After writing these few questions of the treatise on Penance, St. Thomas
was called to the heavenly reward which he had merited by writing so well
of his Divine Master. The remainder of the Summa Theologica, known as the
Supplement, was compiled probably by Fra Rainaldo da Piperno, companion
and friend of the Angelic Doctor, and was gathered from St. Thomas's
commentary on the Fourth Book of the Sentences of Peter Lombard. This
commentary was written in the years 1235-1253, while St. Thomas was under
thirty years of age. Everywhere it reveals the influence of him whom St.
Thomas always called the Master. But that influence was not to be always
supreme. That the mind of the Angelic Doctor moved forward to positions
which directly contradicted the Master may be seen by any student of the
Summa Theologica. The compiler of the Supplement was evidently well
acquainted with the commentary on the Sentences, which had been in
circulation for some twenty years or more, but it is probable that he was
badly acquainted with the Summa Theologica. This will be realized and
must be borne in mind when we read the Supplement, notably TP, Q[62],
A[1]; also Q[43], A[3], ad 2 of the Supplement.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[1] Out. Para. 1/2
SUPPLEMENT (XP): TO THE THIRD PART OF THE SUMMA THEOLOGICA OF ST. THOMAS
AQUINAS GATHERED FROM HIS COMMENTARY ON BOOK IV OF THE SENTENCES (QQ[1]
-99)
OF THE PARTS OF PENANCE, IN PARTICULAR, AND FIRST OF CONTRITION (THREE
ARTICLES)
We must now consider each single part of Penance, and (1) Contrition;
(2) Confession; (3) Satisfaction. The consideration about Contrition will
be fourfold: (1) What is it? (2) What should it be about? (3) How great
should it be? (4) Of its duration; (5) Of its effect.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[1] Out. Para. 2/2
Under the first head there are three points of inquiry:
(1) Whether Contrition is suitably defined?
(2) Whether it is an act of virtue?
(3) Whether attrition can become contrition?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[1] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether contrition is an assumed sorrow for sins, together with the
purpose of confessing them and of making satisfaction for them?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[1] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that contrition is not "an assumed sorrow for sins,
together with the purpose of confessing them and of making satisfaction
for them," as some define it. For, as Augustine states (De Civ. Dei xiv,
6), "sorrow is for those things that happen against our will." But this
does not apply to sin. Therefore contrition is not sorrow for sins.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[1] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, contrition is given us by God. But what is given is not
assumed. Therefore contrition is not an assumed sorrow.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[1] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, satisfaction and confession are necessary for the
remission of the punishment which was not remitted by contrition. But
sometimes the whole punishment is remitted in contrition. Therefore it is
not always necessary for the contrite person to have the purpose of
confessing and of making satisfaction.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[1] A[1] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, stands the definition.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[1] A[1] Body Para. 1/3
I answer that, As stated in Ecclus. 10:15, "pride is the beginning of
all sin," because thereby man clings to his own judgment, and strays from
the Divine commandments. Consequently that which destroys sin must needs
make man give up his own judgment. Now he that persists in his own
judgment, is called metaphorically rigid and hard: wherefore anyone is
said to be broken when he is torn from his own judgment. But, in material
things, whence these expressions are transferred to spiritual things,
there is a difference between breaking and crushing or contrition, as
stated in Meteor. iv, in that we speak of breaking when a thing is
sundered into large parts, but of crushing or contrition when that which
was in itself solid is reduced to minute particles. And since, for the
remission of sin, it is necessary that man should put aside entirely his
attachment to sin, which implies a certain state of continuity and
solidity in his mind, therefore it is that the act through which sin is
cast aside is called contrition metaphorically.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[1] A[1] Body Para. 2/3
In this contrition several things are to be observed, viz. the very
substance of the act, the way of acting, its origin and its effect: in
respect of which we find that contrition has been defined in various
ways. For, as regards the substance of the act, we have the definition
given above: and since the act of contrition is both an act of virtue,
and a part of the sacrament of Penance, its nature as an act of virtue is
explained in this definition by mentioning its genus, viz. "sorrow," its
object by the words "for sins," and the act of choice which is necessary
for an act of virtue, by the word "assumed": while, as a part of the
sacrament, it is made manifest by pointing out its relation to the other
parts, in the words "together with the purpose of confessing and of
making satisfaction."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[1] A[1] Body Para. 3/3
There is another definition which defines contrition, only as an act of
virtue; but at the same time including the difference which confines it
to a special virtue, viz. penance, for it is thus expressed: "Contrition
is voluntary sorrow for sin whereby man punishes in himself that which he
grieves to have done," because the addition of the word "punishes"
defines the definition to a special virtue. Another definition is given
by Isidore (De Sum. Bono ii, 12) as follows: "Contrition is a tearful
sorrow and humility of mind, arising from remembrance of sin and fear of
the Judgment." Here we have an allusion to the derivation of the word,
when it is said that it is "humility of the mind," because just as pride
makes the mind rigid, so is a man humbled, when contrition leads him to
give up his mind. Also the external manner is indicated by the word
"tearful," and the origin of contrition, by the words, "arising from
remembrance of sin," etc. Another definition is taken from the words of
Augustine [*Implicitly on Ps. 46], and indicates the effect of
contrition. It runs thus: "Contrition is the sorrow which takes away
sin." Yet another is gathered from the words of Gregory (Moral. xxxiii,
11) as follows: "Contrition is humility of the soul, crushing sin between
hope and fear." Here the derivation is indicated by saying that
contrition is "humility of the soul"; the effect, by the words, "crushing
sin"; and the origin, by the words, "between hope and fear." Indeed, it
includes not only the principal cause, which is fear, but also its joint
cause, which is hope, without which, fear might lead to despair.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[1] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Although sins, when committed, were voluntary, yet when we
are contrite for them, they are no longer voluntary, so that they occur
against our will; not indeed in respect of the will that we had when we
consented to them, but in respect of that which we have now, so as to
wish they had never been.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[1] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Contrition is from God alone as to the form that quickens
it, but as to the substance of the act, it is from the free-will and from
God, Who operates in all works both of nature and of will.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[1] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Although the entire punishment may be remitted by
contrition, yet confession and satisfaction are still necessary, both
because man cannot be sure that his contrition was sufficient to take
away all, and because confession and satisfaction are a matter of
precept: wherefore he becomes a transgressor, who confesses not and makes
not satisfaction.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[1] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether contrition is an act of virtue?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[1] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that contrition is not an act of virtue. For
passions are not acts of virtue, since "they bring us neither praise nor
blame" (Ethic. ii, 5). But sorrow is a passion. As therefore contrition
is sorrow, it seems that it is not an act of virtue.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[1] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, as contrition is so called from its being a crushing, so
is attrition. Now all agree in saying that attrition is not an act of
virtue. Neither, therefore, is contrition an act of virtue.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[1] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, Nothing but an act of virtue is meritorious. But
contrition is a meritorious act. Therefore it is an act of virtue.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[1] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Contrition as to the literal signification of the word,
does not denote an act of virtue, but a corporeal passion. But the
question in point does not refer to contrition in this sense, but to that
which the word is employed to signify by way of metaphor. For just as the
inflation of one's own will unto wrong-doing implies, in itself, a
generic evil, so the utter undoing and crushing of that same will implies
something generically good, for this is to detest one's own will whereby
sin was committed. Wherefore contrition, which signifies this, implies
rectitude of the will; and so it is the act of that virtue to which it
belongs to detest and destroy past sins, the act, to wit, of penance, as
is evident from what was said above (Sent. iv, D, 14, Q[1], A[1]; TP,
Q[85], AA[2],3).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[1] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Contrition includes a twofold sorrow for sin. One is in the
sensitive part, and is a passion. This does not belong essentially to
contrition as an act of virtue, but is rather its effect. For just as the
virtue of penance inflicts outward punishment on the body, in order to
compensate for the offense done to God through the instrumentality of the
bodily members, so does it inflict on the concupiscible part of the soul
a punishment, viz. the aforesaid sorrow, because the concupiscible also
co-operated in the sinful deeds. Nevertheless this sorrow may belong to
contrition taken as part of the sacrament, since the nature of a
sacrament is such that it consists not only of internal but also of
external acts and sensible things. The other sorrow is in the will, and
is nothing else save displeasure for some evil, for the emotions of the
will are named after the passions, as stated above (Sent. iii, D, 26,
Q[1], A[5]; FS, Q[22], A[3], ad 3). Accordingly, contrition is
essentially a kind of sorrow, and is an act of the virtue of penance.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[1] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Attrition denotes approach to perfect contrition, wherefore
in corporeal matters, things are said to be attrite, when they are worn
away to a certain extent, but not altogether crushed to pieces; while
they are said to be contrite, when all the parts are crushed [tritae]
minutely. Wherefore, in spiritual matters, attrition signifies a certain
but not a perfect displeasure for sins committed, whereas contrition
denotes perfect displeasure.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[1] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether attrition can become contrition?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[1] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that attrition can become contrition. For
contrition differs from attrition, as living from dead. Now dead faith
becomes living. Therefore attrition can become contrition.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[1] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, matter receives perfection when privation is removed.
Now sorrow is to grace, as matter to form, because grace quickens sorrow.
Therefore the sorrow that was previously lifeless, while guilt remained,
receives perfection through being quickened by grace: and so the same
conclusion follows as above.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[1] A[3] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, Things which are caused by principles altogether
diverse cannot be changed, one into the other. Now the principle of
attrition is servile fear, while filial fear is the cause of contrition.
Therefore attrition cannot become contrition.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[1] A[3] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, There are two opinions on this question: for some say
that attrition may become contrition, even as lifeless faith becomes
living faith. But, seemingly, this is impossible; since, although the
habit of lifeless faith becomes living, yet never does an act of lifeless
faith become an act of living faith, because the lifeless act passes away
and remains no more, as soon as charity comes. Now attrition and
contrition do not denote a habit, but an act only: and those habits of
infused virtue which regard the will cannot be lifeless, since they
result from charity, as stated above (Sent. iii, D, 27, Q[2], A[4]; FS,
Q[65], A[4]). Wherefore until grace be infused, there is no habit by
which afterwards the act of contrition may be elicited; so that attrition
can nowise become attrition: and this is the other opinion.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[1] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: There is no comparison between faith and contrition, as
stated above.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[1] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/2
Reply OBJ 2: When the privation is removed from matter, the matter is
quickened if it remains when the perfection comes. But the sorrow which
was lifeless, does not remain when charity comes, wherefore it cannot be
quickened.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[1] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 2/2
It may also be replied that matter does not take its origin from the
form essentially, as an act takes its origin from the habit which
quickens it. Wherefore nothing hinders matter being quickened anew by
some form, whereby it was not quickened previously: whereas this cannot
be said of an act, even as it is impossible for the identically same
thing to arise from a cause wherefrom it did not arise before, since a
thing is brought into being but once.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] Out. Para. 1/1
OF THE OBJECT OF CONTRITION (SIX ARTICLES)
We must now consider the object of contrition. Under this head there are
six points of inquiry:
(1) Whether a man should be contrite on account of his punishment?
(2) Whether, on account of original sin?
(3) Whether, for every actual sin he has committed?
(4) Whether, for actual sins he will commit?
(5) Whether, for the sins of others?
(6) Whether, for each single mortal sin?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether man should be contrite on account of the punishment, and not only
on account of his sin?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that man should be contrite on account of the
punishment, and not only on account of his sin. For Augustine says in De
Poenitentia [*Cf. Hom. 50 inter 1]: "No man desires life everlasting
unless he repent of this mortal life." But the morality of this life is a
punishment. Therefore the penitent should be contrite on account of his
punishments also.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the Master says (Sent. iv, D, 16, cap. i), quoting
Augustine (De vera et falsa Poenitentia [*Work of an unknown author]),
that the penitent should be sorry for having deprived himself of virtue.
But privation of virtue is a punishment. Therefore contrition is sorrow
for punishments also.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[1] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, No one holds to that for which he is sorry. But a
penitent, by the very signification of the word, is one who holds to his
punishment [*"Poenitens," i.e. "poenam tenens"]. Therefore he is not
sorry on account of his punishment, so that contrition which is
penitential sorrow is not on account of punishment.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, As stated above (Q[1], A[1]), contrition implies the
crushing of something hard and whole. Now this wholeness and hardness is
found in the evil of fault, since the will, which is the cause thereof in
the evil-doer, sticks to its own ground*, and refuses to yield to the
precept of the law, wherefore displeasure at a suchlike evil is called
metaphorically "contrition." [*There is a play on the words
here---'integer' (whole) and 'in suis terminis' (to its own ground)]. But
this metaphor cannot be applied to evil of punishment, because
punishment simply denotes a lessening, so that it is possible to have
sorrow for punishment but not contrition.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: According to St. Augustine, penance should be on account of
this mortal life, not by reason of its mortality (unless penance be taken
broadly for every kind of sorrow); but by reason of sins, to which we are
prone on account of the weakness of this life.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Sorrow for the loss of virtue through sin is not
essentially the same as contrition, but is its principle. For just as we
are moved to desire a thing on account of the good we expect to derive
from it, so are we moved to be sorry for something on account of the evil
accruing to us therefrom.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether contrition should be on account of original sin?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that contrition should be on account of original
sin. For we ought to be contrite on account of actual sin; not by reason
of the act, considered as a kind of being, but by reason of its
deformity, since the act, regarded in its substance, is a good, and is
from God. Now original sin has a deformity, even as actual sin has.
Therefore we should be contrite on its account also.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, by original sin man has been turned away from God, since
in punishment thereof he was to be deprived of seeing God. But every man
should be displeased at having been turned away from God. Therefore man
should be displeased at original sin; and so he ought to have contrition
for it.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, The medicine should be proportionate to the disease.
Now we contracted original sin without willing to do so. Therefore it is
not necessary that we should be cleansed from it by an act of the will,
such as contrition is.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Contrition is sorrow, as stated above (Q[1], AA[1],2),
respecting and, so to speak, crushing the hardness of the will.
Consequently it can regard those sins only which result in us through the
hardness of our will. And as original sin was not brought upon us by our
own will, but contracted from the origin of our infected nature, it
follows that, properly speaking, we cannot have contrition on its
account, but only displeasure or sorrow.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/2
Reply OBJ 1: Contrition is for sin, not by reason of the mere substance
of the act, because it does not derive the character of evil therefrom;
nor again, by reason of its deformity alone, because deformity, of
itself, does not include the notion of guilt, and sometimes denotes a
punishment. But contrition ought to be on account of sin, as implying
deformity resulting from an act of the will; and this does not apply to
original sin, so that contrition does not apply to it.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 2/2
The same Reply avails for the Second Objection, because contrition is
due to aversion of the will.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether we should have contrition for every actual sin?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that we have no need to have contrition for every
actual sin we have committed. For contraries are healed by their
contraries. Now some sins are committed through sorrow, e.g. sloth and
envy. Therefore their remedy should not be sorrow, such as contrition is,
but joy.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, contrition is an act of the will, which cannot refer to
that which is not known. But there are sins of which we have no
knowledge, such as those we have forgotten. Therefore we cannot have
contrition for them.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, by voluntary contrition those sins are blotted out which
we committed voluntarily. But ignorance takes away voluntariness, as the
Philosopher declares (Ethic. iii, 1). Therefore contrition need not cover
things which have occurred through ignorance.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[3] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, we need not be contrite for a sin which is not removed
by contrition. Now some sins are not removed by contrition, e.g. venial
sins, that remain after the grace of contrition. Therefore there is no
need to have contrition for all one's past sins.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[3] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, Penance is a remedy for all actual sins. But penance
cannot regard some sins, without contrition regarding them also, for it
is the first part of Penance. Therefore contrition should be for all
one's past sins.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[3] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, no sin is forgiven a man unless he be justified. But
justification requires contrition, as stated above (Q[1], A[1]; FS,
Q[113]). Therefore it is necessary to have contrition for all one's sins.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[3] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Every actual sin is caused by our will not yielding to
God's law, either by transgressing it, or by omitting it, or by acting
beside it: and since a hard thing is one that is disposed not to give way
easily, hence it is that a certain hardness of the will is to be found in
every actual sin. Wherefore, if a sin is to be remedied, it needs to be
taken away by contrition which crushes it.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: As clearly shown above (A[2], ad 1), contrition is opposed
to sin, in so far as it proceeds from the choice of the will that had
failed to obey the command of God's law, and not as regards the material
part of sin: and it is on this that the choice of the will falls. Now the
will's choice falls not only on the acts of the other powers, which the
will uses for its own end, but also on the will's own proper act: for
the will wills to will something. Accordingly the will's choice falls on
that pain or sadness which is to be found in the sin of envy and the
like, whether such pain be in the senses or in the will itself.
