Union, the post-Revolutionary generation consciously instantiated “compromise” as a civic value. Even Darsey allows that “dread of chaos was epidemic in early-nineteenth-century America.”22 Within this logic, Brown’s violent challenge to the dominion of reasoned deliberation was ipso facto “irrational” and possibly indicative of a much larger threat to the civic sphere. But from whence that threat came and with what measures it should be met was less clear. Answers to these questions depended largely upon whether one believed that the civic sphere, as then constituted, was capable of coping with the passions aroused by slavery. For Americans who felt that the civic sphere could weather this storm, as it had so many before, the maintenance of stability and order remained the paramount consideration. Some of these dismissed Brown as a deluded, self-aggrandizing fanatic—a pariah whose protest should be ignored. Others agreed that Brown was a dangerous monomaniac, but believed that he had been driven to this state by the rancorous controversy surrounding slavery. For these observers, Brown was merely the pawn of malignant political factions whose extremism, if unchecked, threatened to destroy the civic sphere. For a third group of contemporary observers, Brown’s “madness” signified something altogether different: paradoxical proof that the civic sphere itself had grown dangerously disordered. To these observers, Brown was a prophet, whose defense of the innocent could only be viewed as “mad” within a civic sphere that had itself [End Page 374] become morally compromised through its complicity with the abomination of slavery. It is important to note that all three of these views were articulated from both sincere and cynical motives (and sometimes both at the same time). One might, for example, hold that Brown truly was insane, a tragic figure, and still appreciate the political capital to be gained by blaming his “madness” on one’s political foes. Similarly, one might believe that Brown was quite sane, yet recognize that he could be discredited by being labeled mad. It is doubtless impossible to know with any certainty whether individual users of the three tropes of “madness” were in earnest or merely exploiting an opportunity to promote (or discredit) an ideology. What is clear is that all three views were voiced in the aftermath of Brown’s raid and that each invited a differing interpretation of its meaning.
Brown as Pariah Popular opinion in Antebellum America held that “madness” typically originated when some inherent flaw or weakness within an individual’s mental character was subjected to severe stress. Everything from a physical injury to the brain, to the effects of alcoholism, to traumatic experiences, to an over-stimulated imagination might trigger insanity in a weak constitution. Grounding insanity in an “imbalance” between a weak-minded individual and a stressful or turbulent environment invited speculation as to whether the behavior of the “mad” had any real social significance. Charles E. Morris notes that “madness” could be a politically expedient diagnosis as well, because “the cultural discourse of madness . . . serves readily and efficiently as a rhetorical mechanism with which the rebellious might be disciplined or silenced.” Indeed, Morris has argued that nineteenth-century concepts of gender, power, and madness conspired to silence abolitionist agitator Abigail Folsom in just such a fashion.23 Morris demonstrates how an accusation of “madness” can insulate a movement’s leadership from the unruly behavior of one of its own members, even as movement leaders profess sympathy for his or her motives. In a similar vein, M. Jimmie Killingsworth and Jacqueline S. Palmer have shown how some early environmentalists were dismissed as “hysterical” by their foes in the agribusiness and chemical industries.24 More recently, politically embarrassing revelations concerning allegedly corrupt actions by Illinois governor Rod Blagojevich that threatened to reflect badly upon the incoming Obama administration were arguably minimized by attributing the governor’s behavior to “madness.”25 While the use of invective to silence one’s opponents is hardly new, a charge of “madness” has distinct advantages when applied to individuals or groups whose actions directly challenge the legitimacy of the civic sphere [End Page 375] itself. First, it renders problematic any critique of the civic sphere raised by the actions of the accused. One can, after all, negotiate with a rational adversary, but there is no negotiating with a monomaniac who, by definition, compromises with no one. Second, by isolating and diminishing the credibility of the accused, it underscores the apparent rationality of the public sphere as it is. For the unreasonableness of one’s opponents doubtless bolsters one’s own claims to reasonableness.26 But although Brown was neither the first nor the last social