Consequently the sorrow of contrition is opposed to those sins.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: One may forget a thing in two ways, either so that it
escapes the memory altogether, and then one cannot search for it; or so
that it escapes from the memory in part, and in part remains, as when I
remember having heard something in general, but know not what it was in
particular, and then I search my memory in order to discover it.
Accordingly a sin also may be forgotten in two ways, either so as to
remain in a general, but not in a particular remembrance, and then a man
is bound to bethink himself in order to discover the sin, because he is
bound to have contrition for each individual mortal sin. And if he is
unable to discover it, after applying himself with due care, it is enough
that he be contrite for it, according as it stands in his knowledge, and
indeed he should grieve not only for the sin, but also for having
forgotten it, because this is owing to his neglect. If, however, the sin
has escaped from his memory altogether, then he is excused from his duty
through being unable to fulfill it, and it is enough that he be contrite
in general for everything wherein he has offended God. But when this
inability is removed, as when the sin is recalled to his memory, then he
is bound to have contrition for that sin in particular, even as a poor
man, who cannot pay a debt, is excused, and yet is bound to, as soon as
he can.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: If ignorance were to remove altogether the will to do evil,
it will excuse, and there would be no sin: and sometimes it does not
remove the will altogether, and then it does not altogether excuse, but
only to a certain extent: wherefore a man is bound to be contrite for a
sin committed through ignorance.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[3] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: A venial sin can remain after contrition for a mortal sin,
but not after contrition for the venial sin: wherefore contrition should
also cover venial sins even as penance does, as stated above (Sent. iv,
D, 16, Q[2], A[2], qu. 2; XP, Q[87], A[1]).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether a man is bound to have contrition for his future sins?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that a man is bound to have contrition for his
future sins also. For contrition is an act of the free-will: and the
free-will extends to the future rather than to the past, since choice,
which is an act of the free-will, is about future contingents, as stated
in Ethic. iii. Therefore contrition is about future sins rather than
about past sins.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, sin is aggravated by the result that ensues from it:
wherefore Jerome says [*St. Basil asserts this implicitly in De Vera
Virgin.] that the punishment of Arius is not yet ended, for it is yet
possible for some to be ruined through his heresy, by reason of whose
ruin his punishment would be increased: and the same applies to a man who
is judged guilty of murder, if he has committed a murderous assault, even
before his victim dies. Now the sinner ought to be contrite during that
intervening time. Therefore the degree of his contrition ought to be
proportionate not only to his past act, but also to its eventual result:
and consequently contrition regards the future.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[4] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, Contrition is a part of penance. But penance always
regards the past: and therefore contrition does also, and consequently is
not for a future sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[4] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, In every series of things moving and moved ordained to
one another, we find that the inferior mover has its proper movement, and
besides this, it follows, in some respect, the movement of the superior
mover: this is seen in the movement of the planets, which, in addition to
their proper movements, follow the movement of the first heaven. Now, in
all the moral virtues, the first mover is prudence, which is called the
charioteer of the virtues. Consequently each moral virtue, in addition to
its proper movement, has something of the movement of prudence: and
therefore, since penance is a moral virtue, as it is a part of justice,
in addition to its own act, it acquires the movement of prudence. Now its
proper movement is towards its proper object, which is a sin committed.
Wherefore its proper and principal act, viz. contrition, essentially
regards past sins alone; but, inasmuch as it acquires something of the
act of prudence, it regards future sins indirectly, although it is not
essentially moved towards those future sins. For this reason, he that is
contrite, is sorry for his past sins, and is cautious of future sins. Yet
we do not speak of contrition for future sins, but of caution, which is a
part of prudence conjoined to penance.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The free-will is said to regard future contingents, in so
far as it is concerned with acts, but not with the object of acts:
because, of his own free-will, a man can think about past and necessary
things, and yet the very act of thinking, in so far as it is subject to
the free-will, is a future contingent. Hence the act the contrition also
is a future contingent, in so far as it is subject to the free-will; and
yet its object can be something past.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The consequent result which aggravates a sin was already
present in the act as in its cause; wherefore when the sin was committed,
its degree of gravity was already complete, and no further guilt accrued
to it when the result took place. Nevertheless some accidental punishment
accrues to it, in the respect of which the damned will have the more
motives of regret for the more evils that have resulted from their sins.
It is in this sense that Jerome [*Basil] speaks. Hence there is not need
for contrition to be for other than past sins.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[5] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether a man ought to have contrition for another's sin?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[5] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that a man ought to have contrition for another's
sin. For one should not ask forgiveness for a sin unless one is contrite
for it. Now forgiveness is asked for another's sin in Ps. 18:13: "From
those of others spare thy servant." Therefore a man ought to be contrite
for another's sins.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[5] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, man is bound, ought of charity, to love his neighbor as
himself. Now, through love of himself, he both grieves for his ills, and
desires good things. Therefore, since we are bound to desire the goods of
grace for our neighbor, as for ourselves, it seems that we ought to
grieve for his sins, even as for our own. But contrition is nothing else
than sorrow for sins. Therefore man should be contrite for the sins of
others.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[5] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, Contrition is an act of the virtue of penance. But no
one repents save for what he has done himself. Therefore no one is
contrite for others' sins.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[5] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, The same thing is crushed [conteritur] which hitherto was
hard and whole. Hence contrition for sin must needs be in the same
subject in which the hardness of sin was hitherto: so that there is no
contrition for the sins of others.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[5] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The prophet prays to be spared from the sins of others, in
so far as, through fellowship with sinners, a man contracts a stain by
consenting to their sins: thus it is written (Ps. 17:27): "With the
perverse thou wilt be perverted."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[5] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: We ought to grieve for the sins of others, but not to have
contrition for them, because not all sorrow for past sins is contrition,
as is evident for what has been said already.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[6] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether it is necessary to have contrition for each mortal sin?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[6] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that it is not necessary to have contrition for
each mortal sin. For the movement of contrition in justification is
instantaneous: whereas a man cannot think of every mortal sin in an
instant. Therefore it is not necessary to have contrition for each mortal
sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[6] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, contrition should be for sins, inasmuch as they turn us
away from God, because we need not be contrite for turning to creatures
without turning away from God. Now all mortal sins agree in turning us
away from God. Therefore one contrition for all is sufficient.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[6] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, mortal sins have more in common with one another, than
actual and original sin. Now one Baptism blots out all sins both actual
and original. Therefore one general contrition blots out all mortal sins.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[6] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, For diverse diseases there are diverse remedies, since
"what heals the eye will not heal the foot," as Jerome says (Super Marc.
ix, 28). But contrition is the special remedy for one mortal sin.
Therefore one general contrition for all mortal sins does not suffice.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[6] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, contrition is expressed by confession. But it is necessary to
confess each mortal sin. Therefore it is necessary to have contrition for
each mortal sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[6] Body Para. 1/2
I answer that, Contrition may be considered in two ways, as to its
origin, and as to its term. By origin of contrition I mean the process of
thought, when a man thinks of his sin and is sorry for it, albeit not
with the sorrow of contrition, yet with that of attrition. The term of
contrition is when that sorrow is already quickened by grace.
Accordingly, as regards the origin of contrition, a man needs to be
contrite for each sin that he calls to mind; but as regards its term, it
suffices for him to have one general contrition for all, because then the
movement of his contrition acts in virtue of all his preceding
dispositions.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[6] Body Para. 2/2
This suffices for the Reply to the First Objection.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[6] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Although all mortal sins agree in turning man away from
God, yet they differ in the cause and mode of aversion, and in the degree
of separation from God; and this regards the different ways in which they
turn us to creatures.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[6] R.O. 3 Para. 1/2
Reply OBJ 3: Baptism acts in virtue of Christ's merit, Who had infinite
power for the blotting out of all sins; and so for all sins one Baptism
suffices. But in contrition, in addition to the merit of Christ, an act
of ours is requisite, which must, therefore, correspond to each sin,
since it has not infinite power for contrition.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[2] A[6] R.O. 3 Para. 2/2
It may also be replied that Baptism is a spiritual generation; whereas
Penance, as regards contrition and its other parts, is a kind of
spiritual healing by way of some alteration. Now it is evident in the
generation of a body, accompanied by corruption of another body, that all
the accidents contrary to the thing generated, and which were the
accidents of the thing corrupted, are removed by the one generation:
whereas in alteration, only that accident is removed which was contrary
to the accident which is the term of the alteration. In like manner, one
Baptism blots out all sins together and introduces a new life; whereas
Penance does not blot out each sin, unless it be directed to each. For
this reason it is necessary to be contrite for, and to confess each sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[3] Out. Para. 1/1
OF THE DEGREE OF CONTRITION (THREE ARTICLES)
We must now consider the degree of contrition: under which head there
are three points of inquiry:
(1) Whether contrition is the greatest possible sorrow in the world?
(2) Whether the sorrow of contrition can be too great?
(3) Whether sorrow for one sin ought to be greater than for another?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[3] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether contrition is the greatest possible sorrow in the world?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[3] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that contrition is not the greatest possible sorrow
in the world. For sorrow is the sensation of hurt. But some hurts are
more keenly felt than the hurt of sin, e.g. the hurt of a wound.
Therefore contrition is not the greatest sorrow.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[3] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, we judge of a cause according to its effect. Now the
effect of sorrow is tears. Since therefore sometimes a contrite person
does not shed outward tears for his sins, whereas he weeps for the death
of a friend, or for a blow, or the like, it seems that contrition is not
the greatest sorrow.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[3] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, the more a thing is mingled with its contrary, the less
its intensity. But the sorrow of contrition has a considerable admixture
of joy, because the contrite man rejoices in his delivery, in the hope of
pardon, and in many like things. Therefore his sorrow is very slight.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[3] A[1] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, the sorrow of contrition is a kind of displeasure. But
there are many things more displeasing to the contrite than their past
sins; for they would not prefer to suffer the pains of hell rather than
to sin. nor to have suffered, nor yet to suffer all manner of temporal
punishment; else few would be found contrite. Therefore the sorrow of
contrition is not the greatest.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[3] A[1] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, According to Augustine (De Civ. Dei xiv, 7, 9), "all
sorrow is based on love." Now the love of charity, on which the sorrow of
contrition is based, is the greatest love. Therefore the sorrow of
contrition is the greatest sorrow.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[3] A[1] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, sorrow is for evil. Therefore the greater the evil, the greater
the sorrow. But the fault is a greater evil than its punishment.
Therefore contrition which is sorrow for fault, surpasses all other
sorrow.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[3] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, As stated above (Q[1], A[2], ad 1), there is a twofold
sorrow in contrition: one is in the will, and is the very essence of
contrition, being nothing else than displeasure at past sin, and this
sorrow, in contrition, surpasses all other sorrows. For the more pleasing
a thing is, the more displeasing is its contrary. Now the last end is
above all things pleasing: wherefore sin, which turns us away from the
last end, should be, above all things, displeasing. The other sorrow is
in the sensitive part, and is caused by the former sorrow either from
natural necessity, in so far as the lower powers follow the movements of
the higher, or from choice, in so far as a penitent excites in himself
this sorrow for his sins. In neither of these ways is such sorrow, of
necessity, the greatest, because the lower powers are more deeply moved
by their own objects than through redundance from the higher powers.
Wherefore the nearer the operation of the higher powers approaches to the
objects of the lower powers, the more do the latter follow the movement
of the former. Consequently there is greater pain in the sensitive part,
on account of a sensible hurt, than that which redounds into the
sensitive part from the reason; and likewise, that which redounds from
the reason when it deliberates on corporeal things, is greater than that
which redounds from the reason in considering spiritual things. Therefore
the sorrow which results in the sensitive part from the reason's
displeasure at sin, is not greater than the other sorrows of which that
same part is the subject: and likewise, neither is the sorrow which is
assumed voluntarily greater than other sorrows---both because the lower
appetite does not obey the higher appetite infallibly, as though in the
lower appetite there should arise a passion of such intensity and of such
a kind as the higher appetite might ordain---and because the passions are
employed by the reason, in acts of virtue, according to a certain
measure, which the sorrow that is without virtue sometimes does not
observe, but exceeds.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[3] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Just as sensible sorrow is on account of the sensation of
hurt, so interior sorrow is on account of the thought of something
hurtful. Therefore, although the hurt of sin is not perceived by the
external sense, yet it is perceived to be the most grievous hurt by the
interior sense or reason.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[3] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Affections of the body are the immediate result of the
sensitive passions and, through them, of the emotions of the higher
appetite. Hence it is that bodily tears flow more quickly from sensible
sorrow, or even from a thing that hurts the senses, than from the
spiritual sorrow of contrition.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[3] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: The joy which a penitent has for his sorrow does not lessen
his displeasure (for it is not contrary to it), but increases it,
according as every operation is increased by the delight which it causes,
as stated in Ethic. x, 5. Thus he who delights in learning a science,
learns the better, and, in like manner, he who rejoices in his
displeasure, is the more intensely displeased. But it may well happen
that this joy tempers the sorrow that results from the reason in the
sensitive part.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[3] A[1] R.O. 4 Para. 1/4
Reply OBJ 4: The degree of displeasure at a thing should be
proportionate to the degree of its malice. Now the malice of mortal sin
is measured from Him against Whom it is committed, inasmuch as it is
offensive to Him; and from him who sins, inasmuch as it is hurtful to
him. And, since man should love God more than himself, therefore he
should hate sin, as an offense against God, more than as being hurtful to
himself. Now it is hurtful to him chiefly because it separates him from
God; and in this respect the separation from God which is a punishment,
should be more displeasing than the sin itself, as causing this hurt
(since what is hated on account of something else, is less hated), but
less than the sin, as an offense against God. Again, among all the
punishments of malice a certain order is observed according to the
degree of the hurt. Consequently, since this is the greatest hurt,
inasmuch as it consists in privation of the greatest good, the greatest
of all punishments will be separation from God.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[3] A[1] R.O. 4 Para. 2/4
Again, with regard to this displeasure, it is necessary to observe that
there is also an accidental degree of malice, in respect of the present
and the past; since what is past, is no more, whence it has less of the
character of malice or goodness. Hence it is that a man shrinks from
suffering an evil at the present, or at some future time, more than he
shudders at the past evil: wherefore also, no passion of the soul
corresponds directly to the past, as sorrow corresponds to present evil,
and fear to future evil. Consequently, of two past evils, the mind
shrinks the more from that one which still produces a greater effect at
the present time, or which, it fears, will produce a greater effect in
the future, although in the past it was the lesser evil. And, since the
effect of the past sin is sometimes not so keenly felt as the effect of
the past punishment, both because sin is more perfectly remedied than
punishment, and because bodily defect is more manifest than spiritual
defect, therefore even a man, who is well disposed, sometimes feels a
greater abhorrence of his past punishment than of his past sin, although
he would be ready to suffer the same punishment over again rather than
commit the same sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[3] A[1] R.O. 4 Para. 3/4
We must also observe, in comparing sin with punishment, that some
punishments are inseparable from offense of God, e.g. separation from
God; and some also are everlasting, e.g. the punishment of hell.