activist to be labeled “mad,” he was in some respects unique in earning that appellation from his friends as well as his enemies. In this regard, Abolitionists and Fireaters, Unionists and Disunionists, Republicans and Democrats—parties that could agree on almost nothing else—found some common ground, however temporary. It is true that the fear and outrage inspired by Brown’s raid were more pronounced in the South. Even so, the widespread consensus that Brown’s behavior had been irrational offered some reassurance to those worried about the possibility of a violent sectional conflict that the norms of republican civility were still in force. Hence, by labeling Brown “mad,” opinion leaders in the press and politics could effectively contain the damage caused by Harper’s Ferry and even, in a sense, convert it to their own advantage. Brown-as-pariah provided a kind of scapegoat whose exclusion from the public sphere might cleanse and heal a divided nation. It is not surprising, therefore, that many public commentaries in the raid’s aftermath discounted it as the product of one man’s fevered imagination. Brown, it was argued, was a pathetic figure, a victim of heredity, perhaps, and certainly of his own delusions of grandeur. He represented no one except himself. The most ardent champions of the Brown-as-pariah trope may have been Republican politicians and editors. Their reasoning is understandable, given that secessionists and Democratic leaders, North and South, were eager to tie Brown to the new party. Brown’s actions seemingly placed Republican leaders on the horns of a dilemma. Republicans could not pretend to be a truly national party unless they condemned Brown’s “assault” on the South. At the same time, they could not affirm their antislavery credentials unless they defended Brown, or at least expressed sympathy with his ends. In the end, they chose to split the difference, by condemning his actions as an “irrational” response to an honorable cause. For example, the Republican-leaning Chicago Press and Tribune professed sympathy with Brown’s desire to help the slaves, but lamented the “fanaticism which led him to his present strait.” In Pittsburgh, the Gazette editorialized: We cannot but disapprove his mad and folly-stricken act, but the unselfishness of his deed; his moderation, when victorious, over the town which he captured; his [End Page 376] spartan courage in defending himself and his fellows, and his sublime contempt of death while overborne and made the manacled tenant of a prison; his stern integrity in scorning the technicalities of the law, and his manliness in all things, will not be quickly forgotten.27 Abraham Lincoln, testing the presidential waters out in the Kansas territory, lamented: “Old John Brown has just been executed for treason against a state. We cannot object, even though he agreed with us in thinking slavery wrong. That cannot excuse violence, bloodshed, and treason.” In nearby Lawrence, Kansas, a local paper summed up the affair: “Poor silly fellows! A straightjacket should be their reward, for they lack moral responsibility because of lunacy.”28 Brown’s legal team did attempt to mount an insanity defense for their client. Working feverishly, they collected more than two dozen affidavits from friends and relatives of their client in an effort to establish that he was now and had been insane for years. Had the effort succeeded, Brown might have been spared the gallows, but the significance of his acts would surely have been severely diminished. Brown must have realized this, for he strenuously objected to every suggestion that he was not of sound mind.29 One contemporary historian has argued that Brown and Virginia Governor Henry Wise (under whose jurisdiction Brown was tried) shared a tacit understanding that precluded an acquittal on the grounds of insanity. Wise needed Brown to be seen as sane by the public because only then did his actions provide tangible proof of Northern designs on the interests of the South. Wise’s political ambitions demanded that he slay a formidable dragon, not a deluded loner. For his part, Brown needed above all to be taken seriously. In any event, the effort to have Brown acquitted at trial on grounds of insanity came to nothing. And Brown was duly convicted on charges of murder and treason against the state of Virginia. Appeals for clemency on the grounds that Brown was insane came from many quarters, right up to the day of the hanging. But Wise refused to stay the execution.30
Brown as Pawn The ambiguity inherent in the popular notion that insanity arose from an imbalance between a subject’s weakened mental constitution and a stressful environment opened the possibility for multiple interpretations of the cause and significance of Brown’s alleged derangement. Emphasizing the former could support the conclusion that Brown alone was responsible for his actions and that they signified little about the state of overall health of the Republic’s civic sphere. Emphasizing the latter produced an entirely different set of conclusions about the meaning of his actions. [End Page 377] Opinions varied among those who saw Brown as a product or extension of larger forces operating within (or upon) the civic sphere. Southern editorialists, defenders of slavery, and Democratic leaders tended to blame Northerners, opponents of slavery, and Republicans, for Brown’s antisocial behavior. Northerners blamed slaveholders and Democrats. But regardless of their viewpoints on the origins of Brown’s insanity, proponents of the Brown-as-pawn trope tended to embrace one of two views about its significance. One view held that Brown had been driven to “madness” by the bitterly partisan rhetoric in which both sides of the slavery debate increasingly indulged. His “madness” was but a harbinger of some darker and far greater rhetorical disorder that threatened to destroy the equilibrium of the civic sphere. The other held that Brown’s insanity resulted not from words, but from deeds of violence committed against him or his sons during his Kansas sojourn earlier in the decade. In both views, Brown was depicted as a fairly normal citizen whose capacity to function rationally within the civic sphere had been subverted by the slavery controversy. Those inclined to attribute Brown’s fanaticism to the prevailing rhetorical climate in the late 1850s differed, of course, over just whose “violent speech” had incited Brown.31 Foes of slavery offered a range of possibilities. For example, the Chicago Press and Tribune put the blame on Congress: “As respects the attempt of an insane old man and his handful of confederates to excite a negro insurrection in Virginia and Maryland, it is easy to determine where the responsibility really belongs. The act is but a part of the legitimate fruit of the repeal of the Missouri Compromise.” Lyman Trumbull (R-IL), on the other hand, argued on the Senate floor that the Democratic Party was to blame for Harper’s Ferry, because it had failed to repudiate a similar raid by proslavery forces on the Federal Arsenal at Liberty, Missouri, in 1855. Yet another opinion was voiced by Thurlow Weed’s Albany Journal, which blamed the incident on slave holders who planted the idea of insurrection in the minds of slaves by continually fussing about abolitionists’ plans to free them. Had not such agitation incited Brown’s mad movement?32 On the other hand, the raid unleashed a storm of invective from critics who saw Brown as the product of virulent antislavery discourse. Memphis Appeal, for example, insisted that if indeed Brown was crazy, he had been made so “by the teachings of abolitionists” and that the “only tendency of abolition theories is anarchy, bloodshed and confusion.” The Nashville Union and American asserted a commonly held view in the South that “Abolitionism is working out its legitimate results in encouraging fanatics to riot and revolution. . . . For the fanatics engaged there would never have dared the attempt at insurrection but for the inflammatory speeches and writings of Seward, Greeley, and the other Republican leaders.” The Richmond Enquirer sounded an equally common theme, asserting that the Republican Party had “impelled [Brown and his [End Page 378] followers] forward in their mad career of treason and bloodshed.” Some commentators laid the blame for Brown’s actions on the words of specific individuals. The Republican Banner and Nashville Whig editorialized, “The effect of the speeches of [Senator William] Seward, [Representative Joshua] Giddings, and other prominent leaders of the Republican Party is to inflame the minds of such fanatics as Ossawatomie Brown and his confederates, and incite them to deeds of blood upon the holders of slaves,” a view seconded by newspapers such as the Raleigh, North Carolina, Register, which concluded that “fanaticism at the North is rampant, and overrides every thing.”33 Nor were such opinions confined to Southern editorialists. James Gordon Bennett’s New York Herald asserted that Brown’s sympathies had been inflamed and exploited by the “Black Republicanism” of men such as William Seward and Charles Sumner: “They—not the crazy fanatic John Brown—are the real culprits; and it is they, not he, who, if justice were fairly meted out would have to grace the gallows.” The newspaper called him “a victim of the mad fanaticism which would plunge the country into bloodshed for its own gratification.” Another newspaper in Concord, New Hampshire, decried Brown and the instigators of “these fools and madmen.” And in his annual message to Congress in 1859, President Buchanan denounced Brown’s raid and worried that it was a symptom of “an incurable disease in the public mind, which may break out in still more outrages.”34 Another body of opinion attributed Brown’s madness to his searing experiences in “Bloody Kansas” three