Therefore the punishment to which is connected offense of God is to be
shunned in the same way as sin; whereas that which is everlasting is
simply to be shunned more than sin. If, however, we separate from these
punishments the notion of offense, and consider only the notion of
punishment, they have the character of malice, less than sin has as an
offense against God: and for this reason should cause less displeasure.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[3] A[1] R.O. 4 Para. 4/4
We must, however, take note that, although the contrite should be thus
disposed, yet he should not be questioned about his feelings, because man
cannot easily measure them. Sometimes that which displeases least seems
to displease most, through being more closely connected with some
sensible hurt, which is more known to us.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[3] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the sorrow of contrition can be too great?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[3] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the sorrow of contrition cannot be too great.
For no sorrow can be more immoderate than that which destroys its own
subject. But the sorrow of contrition, if it be so great as to cause
death or corruption of the body, is praiseworthy. For Anselm says (Orat.
lii): "Would that such were the exuberance of my inmost soul, as to dry
up the marrow of my body"; and Augustine [*De Contritione Cordis, work of
an unknown author] confesses that "he deserves to blind his eyes with
tears." Therefore the sorrow of contrition cannot be too great.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[3] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the sorrow of contrition results from the love of
charity. But the love of charity cannot be too great. Neither, therefore,
can the sorrow of contrition be too great.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[3] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: On the contrary, Every moral virtue is destroyed by excess and
deficiency. But contrition is an act of a moral virtue, viz. penance,
since it is a part of justice. Therefore sorrow for sins can be too great.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[3] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Contrition, as regards the sorrow in the reason, i.e. the
displeasure, whereby the sin is displeasing through being an offense
against God, cannot be too great; even as neither can the love of charity
be too great, for when this is increased the aforesaid displeasure is
increased also. But, as regards the sensible sorrow, contrition may be
too great, even as outward affliction of the body may be too great. In
all these things the rule should be the safeguarding of the subject, and
of that general well-being which suffices for the fulfillment of one's
duties; hence it is written (Rm. 12:1): "Let your sacrifice be reasonable
[*Vulg.: 'Present your bodies . . . a reasonable sacrifice']."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[3] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Anselm desired the marrow of his body to be dried up by the
exuberance of his devotion, not as regards the natural humor, but as to
his bodily desires and concupiscences. And, although Augustine
acknowledged that he deserved to lose the use of his bodily eyes on
account of his sins, because every sinner deserves not only eternal, but
also temporal death, yet he did not wish his eyes to be blinded.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[3] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: This objection considers the sorrow which is in the reason:
while the Third considers the sorrow of the sensitive part.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[3] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether sorrow for one sin should be greater than for another?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[3] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that sorrow for one sin need not be greater than
for another. For Jerome (Ep. cviii) commends Paula for that "she deplored
her slightest sins as much as great ones." Therefore one need not be more
sorry for one sin than for another.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[3] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the movement of contrition is instantaneous. Now one
instantaneous movement cannot be at the same time more intense and more
remiss. Therefore contrition for one sin need not be greater than for
another.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[3] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, contrition is for sin chiefly as turning us away from
God. But all mortal sins agree in turning us away from God, since they
all deprive us of grace whereby the soul is united to God. Therefore we
should have equal contrition for all mortal sins.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[3] A[3] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, It is written (Dt. 25:2): "According to the measure of
the sin, shall the measure also of the stripes be." Now, in contrition,
the stripes are measured according to the sins, because to contrition is
united the purpose of making satisfaction. Therefore contrition should be
for one sin more than for another.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[3] A[3] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, man should be contrite for that which he ought to have avoided.
But he ought to avoid one sin more than another, if that sin is more
grievous, and it be necessary to do one or the other. Therefore, in like
manner, he ought to be more sorry for one, viz. the more grievous, than
for the other.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[3] A[3] Body Para. 1/2
I answer that, We may speak of contrition in two ways: first, in so far
as it corresponds to each single sin, and thus, as regards the sorrow in
the higher appetite, a man ought to be more sorry for a more grievous
sin, because there is more reason for sorrow, viz. the offense against
God, in such a sin than in another, since the more inordinate the act is,
the more it offends God. In like manner, since the greater sin deserves a
greater punishment, the sorrow also of the sensitive part, in so far as
it is voluntarily undergone for sin, as the punishment thereof, ought to
be greater where the sin is greater. But in so far as the emotions of the
lower appetite result from the impression of the higher appetite, the
degree of sorrow depends on the disposition of the lower faculty to the
reception of impressions from the higher faculty, and not on the
greatness of the sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[3] A[3] Body Para. 2/2
Secondly, contrition may be taken in so far as it is directed to all
one's sins together, as in the act of justification. Such contrition
arises either from the consideration of each single sin, and thus
although it is but one act, yet the distinction of the sins remains
virtually therein; or, at least, it includes the purpose of thinking of
each sin; and in this way too it is habitually more for one than for
another.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[3] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Paula is commended, not for deploring all her sins equally,
but because she grieved for her slight sins as much as though they were
grave sins, in comparison with other persons who grieve for their sins:
but for graver sins she would have grieved much more.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[3] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: In that instantaneous movement of contrition, although it
is not possible to find an actually distinct intensity in respect of each
individual sin, yet it is found in the way explained above; and also in
another way, in so far as, in this general contrition, each individual
sin is related to that particular motive of sorrow which occurs to the
contrite person, viz. the offense against God. For he who loves a whole,
loves its parts potentially although not actually, and accordingly he
loves some parts more and some less, in proportion to their relation to
the whole; thus he who loves a community, virtually loves each one more
or less according to their respective relations to the common good. In
like manner he who is sorry for having offended God, implicitly grieves
for his different sins in different ways, according as by them he
offended God more or less.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[3] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Although each mortal sin turns us away from God and
deprives us of His grace, yet some remove us further away than others,
inasmuch as through their inordinateness they become more out of harmony
with the order of the Divine goodness, than others do.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[4] Out. Para. 1/1
OF THE TIME FOR CONTRITION (THREE ARTICLES)
We must now consider the time for contrition: under which head there are
three points of inquiry:
(1) Whether the whole of this life is the time for contrition?
(2) Whether it is expedient to grieve continually for our sins?
(3) Whether souls grieve for their sins even after this life?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[4] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the whole of this life is the time for contrition?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[4] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the time for contrition is not the whole of
this life. For as we should be sorry for a sin committed, so should we be
ashamed of it. But shame for sin does not last all one's life, for
Ambrose says (De Poenit. ii) that "he whose sin is forgiven has nothing
to be ashamed of." Therefore it seems that neither should contrition last
all one's life, since it is sorrow for sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[4] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, it is written (1 Jn. 4:18) that "perfect charity casteth
out fear, because fear hath pain." But sorrow also has pain. Therefore
the sorrow of contrition cannot remain in the state of perfect charity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[4] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, there cannot be any sorrow for the past (since it is,
properly speaking, about a present evil) except in so far as something of
the past sin remains in the present time. Now, in this life, sometimes
one attains to a state in which nothing remains of a past sin, neither
disposition, nor guilt, nor any debt of punishment. Therefore there is no
need to grieve any more for that sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[4] A[1] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, it is written (Rm. 8:28) that "to them that love God all
things work together unto good," even sins as a gloss declares
[*Augustine, De Correp. et Grat.]. Therefore there is no need for them to
grieve for sin after it has been forgiven.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[4] A[1] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, contrition is a part of Penance, condivided with
satisfaction. But there is no need for continual satisfaction. Therefore
contrition for sin need not be continual.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[4] A[1] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, Augustine in De Poenitentia [*De vera et falsa
Poenitentia, work of an unknown author] says that "when sorrow ceases,
penance fails, and when penance fails, no pardon remains." Therefore,
since it behooves one not to lose the forgiveness which has been granted,
it seems that one ought always to grieve for one's sins.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[4] A[1] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, it is written (Ecclus. 5:5): "Be not without fear about sin
forgiven." Therefore man should always grieve, that his sins may be
forgiven him.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[4] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, As stated above (Q[3], A[1]), there is a twofold sorrow
in contrition: one is in the reason, and is detestation of the sin
committed; the other is in the sensitive part, and results from the
former: and as regards both, the time for contrition is the whole of the
present state of life. For as long as one is a wayfarer, one detests the
obstacles which retard or hinder one from reaching the end of the way.
Wherefore, since past sin retards the course of our life towards God
(because the time which was given to us for the course cannot be
recovered), it follows that the state of contrition remains during the
whole of this lifetime, as regards the detestation of sin. The same is to
be said of the sensible sorrow, which is assumed by the will as a
punishment: for since man, by sinning, deserved everlasting punishment,
and sinned against the eternal God, the everlasting punishment being
commuted into a temporal one, sorrow ought to remain during the whole of
man's eternity, i.e. during the whole of the state of this life. For this
reason Hugh of St. Victor says [*Richard of St. Victor, De Pot. Lig. et
Solv. 3,5,13] that "when God absolves a man from eternal guilt and
punishment, He binds him with a chain of eternal detestation of sin."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[4] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Shame regards sin only as a disgraceful act; wherefore
after sin has been taken away as to its guilt, there is no further motive
for shame; but there does remain a motive of sorrow, which is for the
guilt, not only as being something disgraceful, but also as having a hurt
connected with it.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[4] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Servile fear which charity casts out, is opposed to charity
by reason of its servility, because it regards the punishment. But the
sorrow of contrition results from charity, as stated above (Q[3], A[2]):
wherefore the comparison fails.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[4] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Although, by penance, the sinner returns to his former
state of grace and immunity from the debt of punishment, yet he never
returns to his former dignity of innocence, and so something always
remains from his past sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[4] A[1] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: Just as a man ought not to do evil that good may come of
it, so he ought not to rejoice in evil, for the reason that good may
perchance come from it through the agency of Divine grace or providence,
because his sins did not cause but hindered those goods; rather was it
Divine providence that was their cause, and in this man should rejoice,
whereas he should grieve for his sins.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[4] A[1] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: Satisfaction depends on the punishment appointed, which
should be enjoined for sins; hence it can come to an end, so that there
be no further need of satisfaction. But that punishment is proportionate
to sin chiefly on the part of its adherence to a creature whence it
derives its finiteness. On the other hand, the sorrow of contrition
corresponds to sin on the part of the aversion, whence it derives a
certain infinity; wherefore contrition ought to continue always; nor is
it unreasonable if that which precedes remains, when that which follows
is taken away.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[4] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether it is expedient to grieve for sin continually?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[4] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that it is not expedient to grieve for sin
continually. For it is sometimes expedient to rejoice, as is evident from
Phil. 4:4, where the gloss on the words, "Rejoice in the Lord always,"
says that "it is necessary to rejoice." Now it is not possible to rejoice
and grieve at the same time. Therefore it is not expedient to grieve for
sin continually.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[4] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, that which, in itself, is an evil and a thing to be
avoided should not be taken upon oneself, except in so far as it is
necessary as a remedy against something, as in the case of burning or
cutting a wound. Now sorrow is in itself an evil; wherefore it is written
(Ecclus. 30:24): "Drive away sadness far from thee," and the reason is
given (Ecclus. 30:25): "For sadness hath killed many, and there is no
profit in it." Moreover the Philosopher says the same (Ethic. vii, 13,14;
x, 5). Therefore one should not grieve for sin any longer than suffices
for the sin to be blotted out. Now sin is already blotted out after the
first sorrow of contrition. Therefore it is not expedient to grieve any
longer.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[4] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, Bernard says (Serm. xi in Cant.): "Sorrow is a good
thing, if it is not continual; for honey should be mingled with
wormwood." Therefore it seems that it is inexpedient to grieve
continually.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[4] A[2] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, Augustine [*De vera et falsa Poenitentia, work of an
unknown author] says: "The penitent should always grieve, and rejoice in
his grief."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[4] A[2] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, it is expedient always to continue, as far as it is possible,
those acts in which beatitude consists. Now such is sorrow for sin, as is
shown by the words of Mt. 5:5, "Blessed are they that mourn." Therefore
it is expedient for sorrow to be as continual as possible.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[4] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, We find this condition in the acts of the virtues, that
in them excess and defect are not possible, as is proved in Ethic. ii,
6,7. Wherefore, since contrition, so far as it is a kind of displeasure
seated in the rational appetite, is an act of the virtue of penance,
there can never be excess in it, either as to its intensity, or as to its
duration, except in so far as the act of one virtue hinders the act of
another which is more urgent for the time being. Consequently the more
continually a man can perform acts of this displeasure, the better it
is, provided he exercises the acts of other virtues when and how he ought
to. On the other hand, passions can have excess and defect, both in
intensity and in duration. Wherefore, as the passion of sorrow, which the
will takes upon itself, ought to be moderately intense, so ought it to be
of moderate duration, lest, if it should last too long, man fall into
despair, cowardice, and such like vices.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[4] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The sorrow of contrition is a hindrance to worldly joy, but
not to the joy which is about God, and which has sorrow itself for object.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[4] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The words of Ecclesiasticus refer to worldly joy: and the
Philosopher is referring to sorrow as a passion, of which we should make
moderate use, according as the end, for which it is assumed, demands.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[4] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Bernard is speaking of sorrow as a passion.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[4] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether our souls are contrite for sins even after this life?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[4] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that our souls are contrite for sins even after
this life. For the love of charity causes displeasure at sin. Now, after
this life, charity remains in some, both as to its act and as to its
habit, since "charity never falleth away." Therefore the displeasure at
the sin committed, which is the essence of contrition, remains.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[4] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, we should grieve more for sin than for punishment. But
the souls in purgatory grieve for their sensible punishment and for the
delay of glory. Much more, therefore, do they grieve for the sins they
committed.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[4] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, the pain of purgatory satisfies for sin. But
satisfaction derives its efficacy from the power of contrition. Therefore
contrition remains after this life.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[4] A[3] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, contrition is a part of the sacrament of Penance. But
the sacraments do not endure after this life. Neither, therefore, does
contrition.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[4] A[3] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, contrition can be so great as to blot out both guilt and
punishment. If therefore the souls in purgatory could have contrition, it
would be possible for their debt of punishment to be remitted through the
power of their contrition, so that they would be delivered from their
sensible pain, which is false.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[4] A[3] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Three things are to be observed in contrition: first, its
genus, viz. sorrow; secondly, its form, for it is an act of virtue
quickened by charity; thirdly, its efficacy, for it is a meritorious and
sacramental act, and, to a certain extent, satisfactory. Accordingly,
after this life, those souls which dwell in the heavenly country, cannot
have contrition, because they are void of sorrow by reason of the
fulness of their joy: those which are in hell, have no contrition, for
although they have sorrow, they lack the grace which quickens sorrow;
while those which are in purgatory have a sorrow for their sins, that is
quickened by grace; yet it is not meritorious, for they are not in the
state of meriting. In this life, however, all these three can be found.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[4] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Charity does not cause this sorrow, save in those who are
capable of it; but the fulness of joy in the Blessed excludes all
capability of sorrow from them: wherefore, though they have charity, they
have no contrition.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[4] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The souls in purgatory grieve for their sins; but their
sorrow is not contrition, because it lacks the efficacy of contrition.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[4] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: The pain which the souls suffer in purgatory, cannot,
properly speaking, be called satisfaction, because satisfaction demands a
meritorious work; yet, in a broad sense, the payment of the punishment
due may be called satisfaction.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[5] Out. Para. 1/1
OF THE EFFECT OF CONTRITION (THREE ARTICLES)
We must now consider the effect of contrition: under which head there
are three points of inquiry:
(1) Whether the remission of sin is the effect of contrition?
(2) Whether contrition can take away the debt of punishment entirely?
(3) Whether slight contrition suffices to blot out great sins?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[5] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the forgiveness of sin is the effect of contrition?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[5] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the forgiveness of sin is not the effect of
contrition. For God alone forgives sins. But we are somewhat the cause of
contrition, since it is an act of our own. Therefore contrition is not
the cause of forgiveness.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[5] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, contrition is an act of virtue. Now virtue follows the
forgiveness of sin: because virtue and sin are not together in the soul.
Therefore contrition is not the cause of the forgiveness of sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[5] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, nothing but sin is an obstacle to receiving the
Eucharist. But the contrite should not go to Communion before going to
confession. Therefore they have not yet received the forgiveness of their
sins.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[5] A[1] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, a gloss on Ps. 50:19, "A sacrifice to God is an
afflicted spirit," says: "A hearty contrition is the sacrifice by which
sins are loosed."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[5] A[1] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, virtue and vice are engendered and corrupted by the same
causes, as stated in Ethic. ii, 1,2. Now sin is committed through the
heart's inordinate love. Therefore it is destroyed by sorrow caused by
the heart's ordinate love; and consequently contrition blots out sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[5] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Contrition can be considered in two ways, either as part
of a sacrament, or as an act of virtue, and in either case it is the
cause of the forgiveness of sin, but not in the same way. Because, as
part of a sacrament, it operates primarily as an instrument for the
forgiveness of sin, as is evident with regard to the other sacraments
(cf. Sent. iv, D, 1, Q[1], A[4]: TP, Q[62], A[1]); while, as an act of
virtue, it is the quasi-material cause of sin's forgiveness. For a
disposition is, as it were, a necessary condition for justification, and
a disposition is reduced to a material cause, if it be taken to denote
that which disposes matter to receive something. It is otherwise in the
case of an agent's disposition to act, because this is reduced to the
genus of efficient cause.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[5] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: God alone is the principal efficient cause of the
forgiveness of sin: but the dispositive cause can be from us also, and
likewise the sacramental cause, since the sacramental forms are words
uttered by us, having an instrumental power of conferring grace whereby
sins are forgiven.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[5] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The forgiveness of sin precedes virtue and the infusion of
grace, in one way, and, in another, follows: and in so far as it follows,
the act elicited by the virtue can be a cause of the forgiveness of sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[5] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: The dispensation of the Eucharist belongs to the ministers
of the Church: wherefore a man should not go to Communion until his sin
has been forgiven through the ministers of the Church, although his sin
may be forgiven him before God.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[5] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether contrition can take away the debt of punishment entirely?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[5] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that contrition cannot take away the debt of
punishment entirely. For satisfaction and confession are ordained for
man's deliverance from the debt of punishment. Now no man is so perfectly
contrite as not to be bound to confession and satisfaction. Therefore
contrition is never so great as to blot out the entire debt of punishment.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[5] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, in Penance the punishment should in some way compensate
for the sin. Now some sins are accomplished by members of the body.
Therefore, since it is for the due compensation for sin that "by what
things a man sinneth, by the same also he is tormented" (Wis. 11:17), it
seems that the punishment for suchlike sins can never be remitted by
contrition.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[5] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, the sorrow of contrition is finite. Now an infinite
punishment is due for some, viz. mortal, sins. Therefore contrition can
never be so great as to remit the whole punishment.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[5] A[2] OTC Para. 1/3
On the contrary, The affections of the heart are more acceptable to God
than external acts. Now man is absolved from both punishment and guilt by
means of external actions; and therefore he is also by means of the
heart's affections, such as contrition is.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[5] A[2] OTC Para. 2/3
Further, we have an example of this in the thief, to whom it was said
(Lk. 23:43): "This day shalt thou be with Me in paradise," on account of
his one act of repentance.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[5] A[2] OTC Para. 3/3
As to whether the whole debt of punishment is always taken away by
contrition, this question has already been considered above (Sent. iv, D,
14, Q[2], AA[1],2; TP, Q[86], A[4]), where the same question was raised
with regard to Penance.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[5] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, The intensity of contrition may be regarded in two ways.
First, on the part of charity, which causes the displeasure, and in this
way it may happen that the act of charity is so intense that the
contrition resulting therefrom merits not only the removal of guilt, but
also the remission of all punishment. Secondly, on the part of the
sensible sorrow, which the will excites in contrition: and since this
sorrow is also a kind of punishment, it may be so intense as to suffice
for the remission of both guilt and punishment.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[5] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: A man cannot be sure that his contrition suffices for the
remission of both punishment and guilt: wherefore he is bound to confess
and to make satisfaction, especially since his contrition would not be
true contrition, unless he had the purpose of confessing united thereto:
which purpose must also be carried into effect, on account of the precept
given concerning confession.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[5] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Just as inward joy redounds into the outward parts of the
body, so does interior sorrow show itself in the exterior members:
wherefore it is written (Prov. 17:22): "A sorrowful spirit drieth up the
bones."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[5] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Although the sorrow of contrition is finite in its
intensity, even as the punishment due for mortal sin is finite; yet it
derives infinite power from charity, whereby it is quickened, and so it
avails for the remission of both guilt and punishment.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[5] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether slight contrition suffices to blot out great sins?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[5] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that slight contrition does not suffice to blot out
great sins. For contrition is the remedy for sin. Now a bodily remedy,
that heals a lesser bodily infirmity, does not suffice to heal a greater.
Therefore the least contrition does not suffice to blot out very great
sins.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[5] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, it was stated above (Q[3], A[3]) that for greater sins
one ought to have greater contrition. Now contrition does not blot out
sin, unless it fulfills the requisite conditions. Therefore the least
contrition does not blot out all sins.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[5] A[3] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, Every sanctifying grace blots out every mortal sin,
because it is incompatible therewith. Now every contrition is quickened
by sanctifying grace. Therefore, however slight it be, it blots out all
sins.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[5] A[3] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, As we have often said (Q[1], A[2], ad 1; Q[3], A[1]; Q[4]
, A[1]), contrition includes a twofold sorrow. One is in the reason, and
is displeasure at the sin committed. This can be so slight as not to
suffice for real contrition, e.g. if a sin were less displeasing to a
man, than separation from his last end ought to be; just as love can be
so slack as not to suffice for real charity. The other sorrow is in the
senses, and the slightness of this is no hindrance to real contrition,
because it does not, of itself, belong essentially to contrition, but is
connected with it accidentally: nor again is it under our control.
Accordingly we must say that sorrow, however slight it be, provided it
suffice for true contrition, blots out all sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[5] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Spiritual remedies derive infinite efficacy from the
infinite power which operates in them: wherefore the remedy which
suffices for healing a slight sin, suffices also to heal a great sin.
This is seen in Baptism which looses great and small: and the same
applies to contrition provided it fulfill the necessary conditions.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[5] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: It follows of necessity that a man grieves more for a
greater sin than for a lesser, according as it is more repugnant to the
love which causes his sorrow. But if one has the same degree of sorrow
for a greater sin, as another has for a lesser, this would suffice for
the remission of the sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] Out. Para. 1/2
OF CONFESSION, AS REGARDS ITS NECESSITY (SIX ARTICLES)
We must now consider confession, about which there are six points for
our consideration: (1) The necessity of confession; (2) Its nature; (3)
Its minister; (4) Its quality; (5) Its effect; (6) The seal of confession.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] Out. Para. 2/2
Under the first head there are six points of inquiry:
(1) Whether confession is necessary for salvation?
(2) Whether confession is according to the natural law?
(3) Whether all are bound to confession?
(4) Whether it is lawful to confess a sin of which one is not guilty?
(5) Whether one is bound to confess at once?
(6) Whether one can be dispensed from confessing to another man?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether confession is necessary for salvation?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that confession is not necessary for salvation. For
the sacrament of Penance is ordained for the sake of the remission of
sin. But sin is sufficiently remitted by the infusion of grace. Therefore
confession is not necessary in order to do penance for one's sins.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, we read of some being forgiven their sins without
confession, e.g. Peter, Magdalen and Paul. But the grace that remits sins
is not less efficacious now than it was then. Therefore neither is it
necessary for salvation now that man should confess.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, a sin which is contracted from another, should receive
its remedy from another. Therefore actual sin, which a man has committed
through his own act, must take its remedy from the man himself. Now
Penance is ordained against such sins. Therefore confession is not
necessary for salvation.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[1] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, confession is necessary for a judicial sentence, in
order that punishment may be inflicted in proportion to the offense. Now
a man is able to inflict on himself a greater punishment than even that
which might be inflicted on him by another. Therefore it seems that
confession is not necessary for salvation.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[1] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, Boethius says (De Consol. i): "If you want the
physician to be of assistance to you, you must make your disease known to
him." But it is necessary for salvation that man should take medicine for
his sins. Therefore it is necessary for salvation that man should make
his disease known by means of confession.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[1] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, in a civil court the judge is distinct from the accused.
Therefore the sinner who is the accused ought not to be his own judge,
but should be judged by another and consequently ought to confess to him.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Christ's Passion, without whose power, neither original
nor actual sin is remitted, produces its effect in us through the
reception of the sacraments which derive their efficacy from it.
Wherefore for the remission of both actual and original sin, a sacrament
of the Church is necessary, received either actually, or at least in
desire, when a man fails to receive the sacrament actually, through an
unavoidable obstacle, and not through contempt. Consequently those
sacraments which are ordained as remedies for sin which is incompatible
with salvation, are necessary for salvation: and so just as Baptism,
whereby original sin is blotted out, is necessary for salvation, so also
is the sacrament of Penance. And just as a man through asking to be
baptized, submits to the ministers of the Church, to whom the
dispensation of that sacrament belongs, even so, by confessing his sin, a
man submits to a minister of the Church, that, through the sacrament of
Penance dispensed by him, he may receive the pardon of his sins: nor can
the minister apply a fitting remedy, unless he be acquainted with the
sin, which knowledge he acquires through the penitent's confession.
Wherefore confession is necessary for the salvation of a man who has
fallen into a mortal actual sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The infusion of grace suffices for the remission of sin;
but after the sin has been forgiven, the sinner still owes a debt of
temporal punishment. Moreover, the sacraments of grace are ordained in
order that man may receive the infusion of grace, and before he receives
them, either actually or in his intention, he does not receive grace.
This is evident in the case of Baptism, and applies to Penance likewise.
Again, the penitent expiates his temporal punishment by undergoing the
shame of confession, by the power of the keys to which he submits, and by
the enjoined satisfaction which the priest moderates according to the
kind of sins made known to him in confession. Nevertheless the fact that
confession is necessary for salvation is not due to its conducing to the
satisfaction for sins, because this punishment to which one remains bound
after the remission of sin, is temporal, wherefore the way of salvation
remains open, without such punishment being expiated in this life: but it
is due to its conducing to the remission of sin, as explained above.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Although we do not read that they confessed, it may be that
they did; for many things were done which were not recorded in writing.
Moreover Christ has the power of excellence in the sacraments; so that He
could bestow the reality of the sacrament without using the things which
belong to the sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: The sin that is contracted from another, viz. original sin,
can be remedied by an entirely extrinsic cause, as in the case of
infants: whereas actual sin, which a man commits of himself, cannot be
expiated, without some operation on the part of the sinner. Nevertheless
man is not sufficient to expiate his sin by himself, though he was
sufficient to sin by himself, because sin is finite on the part of the
thing to which it turns, in which respect the sinner returns to self;
while, on the part of the aversion, sin derives infinity, in which
respect the remission of sin must needs begin from someone else, because
"that which is last in order of generation is first in the order of
intention" (Ethic. iii). Consequently actual sin also must needs take its
remedy from another.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[1] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: Satisfaction would not suffice for the expiation of sin's
punishment, by reason of the severity of the punishment which is enjoined
in satisfaction, but it does suffice as being a part of the sacrament
having the sacramental power; wherefore it ought to be imposed by the
dispensers of the sacraments, and consequently confession is necessary.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether confession is according to the natural law?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that confession is according to the natural law.
For Adam and Cain were bound to none but the precepts of the natural
law, and yet they are reproached for not confessing their sin. Therefore
confession of sin is according to the natural law.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, those precepts which are common to the Old and New Law
are according to the natural law. But confession was prescribed in the
Old Law, as may be gathered from Is. 43:26: "Tell, if thou hast anything
to justify thyself." Therefore it is according to the natural law.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, Job was subject only to the natural law. But he
confessed his sins, as appears from his words (Job 31:33) "If, as a man,
I have hid my sin." Therefore confession is according to the natural law.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, Isidore says (Etym. v.) that the natural law is the
same in all. But confession is not in all in the same way. Therefore it
is not according to the natural law. Further, confession is made to one
who has the keys. But the keys of the Church are not an institution of
the natural law; neither, therefore, is confession.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, The sacraments are professions of faith, wherefore they
ought to be proportionate to faith. Now faith surpasses the knowledge of
natural reason, whose dictate is therefore surpassed by the sacraments.