years earlier. There, Brown had lost one son to Border Ruffians. Another had been beaten nearly to death and scarred for life. Brown himself was suspected in the murder of five proslavery settlers. The abolitionist orator Wendell Phillips, speaking at Henry Ward Beecher’s Plymouth Church in Brooklyn, argued that “the South planted the seeds of violence in Kansas and taught peaceful Northern men familiarity with the bowie-knife and the revolver. They planted nine hundred ninety-nine seeds, and this is the first one that has flowered.”35 In the Senate, Ben Wade of Ohio alleged that the violence done to Brown’s sons had maddened him: “Undoubtedly, sir, that raid was the parent of this. . . . I believe that he was maddened by the scenes through which he passed in Kansas, because I do not believe that any sane man on earth would have undertaken the enterprise that he undertook at Harper’s Ferry.”36 The Albany Evening Journal similarly theorized that in Kansas, Brown was robbed of his property, maltreated, his house was burned, and three of his sons murdered in cold blood. It is not strange that these wrongs kindled in him a thirst for revenge amounting to monomania. Brooding over them, he has conceived the wildest plans for repaying them, not only upon the guilty authors of his own misery, but upon all Slaveholders. The whole transaction at Harper’s [End Page 379] Ferry evinces this. None but a madman could seriously expect that twenty men could make head against the whole Union, and none but those whose sense of Justice was blunted by deep passion could fail to see that they were committing a crime against Innocent men, women, and children, which would inevitably meet, and justly deserve, universal condemnation. The next day, the Journal expanded its indictment: “But who made Brown a madman by murdering his sons? Who taught that crazy crew to band together with arms in their hands, as the most effective way to accomplish political purposes? The Border Ruffians of Kansas and the Democratic Administration at Washington!”37 Later on the Senate floor, Republican James Doolittle of Wisconsin wondered rhetorically, “Where did Brown get his education? Who taught him to draw blood on this question, and to open up the sluices of civil discord and civil war?” To which Tennessee’s Andrew Johnson countered that Brown’s raid was the “legitimate result” of antislavery agitation, declaring that “John Brown did not go to Kansas to go to school. He went there as a teacher.”38
Brown as Prophet Portrayals of Brown as pariah and as pawn presuppose that, in a democracy, ideological fervor taken to the point of inflicting or suffering violence is, by definition, “irrational.” To be sure, Brown’s actions went well beyond the usual limits of incivility or civil disobedience. It is one thing to spend the night in jail for not paying one’s poll tax, quite another to lead an armed assault against a federal installation. Even those who otherwise approved of Brown’s audacious undertaking struggled to understand his reasoning. What were his intentions once the arsenal had been secured? How could he have hoped to succeed with so small a force? Why did he not flee Harper’s Ferry when it became clear that the raid had failed? What was he thinking? Yet, for at least some of Brown’s defenders, the very insanity of the raid on Harper’s Ferry confirmed that it had been divinely inspired. Brown was “mad” all right, at least as the world reckoned such things, but his was the mania (enthousiasmos) of the prophet. Like a latter-day Jeremiah, Brown had been sent by God to chastise and redirect a nation that had lost its moral bearings and gone seriously astray. It was, after all, a commonplace among radical abolitionists that the Union as it was amounted to a pact with the devil. “Compromise” was, for them, not a virtue but an enabler of vice. Of Wendell Phillips, the movement’s most strident voice, Darsey writes: The mentality of compromise that Phillips excoriated in both politics and the church was intended by its proponents as the vehicle for continued unity. It was [End Page 380] a beguiling notion in its passivity—“live and let live.” It was not a strenuous doctrine. It reflected the realities of the world in all its imperfections. But compromise also has a sharply dyslogistic element: it does not always preserve the interests of opposing elements in mutual deference and respect, but sometimes surrenders one to the other. Compromise can be a “shameful or disreputable concession,” particularly when it is the self that is compromised. . . . In an age where the self is asserted only through the exercise of virtue, the life of ease involves the horrible anxiety of the loss of self, a condition of slavery. And for radical abolitionists such as Phillips, compromise with slavery amounted not only to a “failure of moral vision” at the national level, but to a surrender of personal integrity on the part of