And since "the natural law is not begotten of opinion, but a product of a
certain innate power," as Tully states (De Inv. Rhet. ii), consequently
the sacraments are not part of the natural law, but of the Divine law
which is above nature. This latter, however, is sometimes called natural,
in so far as whatever a thing derives from its Creator is natural to it,
although, properly speaking, those things are said to be natural which
are caused by the principles of nature. But such things are above nature
as God reserves to Himself; and these are wrought either through the
agency of nature, or in the working of miracles, or in the revelation of
mysteries, or in the institution of the sacraments. Hence confession,
which is of sacramental necessity, is according to Divine, but not
according to natural law.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Adam is reproached for not confessing his sin before God:
because the confession which is made to God by the acknowledgment of
one's sin, is according to the natural law. whereas here we are speaking
of confession made to a man. We may also reply that in such a case
confession of one's sin is according to the natural law, namely when one
is called upon by the judge to confess in a court of law, for then the
sinner should not lie by excusing or denying his sin, as Adam and Cain
are blamed for doing. But confession made voluntarily to a man in order
to receive from God the forgiveness of one's sins, is not according to
the natural law.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The precepts of the natural law avail in the same way in
the law of Moses and in the New Law. But although there was a kind of
confession in the law of Moses, yet it was not after the same manner as
in the New Law, nor as in the law of nature; for in the law of nature it
was sufficient to acknowledge one's sin inwardly before God; while in the
law of Moses it was necessary for a man to declare his sin by some
external sign, as by making a sin-offering, whereby the fact of his
having sinned became known to another man; but it was not necessary for
him to make known what particular sin he had committed, or what were its
circumstances, as in the New Law.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Job is speaking of the man who hides his sin by denying it
or excusing himself when he is accused thereof, as we may gather from a
gloss [*Cf. Gregory, Moral. xxii, 9] on the passage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether all are bound to confession?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that not all are bound to confession, for Jerome
says on Is. 3:9 ("They have proclaimed abroad"), "their sin," etc.:
"Penance is the second plank after shipwreck." But some have not suffered
shipwreck after Baptism. Therefore Penance is not befitting them, and
consequently neither is confession which is a part of Penance.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, it is to the judge that confession should be made in any
court. But some have no judge over them. Therefore they are not bound to
confession.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, some have none but venial sins. Now a man is not bound
to confess such sins. Therefore not everyone is bound to confession.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[3] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, Confession is condivided with satisfaction and
contrition. Now all are bound to contrition and satisfaction. Therefore
all are bound to confession also.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[3] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, this appears from the Decretals (De Poenit. et Remiss. xii),
where it is stated that "all of either sex are bound to confess their
sins as soon as they shall come to the age of discretion."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[3] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, We are bound to confession on two counts: first, by the
Divine law, from the very fact that confession is a remedy, and in this
way not all are bound to confession, but those only who fall into mortal
sin after Baptism; secondly, by a precept of positive law, and in this
way all are bound by the precept of the Church laid down in the general
council (Lateran iv, Can. 21) under Innocent III, both in order that
everyone may acknowledge himself to be a sinner, because "all have sinned
and need the grace of God" (Rm. 3:23); and that the Eucharist may be
approached with greater reverence; and lastly, that parish priests may
know their flock, lest a wolf may hide therein.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Although it is possible for a man, in this mortal life, to
avoid shipwreck, i.e. mortal sin, after Baptism, yet he cannot avoid
venial sins, which dispose him to shipwreck, and against which also
Penance is ordained; wherefore there is still room for Penance, and
consequently for confession, even in those who do not commit mortal sins.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: All must acknowledge Christ as their judge, to Whom they
must confess in the person of His vicar; and although the latter may be
the inferior if the penitent be a prelate, yet he is the superior, in so
far as the penitent is a sinner, while the confessor is the minister of
Christ.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: A man is bound to confess his venial sins, not in virtue of
the sacrament, but by the institution of the Church, and that, when he
has no other sins to confess. We may also, with others, answer that the
Decretal quoted above does not bind others than those who have mortal
sins to confess. This is evident from the fact that it orders all sins to
be confessed, which cannot apply to venial sins, because no one can
confess all his venial sins. Accordingly, a man who has no mortal sins to
confess, is not bound to confess his venial sins, but it suffices for the
fulfillment of the commandment of the Church that he present himself
before the priest, and declare himself to be unconscious of any mortal
sin: and this will count for his confession.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether it is lawful for a man to confess a sin which he has not
committed?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that it is lawful for a man to confess a sin which
he has not committed. For, as Gregory says (Regist. xii), "it is the mark
of a good conscience to acknowledge a fault where there is none."
Therefore it is the mark of a good conscience to accuse oneself of those
sins which one has not committed.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, by humility a man deems himself worse than another, who
is known to be a sinner, and in this he is to be praised. But it is
lawful for a man to confess himself to be what he thinks he is. Therefore
it is lawful to confess having committed a more grievous sin than one has.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[4] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, sometimes one doubts about a sin, whether it be mortal
or venial, in which case, seemingly, one ought to confess it as mortal.
Therefore a person must sometimes confess a sin which he has not
committed.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[4] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, satisfaction originates from confession. But a man can
do satisfaction for a sin which he has not committed. Therefore he can
also confess a sin which he has not done.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[4] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, Whosoever says he has done what he did not, tells an
untruth. But no one ought to tell an untruth in confession, since every
untruth is a sin. Therefore no one should confess a sin which he has not
committed.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[4] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, in the public court of justice, no one should be accused of a
crime which cannot be proved by means of proper witnesses. Now the
witness, in the tribunal of Penance, is the conscience. Therefore a man
ought not to accuse himself of a sin which is not on his conscience.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[4] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, The penitent should, by his confession, make his state
known to his confessor. Now he who tells the priest something other than
what he has on his conscience, whether it be good or evil, does not make
his state known to the priest, but hides it; wherefore his confession is
unavailing: and in order for it to be effective his words must agree with
his thoughts, so that his words accuse him only of what is on his
conscience.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/2
Reply OBJ 1: To acknowledge a fault where there is none, may be
understood in two ways: first, as referring to the substance of the act,
and then it is untrue; for it is a mark, not of a good, but of an
erroneous conscience, to acknowledge having done what one has not done.
Secondly, as referring to the circumstances of the act, and thus the
saying of Gregory is true, because a just man fears lest, in any act
which is good in itself, there should be any defect on his part. thus it
is written (Job 9:28): "I feared all my works." Wherefore it is also the
mark of a good conscience that a man should accuse himself in words of
this fear which he holds in his thoughts.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 2/2
From this may be gathered the Reply to the Second Objection, since a
just man, who is truly humble, deems himself worse not as though he had
committed an act generically worse, but because he fears lest in those
things which he seems to do well, he may by pride sin more grievously.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[4] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: When a man doubts whether a certain sin be mortal, he is
bound to confess it, so long as he remains in doubt, because he sins
mortally by committing or omitting anything, while doubting of its being
a mortal sin, and thus leaving the matter to chance; and, moreover, he
courts danger, if he neglect to confess that which he doubts may be a
mortal sin. He should not, however, affirm that it was a mortal sin, but
speak doubtfully, leaving the verdict to the priest, whose business it is
to discern between what is leprosy and what is not.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[4] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: A man does not commit a falsehood by making satisfaction
for a sin which he did not commit, as when anyone confesses a sin which
he thinks he has not committed. And if he mentions a sin that he has not
committed, believing that he has, he does not lie; wherefore he does not
sin, provided his confession thereof tally with his conscience.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[5] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether one is bound to confess at once?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[5] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that one is bound to confess at once. For Hugh of
St. Victor says (De Sacram. ii): "The contempt of confession is
inexcusable, unless there be an urgent reason for delay." But everyone is
bound to avoid contempt. Therefore everyone is bound to confess as soon
as possible.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[5] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, everyone is bound to do more to avoid spiritual disease
than to avoid bodily disease. Now if a man who is sick in body were to
delay sending for the physician, it would be detrimental to his health.
Therefore it seems that it must needs be detrimental to a man's health if
he omits to confess immediately to a priest if there be one at hand.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[5] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, that which is due always, is due at once. But man owes
confession to God always. Therefore he is bound to confess at once.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[5] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, A fixed time both for confession and for receiving the
Eucharist is determined by the Decretals (Cap. Omnis utriusque sexus: De
Poenit. et Remiss.). Now a man does not sin by failing to receive the
Eucharist before the fixed time. Therefore he does not sin if he does not
confess before that time.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[5] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, it is a mortal sin to omit doing what a commandment bids us to
do. If therefore a man is bound to confess at once, and omits to do so,
with a priest at hand, he would commit a mortal sin; and in like manner
at any other time, and so on, so that he would fall into many mortal sins
for the delay in confessing one, which seems unreasonable.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[5] Body Para. 1/5
I answer that, As the purpose of confessing is united to contrition, a
man is bound to have this purpose when he is bound to have contrition,
viz. when he calls his sins to mind, and chiefly when he is in danger of
death, or when he is so circumstanced that unless his sin be forgiven, he
must fall into another sin: for instance, if a priest be bound to say
Mass, and a confessor is at hand, he is bound to confess or, if there be
no confessor, he is bound at least to contrition and to have the purpose
of confessing.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[5] Body Para. 2/5
But to actual confession a man is bound in two ways. First,
accidentally, viz. when he is bound to do something which he cannot do
without committing a mortal sin, unless he go to confession first: for
then he is bound to confess; for instance, if he has to receive the
Eucharist, to which no one can approach, after committing a mortal sin,
without confessing first, if a priest be at hand, and there be no urgent
necessity. Hence it is that the Church obliges all to confess once a
year; because she commands all to receive Holy Communion once a year,
viz. at Easter, wherefore all must go to confession before that time.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[5] Body Para. 3/5
Secondly, a man is bound absolutely to go to confession; and here the
same reason applies to delay of confession as to delay of Baptism,
because both are necessary sacraments. Now a man is not bound to receive
Baptism as soon as he makes up his mind to be baptized; and so he would
not sin mortally, if he were not baptized at once: nor is there any fixed
time beyond which, if he defer Baptism, he would incur a mortal sin.
Nevertheless the delay of Baptism may amount to a mortal sin, or it may
not, and this depends on the cause of the delay, since, as the
Philosopher says (Phys. viii, text. 15), the will does not defer doing
what it wills to do, except for a reasonable cause. Wherefore if the
cause of the delay of Baptism has a mortal sin connected with it, e.g. if
a man put off being baptized through contempt, or some like motive, the
delay will be a mortal sin, but otherwise not: and the same seems to
apply to confession which is not more necessary than Baptism. Moreover,
since man is bound to fulfill in this life those things that are
necessary for salvation, therefore, if he be in danger of death, he is
bound, even absolutely, then and there to make his confession or to
receive Baptism. For this reason too, James proclaimed at the same time
the commandment about making confession and that about receiving Extreme
Unction (James 5:14,16). Therefore the opinion seems probable of those
who say that a man is not bound to confess at once, though it is
dangerous to delay.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[5] Body Para. 4/5
Others, however, say that a contrite man is bound to confess at once, as
soon as he has a reasonable and proper opportunity. Nor does it matter
that the Decretal fixes the time limit to an annual confession, because
the Church does not favor delay, but forbids the neglect involved in a
further delay. Wherefore by this Decretal the man who delays is excused,
not from sin in the tribunal of conscience; but from punishment in the
tribunal of the Church; so that such a person would not be deprived of
proper burial if he were to die before that time. But this seems too
severe, because affirmative precepts bind, not at once, but at a fixed
time; and this, not because it is most convenient to fulfill them then
(for in that case if a man were not to give alms of his superfluous
goods, whenever he met with a man in need, he would commit a mortal sin,
which is false), but because the time involves urgency. Consequently, if
he does not confess at the very first opportunity, it does not follow
that he commits a mortal sin, even though he does not await a better
opportunity. unless it becomes urgent for him to confess through being in
danger of death. Nor is it on account of the Church's indulgence that he
is not bound to confess at once, but on account of the nature of an
affirmative precept, so that before the commandment was made, there was
still less obligation.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[5] Body Para. 5/5
Others again say that secular persons are not bound to confess before
Lent, which is the time of penance for them; but that religious are bound
to confess at once, because, for them, all time is a time for penance.
But this is not to the point; for religious have no obligations besides
those of other men, with the exception of such as they are bound to by
vow.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[5] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Hugh is speaking of those who die without this sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[5] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: It is not necessary for bodily health that the physician
be sent for at once, except when there is necessity for being healed: and
the same applies to spiritual disease.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[5] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: The retaining of another's property against the owner's
will is contrary to a negative precept, which binds always and for
always, and therefore one is always bound to make immediate restitution.
It is not the same with the fulfillment of an affirmative precept, which
binds always, but not for always, wherefore one is not bound to fulfill
it at once.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[6] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether one can be dispensed from confession?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[6] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that one can be dispensed from confessing his sins
to a man. For precepts of positive law are subject to dispensation by the
prelates of the Church. Now such is confession, as appears from what was
said above (A[3]). Therefore one may be dispensed from confession.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[6] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, a man can grant a dispensation in that which was
instituted by a man. But we read of confession being instituted, not by
God, but by a man (James 5:16): "Confess your sins, one to another." Now
the Pope has the power of dispensation in things instituted by the
apostles, as appears in the matter of bigamists. Therefore he can also
dispense a man from confessing.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[6] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, Penance, whereof confession is a part, is a necessary
sacrament, even as Baptism is. Since therefore no one can be dispensed
from Baptism, neither can one be dispensed from confession.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[6] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, The ministers of the Church are appointed in the Church
which is founded by God. Wherefore they need to be appointed by the
Church before exercising their ministry, just as the work of creation is
presupposed to the work of nature. And since the Church is founded on
faith and the sacraments, the ministers of the Church have no power to
publish new articles of faith, or to do away with those which are already
published, or to institute new sacraments, or to abolish those that are
instituted, for this belongs to the power of excellence, which belongs to
Christ alone, Who is the foundation of the Church. Consequently, the Pope
can neither dispense a man so that he may be saved without Baptism, nor
that he be saved without confession, in so far as it is obligatory in
virtue of the sacrament. He can, however, dispense from confession, in so
far as it is obligatory in virtue of the commandment of the Church; so
that a man may delay confession longer than the limit prescribed by the
Church.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[6] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The precepts of the Divine law do not bind less than those
of the natural law: wherefore, just as no dispensation is possible from
the natural law, so neither can there be from positive Divine law.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[6] A[6] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The precept about confession was not instituted by a man
first of all, though it was promulgated by James: it was instituted by
God, and although we do not read it explicitly, yet it was somewhat
foreshadowed in the fact that those who were being prepared by John's
Baptism for the grace of Christ, confessed their sins to him, and that
the Lord sent the lepers to the priests, and though they were not priests
of the New Testament, yet the priesthood of the New Testament was
foreshadowed in them.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[7] Out. Para. 1/1
OF THE NATURE OF CONFESSION (THREE ARTICLES)
We must now consider the nature of confession, under which head there
are three points of inquiry:
(3) Whether confession is an act of the virtue of penance?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[7] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether Augustine fittingly defines confession?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[7] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that Augustine defines confession unfittingly, when
he says (Super Ps. 21) that confession "lays bare the hidden disease by
the hope of pardon." For the disease against which confession is
ordained, is sin. Now sin is sometimes manifest. Therefore it should not
be said that confession is the remedy for a "hidden" disease.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[7] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the beginning of penance is fear. But confession is a
part of Penance. Therefore fear rather than "hope" should be set down as
the cause of confession.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[7] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, that which is placed under a seal, is not laid bare, but
closed up. But the sin which is confessed is placed under the seal of
confession. Therefore sin is not laid bare in confession, but closed up.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[7] A[1] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, other definitions are to be found differing from the
above. For Gregory says (Hom. xl in Evang.) that confession is "the
uncovering of sins, and the opening of the wound." Others say that
"confession is a legal declaration of our sins in the presence of a
priest." Others define it thus: "Confession is the sinner's sacramental
self-accusation through shame for what he has done, which through the
keys of the Church makes satisfaction for his sins, and binds him to
perform the penance imposed on him." Therefore it seems that the
definition in question is insufficient, since it does not include all
that these include.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[7] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Several things offer themselves to our notice in the act
of confession: first, the very substance or genus of the act, which is a
kind of manifestation; secondly, the matter manifested, viz. sin;
thirdly, the person to whom the manifestation is made, viz. the priest;
fourthly, its cause, viz. hope of pardon; fifthly, its effect, viz.
release from part of the punishment, and the obligation to pay the other
part. Accordingly the first definition, given by Augustine, indicates
the substance of the act, by saying that "it lays bare"---the matter of
confession, by saying that it is a "hidden disease"---its cause, which is
"the hope of pardon"; while the other definitions include one or other of
the five things aforesaid, as may be seen by anyone who considers the
matter.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[7] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Although the priest, as a man, may sometimes have knowledge
of the penitent's sin, yet he does not know it as a vicar of Christ (even
as a judge sometimes knows a thing, as a man, of which he is ignorant, as
a judge), and in this respect it is made known to him by confession. or
we may reply that although the external act may be in the open, yet the
internal act, which is the cause of the external act, is hidden; so that
it needs to be revealed by confession.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[7] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Confession presupposes charity, which gives us life, as
stated in the text (Sent. iv, D, 17). Now it is in contrition that
charity is given; while servile fear, which is void of hope, is previous
to charity: yet he that has charity is moved more by hope than by fear.
Hence hope rather than fear is set down as the cause of confession.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[7] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: In every confession sin is laid bare to the priest, and
closed to others by the seal of confession.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[7] A[1] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: It is not necessary that every definition should include
everything connected with the thing defined: and for this reason we find
some definitions or descriptions that indicate one cause, and some that
indicate another.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[7] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether confession is an act of virtue?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[7] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that confession is not an act of virtue. For every
act of virtue belongs to the natural law, since "we are naturally capable
of virtue," as the Philosopher says (Ethic. ii, 1). But confession does
not belong to the natural law. Therefore it is not an act of virtue.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[7] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, an act of virtue is more befitting one who is innocent
than one who has sinned. But the confession of a sin, which is the
confession of which we are speaking now, cannot be befitting an innocent
man. Therefore it is not an act of virtue.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[7] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, the grace which is in the sacraments differs somewhat
from the grace which is in the virtues and gifts. But confession is part
of a sacrament. Therefore it is not an act of virtue.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[7] A[2] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, The precepts of the law are about acts of virtue. But
confession comes under a precept. Therefore it is an act of virtue.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[7] A[2] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, we do not merit except by acts of virtue. But confession is
meritorious, for "it opens the gate of heaven," as the Master says (Sent.
iv, D, 17). Therefore it seems that it is an act of virtue.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[7] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, As stated above (FS, Q[18], AA[6],7; SS, Q[80]; SS, Q[85]
, A[3]; SS, Q[109], A[3]), for an act to belong to a virtue it suffices
that it be of such a nature as to imply some condition belonging to
virtue. Now, although confession does not include everything that is
required for virtue, yet its very name implies the manifestation of that
which a man has on his conscience: for thus his lips and heart agree. For
if a man professes with his lips what he does not hold in his heart, it
is not a confession but a fiction. Now to express in words what one has
in one's thoughts is a condition of virtue; and, consequently, confession
is a good thing generically, and is an act of virtue: yet it can be done
badly, if it be devoid of other due circumstances.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[7] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Natural reason, in a general way, inclines a man to make
confession in the proper way, to confess as he ought, what he ought, and
when he ought, and in this way confession belongs to the natural law. But
it belongs to the Divine law to determine the circumstances, when, how,
what, and to whom, with regard to the confession of which we are speaking
now. Accordingly it is evident that the natural law inclines a man to
confession, by means of the Divine law, which determines the
circumstances, as is the case with all matters belonging to the positive
law.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[7] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Although an innocent man may have the habit of the virtue
whose object is a sin already committed, he has not the act, so long as
he remains innocent. Wherefore the confession of sins, of which
confession we are speaking now, is not befitting an innocent man, though
it is an act of virtue.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[7] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Though the grace of the sacraments differs from the grace
of the virtues, they are not contrary but disparate; hence there is
nothing to prevent that which is an act of virtue, in so far as it
proceeds from the free-will quickened by grace, from being a sacrament,
or part of a sacrament, in so far as it is ordained as a remedy for sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[7] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether confession is an act of the virtue of penance?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[7] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that confession is not an act of the virtue of
penance. For an act belongs to the virtue which is its cause. Now the
cause of confession is the hope of pardon, as appears from the definition
given above (A[1]). Therefore it seems that it is an act of hope and not
of penance.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[7] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, shame is a part of temperance. But confession arises
from shame, as appears in the definition given above (A[1], OBJ[4]).
Therefore it is an act of temperance and not of penance.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[7] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, the act of penance leans on Divine mercy. But confession
leans rather on Divine wisdom, by reason of the truth which is required
in it. Therefore it is not an act of penance.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[7] A[3] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, we are moved to penance by the article of the Creed
which is about the Judgment, on account of fear, which is the origin of
penance. But we are moved to confession by the article which is about
life everlasting, because it arises from hope of pardon. Therefore it is
not an act of penance.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[7] A[3] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, it belongs to the virtue of truth that a man shows
himself to be what he is. But this is what a man does when he goes to
confession. Therefore confession is an act of that virtue which is called
truth, and not of penance.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[7] A[3] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, Penance is ordained for the destruction of sin. Now
confession is ordained to this also. Therefore it is an act of penance.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[7] A[3] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, It must be observed with regard to virtues, that when a
special reason of goodness or difficulty is added over and above the
object of a virtue, there is need of a special virtue: thus the
expenditure of large sums is the object of magnificence, although the
ordinary kind of average expenditure and gifts belongs to liberality, as
appears from Ethic. ii, 7; iv, 1. The same applies to the confession of
truth, which, although it belongs to the virtue of truth absolutely, yet,
on account of the additional reason of goodness, begins to belong to
another kind of virtue. Hence the Philosopher says (Ethic. iv, 7) that a
confession made in a court of justice belongs to the virtue of justice
rather than to truth. In like manner the confession of God's favors in
praise of God, belongs not to truth, but to religion: and so too the
confession of sins, in order to receive pardon for them, is not the
elicited act of the virtue of truth, as some say, but of the virtue of
penance. It may, however, be the commanded act of many virtues, in so far
as the act of confession can be directed to the end of many virtues.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[7] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Hope is the cause of confession, not as eliciting but as
commanding.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[7] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: In that definition shame is not mentioned as the cause of
confession, since it is more of a nature to hinder the act of confession,
but rather as the joint cause of delivery from punishment (because shame
is in itself a punishment), since also the keys of the Church are the
joint cause with confession, to the same effect.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[7] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: By a certain adaptation the parts of Penance can be
ascribed to three Personal Attributes, so that contrition may correspond
to mercy or goodness, by reason of its being sorrow for evil---confession
to wisdom, by reason of its being a manifestation of the truth---and
satisfaction to power, on account of the labor it entails. And since
contrition is the first part of Penance, and renders the other parts
efficacious, for this reason the same is to be said of Penance as a
whole, as of contrition.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[7] A[3] R.O. 4 Para. 1/2
Reply OBJ 4: Since confession results from hope rather than from fear,
as stated above (A[1], ad 2), it is based on the article about eternal
life which hope looks to, rather than on the article about the Judgment,
which fear considers; although penance, in its aspect of contrition, is
the opposite.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[7] A[3] R.O. 4 Para. 2/2
The Reply to the Fifth Objection is to be gathered from what has been
said.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] Out. Para. 1/1
OF THE MINISTER OF CONFESSION (SEVEN ARTICLES)
We must now consider the minister of confession, under which head there
are seven points of inquiry:
(1) Whether it is necessary to confess to a priest?
(2) Whether it is ever lawful to confess to another than a priest?
(3) Whether outside a case of necessity one who is not a priest can hear
the confession of venial sins?
(4) Whether it is necessary for a man to confess to his own priest?
(5) Whether it is lawful for anyone to confess to another than his own
priest, in virtue of a privilege or of the command of a superior?
(6) Whether a penitent, in danger of death can be absolved by any priest?
(7) Whether the temporal punishment should be enjoined in proportion to
the sin?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether it is necessary to confess to a priest?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that it is not necessary to confess to a priest.
For we are not bound to confession, except in virtue of its Divine
institution. Now its Divine institution is made known to us (James 5:16):
"Confess your sins, one to another," where there is no mention of a
priest. Therefore it is not necessary to confess to a priest.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, Penance is a necessary sacrament, as is also Baptism.
But any man is the minister of Baptism, on account of its necessity.
Therefore any man is the minister of Penance. Now confession should be
made to the minister of Penance. Therefore it suffices to confess to
anyone.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, confession is necessary in order that the measure of
satisfaction should be imposed on the penitent. Now, sometimes another
than a priest might be more discreet than many priests are in imposing
the measure of satisfaction on the penitent. Therefore it is not
necessary to confess to a priest.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[1] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, confession was instituted in the Church in order that
the rectors might know their sheep by sight. But sometimes a rector or
prelate is not a priest. Therefore confession should not always be made
to a priest.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[1] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, The absolution of the penitent, for the sake of which
he makes his confession, is imparted by none but priests to whom the keys
are intrusted. Therefore confession should be made to a priest.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[1] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, confession is foreshadowed in the raising of the dead Lazarus
to life. Now our Lord commanded none but the disciples to loose Lazarus
(Jn. 11:44). Therefore confession should be made to a priest.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, The grace which is given in the sacraments, descends from
the Head to the members. Wherefore he alone who exercises a ministry over
Christ's true body is a minister of the sacraments, wherein grace is
given; and this belongs to a priest alone, who can consecrate the
Eucharist. Therefore, since grace is given in the sacrament of Penance,
none but a priest is the minister of the sacrament: and consequently
sacramental confession which should be made to a minister of the Church,
should be made to none but a priest.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: James speaks on the presupposition of the Divine
institutions: and since confession had already been prescribed by God to
be made to a priest, in that He empowered them, in the person of the
apostles, to forgive sins, as related in Jn. 20:23, we must take the
words of James as conveying an admonishment to confess to priests.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Baptism is a sacrament of greater necessity than Penance,
as regards confession and absolution, because sometimes Baptism cannot be
omitted without loss of eternal salvation, as in the case of children who
have not come to the use of reason: whereas this cannot be said of
confession and absolution, which regard none but adults, in whom
contrition, together with the purpose of confessing and the desire of
absolution, suffices to deliver them from everlasting death. Consequently
there is no parity between Baptism and confession.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: In satisfaction we must consider not only the quantity of
the punishment but also its power, inasmuch as it is part of a sacrament.
In this way it requires a dispenser of the sacraments, though the
quantity of the punishment may be fixed by another than a priest.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[1] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: It may be necessary for two reasons to know the sheep by
sight. First, in order to register them as members of Christ's flock, and
to know the sheep by sight thus belongs to the pastoral charge and care,
which is sometimes the duty of those who are not priests. Secondly, that
they may be provided with suitable remedies for their health; and to know
the sheep by sight thus belongs to the man, i.e. the priest, whose
business it is to provide remedies conducive to health, such as the
sacrament of the Eucharist, and other like things. It is to this
knowledge of the sheep that confession is ordained.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether it is ever lawful to confess to another than a priest?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that it is never lawful to confess to another than
a priest. For confession is a sacramental accusation, as appears from the
definition given above (Q[7], A[1]). But the dispensing of a sacrament
belongs to none but the minister of a sacrament. Since then the proper
minister of Penance is a priest, it seems that confession should be made
to no one else.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, in every court of justice confession is ordained to the
sentence. Now in a disputed case the sentence is void if pronounced by
another than the proper judge; so that confession should be made to none
but a judge. But, in the court of conscience, the judge is none but a
priest, who has the power of binding and loosing. Therefore confession
should be made to no one else.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, in the case of Baptism, since anyone can baptize, if a
layman has baptized, even without necessity, the Baptism should not be
repeated by a priest. But if anyone confess to a layman in a case of
necessity, he is bound to repeat his confession to a priest, when the
cause for urgency has passed. Therefore confession should not be made to
a layman in a case of necessity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, is the authority of the text (Sent. iv, D, 17).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Just as Baptism is a necessary sacrament, so is Penance.
And Baptism, through being a necessary sacrament has a twofold minister:
one whose duty it is to baptize, in virtue of his office, viz. the
priest, and another, to whom the conferring of Baptism is committed, in a
case of necessity. In like manner the minister of Penance, to whom, in
virtue of his office, confession should be made, is a priest; but in a
case of necessity even a layman may take the place of a priest, and hear
a person's confession.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: In the sacrament of Penance there is not only something on
the part of the minister, viz. the absolution and imposition of
satisfaction, but also something on the part of the recipient, which is
also essential to the sacrament, viz. contrition and confession. Now
satisfaction originates from the minister in so far as he enjoins it, and
from the penitent who fulfills it; and, for the fulness of the sacrament,
both these things should concur when possible. But when there is reason
for urgency, the penitent should fulfill his own part, by being contrite
and confessing to whom he can; and although this person cannot perfect
the sacrament, so as to fulfill the part of the priest by giving
absolution, yet this defect is supplied by the High Priest. Nevertheless
confession made to a layman, through lack* of a priest, is
quasi-sacramental, although it is not a perfect sacrament, on account of
the absence of the part which belongs to the priest. [*Here and in the
Reply to OBJ[2] the Leonine edition reads "through desire for a priest".]
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Although a layman is not the judge of the person who
confesses to him, yet, on account of the urgency, he does take the place
of a judge over him, absolutely speaking, in so far as the penitent
submits to him, through lack of a priest.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: By means of the sacraments man must needs be reconciled not
only to God, but also to the Church. Now he cannot be reconciled to the
Church, unless the hallowing of the Church reach him. In Baptism the
hallowing of the Church reaches a man through the element itself applied
externally, which is sanctified by "the word of life" (Eph. 5:26), by
whomsoever it is conferred: and so when once a man has been baptized, no
matter by whom, he must not be baptized again. On the other hand, in
Penance the hallowing of the Church reaches man by the minister alone,
because in that sacrament there is no bodily element applied externally,
through the hallowing of which grace may be conferred. Consequently
although the man who, in a case of necessity, has confessed to a layman,
has received forgiveness from God, for the reason that he fulfilled, so
far as he could, the purpose which he conceived in accordance with God's
command, he is not yet reconciled to the Church, so as to be admitted to
the sacraments, unless he first be absolved by a priest, even as he who
has received the Baptism of desire, is not admitted to the Eucharist.