every “free” man as well.39 No one was more certain of this truth that Brown, himself. While he did not consider himself to be possessed or irrational, Brown certainly believed himself to be divinely appointed to the work of destroying slavery (a fact that doubtless convinced many others that he was “mad”). In a dramatic post-capture interview widely reported in the North, Brown had been asked: “Do you consider yourself an instrument in the hands of Providence?” “I do,” he calmly replied. Later in the same interview, one of Brown’s interrogators had asserted: “I think you are fanatical.” In reply, Brown defiantly turned the accusation back on its maker: “And I think you are fanatical. ‘Whom the Gods would destroy, they first make mad.’ And you are mad.”40 Brown’s trial, which formally commenced on October 27, 1859, and played out over the next two and a half weeks, afforded additional opportunities to affirm his status as a divinely appointed martyr. Indeed, Marouf Hasian has argued that Brown ingeniously exploited the situation to transform himself into the “iconic embodiment of the natural law itself,” and that his deliberate “blurring of the secular and the sacred allowed millions of Americans to visualize the possibility that natural laws could be both beautiful and reasonable.”41 Brown’s moving plea to the court at the trial’s conclusion, writes Stephen Oates, was intended to “win an entire generation to his side.” But it failed to impress the trial judge, who sentenced him to hang on December 2, 1859.42 Between his sentencing and execution three weeks later, Brown received a steady stream of visitors and corresponded regularly with family, friends, and supporters throughout the North. Brown’s composure during these last weeks and masterful manipulation of the rhetorical possibilities of his confinement helped to lay the foundation for his enduring martyrdom. Brown’s jailhouse correspondence testifies eloquently to his faith in the transcendent purposes of his work and to his confidence that it had set in motion the machinery that would one day end slavery. It is clear that Brown believed himself to be playing a central role in a grand historical drama. As he wrote to one Boston friend: “I [End Page 381] know that the very errors by which my scheme was marred were decreed before the world was made. I had no more to do with the course I pursued than a shot leaving a cannon has to do with the spot where it shall fall.”43 Perhaps the most notable public proponent of the Brown-as-prophet trope was the philosopher and essayist Henry David Thoreau. On hearing the news of Brown’s execution, Thoreau famously apotheosized his subject: “Some eighteen hundred years ago, Christ was crucified; this morning, perchance, Captain Brown was hung. These are the two ends of a chain which is not without its links. He is not old Brown any longer; he is an angel of light.” As for Brown’s executioners, Thoreau pronounced them “but helpless tools in this great work. It was no human power that gathered them about this preacher.”44 Abolitionist orators such as Wendell Phillips argued that Brown was doing God’s work, identifying him with Protestant heroes Jan Wycliffe and John Huss, as well as the early Christian martyrs. “It is honorable, then, to break bad laws, and such law breaking history loves and God blesses,” pronounced the Reverend George Cheever, an influential New York Congregationalist. John Brown is “God’s handwriting on the wall of Slavery; and the knees of the whole South knock together at the apparition. John Brown is God’s own protest against this tyranny, against the unrighteous laws that sanction it, against the men and states that support it.” At a memorial service for Brown held only days later, Cheever compared Brown’s apprenticeship to that of the prophet Jeremiah. Attended by such angels, commissioned by such words, John Brown grew onward to the sphere of character and duty for which God had appointed him. The same influence in kind came upon him as came upon Jeremiah, the same concentration and intensifying of Divine revelation in one direction, as always happens when God pleases, and when, for his own great purposes, He will discipline and prepare a man for Himself, to bear the reproach among men of being a fanatic,—a man of one idea.45 James Freeman Clarke, fellow abolitionist and prominent Unitarian minister in Boston, labeled Brown’s raid “one of those acts of madness which History cherishes, and which Poetry loves forever to adorn with her choicest wreaths of laurel.” Still other ministers compared Brown to Samson, Moses, John the Baptist, and in the case of at least one Southern divine, Satan.46
[END]
---
[1] Url:
https://muse.jhu.edu/article/363156
Published and (C) by Common Dreams
Content appears here under this condition or license: Creative Commons CC BY-NC-ND 3.0..
via Magical.Fish Gopher News Feeds:
gopher://magical.fish/1/feeds/news/commondreams/