Wherefore he must confess again to a priest, as soon as there is one at
hand, and the more so since, as stated above (ad 1), the sacrament of
Penance was not perfected, and so it needs yet to be perfected, in order
that by receiving the sacrament, the penitent may receive a more
plentiful effect, and that he may fulfill the commandment about receiving
the sacrament of Penance.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether, outside a case of necessity, anyone who is not a priest may hear
the confession of venial sins?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that, outside a case of necessity, no one but a
priest may hear the confession of venial sins. For the dispensation of a
sacrament is committed to a layman by reason of necessity. But the
confession of venial sins is not necessary. Therefore it is not committed
to a layman.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, Extreme Unction is ordained against venial sin, just as
Penance is. But the former may not be given by a layman, as appears from
James 5:14. Therefore neither can the confession of venial sins be made
to a layman.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[3] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, is the authority of Bede (on James 5:16, "Confess . . .
one to another") quoted in the text (Sent. iv, D, 17).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[3] Body Para. 1/2
I answer that, By venial sin man is separated neither from God nor from
the sacraments of the Church: wherefore he does not need to receive any
further grace for the forgiveness of such a sin, nor does he need to be
reconciled to the Church. Consequently a man does not need to confess his
venial sins to a priest. And since confession made to a layman is a
sacramental, although it is not a perfect sacrament, and since it
proceeds from charity, it has a natural aptitude to remit sins, just as
the beating of one's breast, or the sprinkling of holy water (cf. TP,
Q[87], A[3]).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[3] Body Para. 2/2
This suffices for the Reply to the First Objection, because there is no
need to receive a sacrament for the forgiveness of venial sins. and a
sacramental, such as holy water or the like, suffices for the purpose.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Extreme Unction is not given directly as a remedy for
venial sin, nor is any other sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether it is necessary for one to confess to one's own priest?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that it is nol necessary to confess to one's own
priest. For Gregory [*Cf. Can. Ex auctoritate xvi, Q[1]] says: "By our
apostolic authority and in discharge of our solicitude we have decreed
that priests, who as monks imitate the ex. ample of the apostles, may
preach, baptize, give communion, pray for sinners, impose penances, and
absolve from sins." Now monks are not the proper priests of anyone, since
they have not the care of souls. Since, therefore confession is made for
the sake of absolution it suffices for it to be made to any priest.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the minister of this sacrament is a priest, as also of
the Eucharist. But any priest can perform the Eucharist. Therefore any
priest can administer the sacrament of Penance. Therefore there is no
need to confess to one's own priest.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[4] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, when we are bound to one thing in particular it is not
left to our choice. But the choice of a discreet priest is left to us as
appears from the authority of Augustine quoted in the text (Sent. ix, D,
17): for he says in De vera et falsa Poenitentia [*Work of an unknown
author]: "He who wishes to confess his sins, in order to find grace, must
seek a priest who knows how to loose and to bind." Therefore it seems
unnecessary to confess to one's own priest.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[4] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, there are some, such as prelates, who seem to have no
priest of their own, since they have no superior: yet they are bound to
confession. Therefore a man is not always bound to confess to his own
priest.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[4] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, "That which is instituted for the sake of charity, does
not militate against charity," as Bernard observes (De Praecept. et
Dispens. ii). Now confession, which was instituted for the sake of
charity, would militate against charity, if a man were bound to confess
to any particular priest: e.g. if the sinner know that his own priest is
a heretic, or a man of evil influence, or weak and prone to the very sin
that he wishes to confess to him, or reasonably suspected of breaking the
seal of confession, or if the penitent has to confess a sin committed
against his confessor. Therefore it seems that one need not always
confess to one's own priest.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[4] Obj. 6 Para. 1/1
OBJ 6: Further, men should not be straitened in matters necessary for
salvation, lest they be hindered in the way of salvation. But it seems a
great inconvenience to be bound of necessity to confess to one particular
man, and many might be hindered from going to confession, through either
fear, shame, or something else of the kind. Therefore, since confession
is necessary for salvation, men should not be straitened, as apparently
they would be, by having to confess to their own priest.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[4] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, stands a decree of Pope Innocent III in the Fourth
Lateran Council (Can. 21), who appointed "all of either sex to confess
once a year to their own priest."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[4] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, as a bishop is to his diocese, so is a priest to his parish.
Now it is unlawful, according to canon law (Can. Nullus primas ix, Q[2];
Can. Si quis episcoporum xvi, Q[5]), for a bishop to exercise the
episcopal office in another diocese. Therefore it is not lawful for one
priest to hear the confession of another's parishioner.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[4] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, The other sacraments do not consist in an action of the
recipient, but only in his receiving something, as is evident with regard
to Baptism and so forth. though the action of the recipient is required
as removing an obstacle, i.e. insincerity, in order that he may receive
the benefit of the sacrament, if he has come to the use of his free-will.
On the other hand, the action of the man who approaches the sacrament of
Penance is essential to the sacrament, since contrition, confession, and
satisfaction, which are acts of the penitent, are parts of Penance. Now
our actions, since they have their origin in us, cannot be dispensed by
others, except through their command. Hence whoever is appointed a
dispenser of this sacrament, must be such as to be able to command
something to be done. Now a man is not competent to command another
unless he have jurisdiction over him. Consequently it is essential to
this sacrament, not only for the minister to be in orders, as in the case
of the other sacraments, but also for him to have jurisdiction: wherefore
he that has no jurisdiction cannot administer this sacrament any more
than one who is not a priest. Therefore confession should be made not
only to a priest, but to one's own priest; for since a priest does not
absolve a man except by binding him to do something, he alone can
absolve, who, by his command, can bind the penitent to do something.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Gregory is speaking of those monks who have jurisdiction,
through having charge of a parish; about whom some had maintained that
from the very fact that they were monks, they could not absolve or impose
penance, which is false.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The sacrament of the Eucharist does not require the power
of command over a man, whereas this sacrament does, as stated above: and
so the argument proves nothing. Nevertheless it is not lawful to receive
the Eucharist from another than one's own priest, although it is a real
sacrament that one receives from another.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[4] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: The choice of a discreet priest is not left to us in such a
way that we can do just as we like; but it is left to the permission of a
higher authority, if perchance one's own priest happens to be less
suitable for applying a salutary remedy to our sins.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[4] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: Since it is the duty of prelates to dispense the
sacraments, which the clean alone should handle, they are allowed by law
(De Poenit. et Remiss., Cap. Ne pro dilatione) to choose a priest for
their confessor; who in this respect is the prelate's superior; even as
one physician is cured by another, not as a physician but as a patient.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[4] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: In those cases wherein the penitent has reason to fear some
harm to himself or to the priest by reason of his confessing to him, he
should have recourse to the higher authority, or ask permission of the
priest himself to confess to another; and if he fails to obtain
permission, the case is to be decided as for a man who has no priest at
hand; so that he should rather choose a layman and confess to him. Nor
does he disobey the law of the Church by so doing, because the precepts
of positive law do not extend beyond the intention of the lawgiver, which
is the end of the precept, and in this case, is charity, according to the
Apostle (1 Tim. 1:5). Nor is any slur cast on the priest, for he deserves
to forfeit his privilege, for abusing the power intrusted to him.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[4] R.O. 6 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 6: The necessity of confessing to one's own priest does not
straiten the way of salvation, but determines it sufficiently. A priest,
however, would sin if he were not easy in giving permission to confess to
another, because many are so weak that they would rather die without
confession than confess to such a priest. Wherefore those priests who are
too anxious to probe the consciences of their subjects by means of
confession, lay a snare of damnation for many, and consequently for
themselves.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[5] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether it is lawful for anyone to confess to another than his own
priest, in virtue of a privilege or a command given by a superior?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[5] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that it is not lawful for anyone to confess to
another than his own priest, even in virtue of a privilege or command
given by a superior. For no privilege should be given that wrongs a third
party. Now it would be prejudicial to the subject's own priest, if he
were to confess to another. Therefore this cannot be allowed by a
superior's privilege, permission, or command.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[5] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, that which hinders the observance of a Divine command
cannot be the subject of a command or privilege given by man. Now it is a
Divine command to the rectors of churches to "know the countenance of
their own cattle" (Prov. 27:23); and this is hindered if another than the
rector hear the confession of his subjects. Therefore this cannot be
prescribed by any human privilege or command.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[5] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, he that hears another's confession is the latter's own
judge, else he could not bind or loose him. Now one man cannot have
several priests or judges of his own, for then he would be bound to obey
several men, which would be impossible, if their commands were contrary
or incompatible. Therefore one may not confess to another than one's own
priest, even with the superior's permission.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[5] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, it is derogatory to a sacrament, or at least useless, to
repeat a sacrament over the same matter. But he who has confessed to
another priest, is bound to confess again to his own priest, if the
latter requires him to do so, because he is not absolved from his
obedience, whereby he is bound to him in this respect. Therefore it
cannot be lawful for anyone to confess to another than his own priest.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[5] OTC Para. 1/3
On the contrary, He that can perform the actions of an order can depute
the exercise thereof to anyone who has the same order. Now a superior,
such as a bishop, can hear the confession of anyone belonging to a
priest's parish, for sometimes he reserves certain cases to himself,
since he is the chief rector. Therefore he can also depute another priest
to hear that man.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[5] OTC Para. 2/3
Further, a superior can do whatever his subject can do. But the priest
himself can give his parishioner permission to confess to another. Much
more, therefore, can his superior do this.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[5] OTC Para. 3/3
Further, the power which a priest has among his people, comes to him
from the bishop. Now it is through that power that he can hear
confessions. Therefore, in like manner, another can do so, to whom the
bishop gives the same power.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[5] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, A priest may be hindered in two ways from hearing a man's
confession: first, through lack of jurisdiction; secondly, through being
prevented from exercising his order, as those who are excommunicate,
degraded, and so forth. Now whoever has jurisdiction, can depute to
another whatever comes under his jurisdiction; so that if a priest is
hindered from hearing a man's confession through want of jurisdiction,
anyone who has immediate jurisdiction over that man, priest, bishop, or
Pope, can depute that priest to hear his confession and absolve him. If,
on the other hand, the priest cannot hear the confession, on account of
an impediment to the exercise of his order, anyone who has the power to
remove that impediment can permit him to hear confessions.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[5] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: No wrong is done to a person unless what is taken away from
him was granted for his own benefit. Now the power of jurisdiction is not
granted a man for his own benefit, but for the good of the people and for
the glory of God. Wherefore if the higher prelates deem it expedient for
the furthering of the people's salvation and God's glory, to commit
matters of jurisdiction to others, no wrong is done to the inferior
prelates, except to those who "seek the things that are their own; not
the things that are Jesus Christ's" (Phil. 2:21), and who rule their
flock, not by feeding it, but by feeding on it.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[5] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The rector of a church should "know the countenance of his
own cattle" in two ways. First, by an assiduous attention to their
external conduct, so as to watch over the flock committed to his care:
and in acquiring this knowledge he should not believe his subject, but,
as far as possible, inquire into the truth of facts. Secondly, by the
manifestation of confession; and with regard to this knowledge, he cannot
arrive at any greater certainty than by believing his subject, because
this is necessary that he may help his subject's conscience. Consequently
in the tribunal of confession, the penitent is believed whether he speak
for himself or against himself, but not in the court of external
judgment: wherefore it suffices for this knowledge that he believe the
penitent when he says that he has confessed to one who could absolve him.
It is therefore clear that this knowledge of the flock is not hindered by
a privilege granted to another to hear confessions.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[5] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: It would be inconvenient, if two men were placed equally
over the same people, but there is no inconvenience if over the same
people two are placed one of whom is over the other. In this way the
parish priest, the bishop, and the Pope are placed immediately over the
same people, and each of them can commit matters of jurisdiction to some
other. Now a higher superior delegates a man in two ways: first, so that
the latter takes the superior's place, as when the Pope or a bishop
appoints his penitentiaries; and then the man thus delegated is higher
than the inferior prelate, as the Pope's penitentiary is higher than a
bishop, and the bishop's penitentiary than a parish priest, and the
penitent is bound to obey the former rather than the latter. Secondly, so
that the delegate is appointed the coadjutor of this other priest; and
since a co-adjutor is subordinate to the person he is appointed to help,
he holds a lower rank, and the penitent is not so bound to obey him as
his own priest.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[5] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: No man is bound to confess sins that he has no longer.
Consequently, if a man has confessed to the bishop's penitentiary, or to
someone else having faculties from the bishop, his sins are forgiven both
before the Church and before God, so that he is not bound to confess them
to his own priest, however much the latter may insist: but on account of
the Ecclesiastical precept (De Poenit. et Remiss., Cap. Omnis utriusque)
which prescribes confession to be made once a year to one's own priest,
he is under the same obligation as one who has committed none but venial
sins. For such a one, according to some, is bound to confess none but
venial sins, or he must declare that he is free from mortal sin, and the
priest, in the tribunal of conscience, ought, and is bound, to believe
him. If, however, he were bound to confess again, his first confession
would not be useless, because the more priests one confesses to, the more
is the punishment remitted, both by reason of the shame in confessing,
which is reckoned as a satisfactory punishment, and by reason of the
power of the keys: so that one might confess so often as to be delivered
from all punishment. Nor is repetition derogatory to a sacrament, except
in those wherein there is some kind of sanctification, either by the
impressing of a character, or by the consecration of the matter, neither
of which applies to Penance. Hence it would be well for him who hears
confessions by the bishop's authority, to advise the penitent to confess
to his own priest, yet he must absolve him, even if he declines to do so.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[6] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether a penitent, at the point of death, can be absolved by any priest?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[6] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that a penitent, at the point of death, cannot be
absolved by any priest. For absolution requires jurisdiction, as stated
above (A[5]). Now a priest does not acquire jurisdiction over a man who
repents at the point of death. Therefore he cannot absolve him.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[6] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, he that receives the sacrament of Baptism, when in
danger of death, from another than his own priest, does not need to be
baptized again by the latter. If, therefore, any priest can absolve, from
any sin, a man who is in danger of death, the penitent, if he survive the
danger, need not go to his own priest; which is false, since otherwise
the priest would not "know the countenance of his cattle."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[6] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, when there is danger of death, Baptism can be conferred
not only by a strange priest, but also by one who is not a priest. But
one who is not a priest can never absolve in the tribunal of Penance.
Therefore neither can a priest absolve a man who is not his subject, when
he is in danger of death.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[6] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, Spiritual necessity is greater than bodily necessity.
But it is lawful in a case of extreme necessity, for a man to make use of
another's property, even against the owner's will, in order to supply a
bodily need. Therefore in danger of death, a man may be absolved by
another than his own priest, in order to supply his spiritual need.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[6] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, the authorities quoted in the text prove the same (Sent. iv, D,
20, Cap. Non Habet).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[6] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, If we consider the power of the keys, every priest has
power over all men equally and over all sins: and it is due to the fact
that by the ordination of the Church, he has a limited jurisdiction or
none at all, that he cannot absolve all men from all sins. But since
"necessity knows no law" [*Cap. Consilium, De observ. jejun.; De reg.
jur. (v, Decretal)] in cases of necessity the ordination of the Church
does not hinder him from being able to absolve, since he has the keys
sacramentally: and the penitent will receive as much benefit from the
absolution of this other priest as if he had been absolved by his own.
Moreover a man can then be absolved by any priest not only from his sins,
but also from excommunication, by whomsoever pronounced, because such
absolution is also a matter of that jurisdiction which by the ordination
of the Church is con. fined within certain limits.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[6] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: One person may act on the jurisdiction of another according
to the latter's will, since matters of jurisdiction can be deputed.
Since, therefore, the Church recognizes absolution granted by any priest
at the hour of death, from this very fact a priest has the use of
jurisdiction though he lack the power of jurisdiction.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[6] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: He needs to go to his own priest, not that he may be
absolved again from the sins, from which he was absolved when in danger
of death, but that his own priest may know that he is absolved. In like
manner, he who has been absolved from excommunication needs to go to the
judge, who in other circumstances could have absolved him, not in order
to seek absolution, but in order to offer satisfaction.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[6] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Baptism derives its efficacy from the sanctification of the
matter itself, so that a man receives the sacrament whosoever baptizes
him: whereas the sacramental power of Penance consists in a
sanctification pronounced by the minister, so that if a man confess to a
layman, although he fulfills his own part of the sacramental confession,
he does not receive sacramental absolution. Wherefore his confession
avails him somewhat, as to the lessening of his punishment, owing to the
merit derived from his confession and to his repentance. but he does not
receive that diminution of his punishment which results from the power of
the keys; and consequently he must confess again to a priest; and one who
has confessed thus, is more punished hereafter than if he had confessed
to a priest.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[7] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the temporal punishment is imposed according to the degree of the
fault?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[7] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the temporal punishment, the debt of which
remains after Penance, is not imposed according to the degree of fault.
For it is imposed according to the degree of pleasure derived from the
sin, as appears from Apoc. 18:7: "As much as she hath glorified herself
and lived in delicacies, so much torment and sorrow give ye her." Yet
sometimes where there is greater pleasure, there is less fault, since
"carnal sins, which afford more pleasure than spiritual sins, are less
guilty," according to Gregory (Moral. xxxiii, 2). Therefore the
punishment is not imposed according to the degree of fault.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[7] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, in the New Law one is bound to punishment for mortal
sins, in the same way as in the Old Law. Now in the Old Law the
punishment for sin was due to last seven days, in other words, they had
to remain unclean seven days for one mortal sin. Since therefore, in the
New Testament, a punishment of seven years is imposed for one mortal sin,
it seems that the quantity of the punishment does not answer to the
degree of fault.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[7] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, the sin of murder in a layman is more grievous than that
of fornication in a priest, because the circumstance which is taken from
the species of a sin, is more aggravating than that which is taken from
the person of the sinner. Now a punishment of seven years' duration is
appointed for a layman guilty of murder, while for fornication a priest
is punished for ten years, according to Can. Presbyter, Dist. lxxxii.
Therefore punishment is not imposed according to the degree of fault.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[7] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, a sin committed against the very body of Christ is most
grievous, because the greater the person sinned against, the more
grievous the sin. Now for spilling the blood of Christ in the sacrament
of the altar a punishment of forty days or a little more is enjoined,
while a punishment of seven years is prescribed for fornication,
according to the Canons (Can. Presbyter, Dist. lxxxii). Therefore the
quantity of the punishment does not answer to the degree of fault.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[7] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, It is written (Is. 27:8): "In measure against measure,
when it shall be cast off, thou shalt judge it." Therefore the quantity
of punishment adjudicated for sin answers the degree of fault.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[7] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, man is reduced to the equality of justice by the punishment
inflicted on him. But this would not be so if the quantity of the fault
and of the punishment did not mutually correspond. Therefore one answers
to the other.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[7] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, After the forgiveness of sin, a punishment is required
for two reasons, viz. to pay the debt, and to afford a remedy. Hence the
punishment may be imposed in consideration of two things. First, in
consideration of the debt, and in this way the quantity of the punishment
corresponds radically to the quantity of the fault, before anything of
the latter is forgiven: yet the more there is remitted by the first of
those things which are of a nature to remit punishment, the less there
remains to be remitted or paid by the other, because the more contrition
remits of the punishment, the less there remains to be remitted by
confession. Secondly, in consideration of the remedy, either as regards
the one who sinned, or as regards others: and thus sometimes a greater
punishment is enjoined for a lesser sin; either because one man's sin is
more difficult to resist than another's (thus a heavier punishment is
imposed on a young man for fornication, than on an old man, though the
former's sin be less grievous), or because one man's sin; for instance, a
priest's, is more dangerous to others, than another's sin, or because the
people are more prone to that particular sin, so that it is necessary by
the punishment of the one man to deter others. Consequently, in the
tribunal of Penance, the punishment has to be imposed with due regard to
both these things: and so a greater punishment is not always imposed for
a greater sin. on the other hand, the punishment of Purgatory is only for
the payment of the debt, because there is no longer any possibility of
sinning, so that this punishment is meted only according to the measure
of sin, with due consideration however for the degree of contrition, and
for confession and absolution, since all these lessen the punishment
somewhat: wherefore the priest in enjoining satisfaction should bear them
in mind.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[7] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: In the words quoted two things are mentioned with regard to
the sin, viz. "glorification" and "delicacies" or "delectation"; the
first of which regards the uplifting of the sinner, whereby he resists
God; while the second regards the pleasure of sin: and though sometimes
there is less pleasure in a greater sin, yet there is greater uplifting;
wherefore the argument does not prove.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[7] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: This punishment of seven days did not expiate the
punishment due for the sin, so that even if the sinner died after that
time, he would be punished in Purgatory: but it was in expiation of the
irregularity incurred, from which all the legal sacrifices expiated.
Nevertheless, other things being equal, a man sins more grievously under
the New Law than under the Old, on account of the more plentiful
sanctification received in Baptism, and on account of the more powerful
blessings bestowed by God on the human race. This is evident from Heb.
29: "How much more, do you think, he deserveth worse punishments," etc.
And yet it is not universally true that a seven years' penance is exacted
for every mortal sin: but it is a kind of general rule applicable to the
majority of cases, which must, nevertheless, be disregarded, with due
consideration for the various circumstances of sins and penitents.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[7] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: A bishop or priest sins with greater danger to others or to
himself; wherefore the canons are more anxious to withdraw him from sin,
by inflicting a greater punishment, in as much as it is intended as a
remedy; although sometimes so great a punishment is not strictly due.
Hence he is punished less in Purgatory.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[8] A[7] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: This punishment refers to the case when this happens
against the priest's will: for if he spilled it willingly he would
deserve a much heavier punishment.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] Out. Para. 1/1
OF THE QUALITY OF CONFESSION (FOUR ARTICLES)
We must now consider the quality of confession: under which head there
are four points of inquiry:
(1) Whether confession can be lacking in form?
(2) Whether confession ought to be entire?
(3) Whether one can confess through another, or by writing?
(4) Whether the sixteen conditions, which are assigned by the masters,
are necessary for confession?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether confession can be lacking in form?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that confession cannot be lacking in form. For it
is written (Ecclus. 17:26): "Praise [confession] perisheth from the dead
as nothing." But a man without charity is dead, because charity is the
life of the soul. Therefore there can be no confession without charity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, confession is condivided with contrition and
satisfaction. But contrition and satisfaction are impossible without
charity. Therefore confession is also impossible without charity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, it is necessary in confession that the word should agree
with the thought for the very name of confession requires this. Now if a
man confess while remaining attached to sin, his word is not in accord
with his thought, since in his heart he holds to sin, while he condemns
it with his lips. Therefore such a man does not confess.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[1] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, Every man is bound to confess his mortal sins. Now if a
man in mortal sin has confessed once, he is not bound to confess the same
sins again, because, as no man knows himself to have charity, no man
would know of him that he had confessed. Therefore it is not necessary
that confession should be quickened by charity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Confession is an act of virtue, and is part of a
sacrament. In so far as it is an act of virtue, it has the property of
being meritorious, and thus is of no avail without charity, which is the
principle of merit. But in so far as it is part of a sacrament, it
subordinates the penitent to the priest who has the keys of the Church,
and who by means of the confession knows the conscience of the person
confessing. In this way it is possible for confession to be in one who is
not contrite, for he can make his sins known to the priest, and subject
himself to the keys of the Church: and though he does not receive the
fruit of absolution then, yet he will begin to receive it, when he is
sincerely contrite, as happens in the other sacraments: wherefore he is
not bound to repeat his confession, but to confess his lack of sincerity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: These words must be understood as referring to the
receiving of the fruit of confession, which none can receive who is not
in the state of charity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Contrition and satisfaction are offered to God: but
confession is made to man: hence it is essential to contrition and
satisfaction, but not to confession, that man should be united to God by
charity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: He who declares the sins which he has, speaks the truth;
and thus his thought agrees with his lips or words, as to the substance
of confession, though it is discordant with the purpose of confession.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether confession should be entire?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that it is not necessary for confession to be
entire, namely, for a man to confess all his sins to one priest. For
shame conduces to the diminution of punishment. Now the greater the
number of priests to whom a man confesses, the greater his shame.
Therefore confession is more fruitful if it be divided among several
priests.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, confession is necessary in Penance in order that
punishment may be enjoined for sin according to the judgment of the
priest. Now a sufficient punishment for different sins can be imposed by
different priests. Therefore it is not necessary to confess all one's
sins to one priest.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, it may happen that a man after going to confession and
performing his penance, remembers a mortal sin, which escaped his memory
while confessing, and that his own priest to whom he confessed first is
no longer available, so that he can only confess that sin to another
priest, and thus he will confess different sins to different priests.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[2] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, the sole reason for confessing one's sins to a priest is
in order to receive absolution. Now sometimes, the priest who hears a
confession can absolve from some of the sins, but not from all. Therefore
in such a case at all events the confession need not be entire.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, Hypocrisy is an obstacle to Penance. But it savors of
hypocrisy to divide one's confession, as Augustine says [*De vera et
falsa Poenitentia, work of an unknown author]. Therefore confession
should be entire. Further, confession is a part of Penance. But Penance
should be entire. Therefore confession also should be entire.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, In prescribing medicine for the body, the physician
should know not only the disease for which he is prescribing, but also
the general constitution of the sick person, since one disease is
aggravated by the addition of another, and a medicine which would be
adapted to one disease, would be harmful to another. The same is to be
said in regard to sins, for one is aggravated when another is added to
it; and a remedy which would be suitable for one sin, might prove an
incentive to another, since sometimes a man is guilty of contrary sins,
as Gregory says (Pastoral. iii, 3). Hence it is necessary for confession
that man confess all the sins that he calls to mind, and if he fails to
do this, it is not a confession, but a pretense of confession.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Although a man's shame is multiplied when he makes a
divided confession to different confessors, yet all his different shames
together are not so great as that with which he confesses all his sins
together: because one sin considered by itself does not prove the evil
disposition of the sinner, as when it is considered in conjunction with
several others, for a man may fall into one sin through ignorance or
weakness, but a number of sins proves the malice of the sinner, or his
great corruption.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The punishment imposed by different priests would not be
sufficient, because each would only consider one sin by itself, and not
the gravity which it derives from being in conjunction with another.
Moreover sometimes the punishment which would be given for one sin would
foster another. Again the priest in hearing a confession takes the place
of God, so that confession should be made to him just as contrition is
made to God: wherefore as there would be no contrition unless one were
contrite for all the sins which one calls to mind, so is there no
confession unless one confess all the sins that one remembers committing.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Some say that when a man remembers a sin which he had
previously forgotten, he ought to confess again the sins which he had
confessed before, especially if he cannot go to the same priest to whom
his previous confession was made, in order that the total quantity of his
sins may be made known to one priest. But this does not seem necessary,
because sin takes its quantity both from itself and from the conjunction
of another; and as to the sins which he confessed he had already
manifested their quantity which they have of themselves, while as to the
sin which he had forgotten, in order that the priest may know the
quantity which it has under both the above heads, it is enough that the
penitent declare it explicitly, and confess the others in general, saying
that he had confessed many sins in his previous confession, but had
forgotten this particular one.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[2] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: Although the priest may be unable to absolve the penitent
from all his sins, yet the latter is bound to confess all to him, that he
may know the total quantity of his guilt, and refer him to the superior
with regard to the sins from which he cannot absolve him.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether one may confess through another, or by writing?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that one may confess through another, or by
writing. For confession is necessary in order that the penitent's
conscience may be made known to the priest. But a man can make his
conscience known to the priest, through another or by writing. Therefore
it is enough to confess through another or by writing.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, some are not understood by their own priests on account
of a difference of language, and consequently cannot confess save through
others. Therefore it is not essential to the sacrament that one should
confess by oneself, so that if anyone confesses through another in any
way whatever, it suffices for his salvation.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, it is essential to the sacrament that a man should
confess to his own priest, as appears from what has been said (Q[8], A[5]
). Now sometimes a man's own priest is absent, so that the penitent
cannot speak to him with his own voice. But he could make his conscience
known to him by writing. Therefore it seems that he ought to manifest his
conscience to him by writing to him.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[3] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, Man is bound to confess his sins even as he is bound to
confess his faith. But confession of faith should be made "with the
mouth," as appears from Rm. 10:10: therefore confession of sins should
also.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[3] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, who sinned by himself should, by himself, do penance. But
confession is part of penance. Therefore the penitent should confess his
own sins.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[3] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Confession is not only an act of virtue, but also part of
a sacrament. Now, though, in so far as it is an act of virtue it matters
not how it is done, even if it be easier to do it in one way than in
another, yet, in so far as it is part of a sacrament, it has a
determinate act, just as the other sacraments have a determinate matter.
And as in Baptism, in order to signify the inward washing, we employ that
element which is chiefly used in washing, so in the sacramental act which
is intended for manifestation we generally make use of that act which is
most commonly employed for the purpose of manifestation, viz. our own
words; for other ways have been introduced as supplementary to this.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Just as in Baptism it is not enough to wash with anything,
but it is necessary to wash with a determinate element, so neither does
it suffice, in Penance, to manifest one's sins anyhow, but they must be
declared by a determinate act.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: It is enough for one who is ignorant of a language, to
confess by writing, or by signs, or by an interpreter, because a man is
not bound to do more than he can: although a man is not able or obliged
to receive Baptism, except with water, which is from an entirely external
source and is applied to us by another: whereas the act of confession is
from within and is performed by ourselves, so that when we cannot confess
in one way, we must confess as we can.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: In the absence of one's own priest, confession may be made
even to a layman, so that there is no necessity to confess in writing,
because the act of confession is more essential than the person to whom
confession is made.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the sixteen conditions usually assigned are necessary for
confession?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the conditions assigned by masters, and
contained in the following lines, are not requisite for confession:
Simple, humble, pure, faithful,
Frequent, undisguised, discreet, voluntary,
shamefaced,
Entire, secret, tearful, not delayed,
Courageously accusing, ready to obey.
For fidelity, simplicity, and courage are virtues by themselves, and
therefore should not be reckoned as conditions of confession.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, a thing is "pure" when it is not mixed with anything
else: and "simplicity," in like manner, removes composition and
admixture. Therefore one or the other is superfluous.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[4] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, no one is bound to confess more than once a sin which he
has committed but once. Therefore if a man does not commit a sin again,
his penance need not be "frequent."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[4] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, confession is directed to satisfaction. But satisfaction
is sometimes public. Therefore confession should not always be "secret."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[4] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, that which is not in our power is not required of us.
But it is not in our power to shed "tears." Therefore it is not required
of those who confess.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[4] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, We have the authority of the masters who assigned the
above.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[4] Body Para. 1/5
I answer that, Some of the above conditions are essential to confession,
and some are requisite for its well-being. Now those things which are
essential to confession belong to it either as to an act of virtue, or as
to part of a sacrament. If in the first way, it is either by reason of
virtue in general, or by reason of the special virtue of which it is the
act, or by reason of the act itself. Now there are four conditions of
virtue in general, as stated in Ethic. ii, 4. The first is knowledge, in
respect of which confession is said to be "discreet," inasmuch as
prudence is required in every act of virtue: and this discretion consists
in giving greater weight to greater sins. The second condition is choice,
because acts of virtue should be voluntary, and in this respect
confession is said to be "voluntary." The third condition is that the
act be done for a particular purpose, viz. the due end, and in this
respect confession is said to be "pure," i.e. with a right intention. The
fourth condition is that one should act immovably, and in this respect it
is said that confession should be "courageous," viz. that the truth
should not be forsaken through shame.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[4] Body Para. 2/5
Now confession is an act of the virtue of penance. First of all it takes
its origin in the horror which one conceives for the shamefulness of sin,
and in this respect confession should be "full of shame," so as not to be
a boastful account of one's sins, by reason of some worldly vanity
accompanying it. Then it goes on to deplore the sin committed, and in
this respect it is said to be "tearful." Thirdly, it culminates in
self-abjection, and in this respect it should be "humble," so that one
confesses one's misery and weakness.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[4] Body Para. 3/5
By reason of its very nature, viz. confession, this act is one of
manifestation: which manifestation can be hindered by four things: first,
by falsehood, and in this respect confession is said to be "faithful,"
i.e. true. Secondly, by the use of vague words, and against this
confession is said to be "open," so as not to be wrapped up in vague
words; thirdly, by "multiplicity" of words, in which respect it is said
to be "simple" indicating that the penitent should relate only such
matters as affect the gravity of the sin; fourthly none of those things
should be suppressed which should be made known, and in this respect
confession should be "entire."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[4] Body Para. 4/5
In so far as confession is part of a sacrament it is subject to the
judgment of the priest who is the minister of the sacrament. Wherefore it
should be an "accusation" on the part of the penitent, should manifest
his "readiness to obey" the priest, should be "secret" as regards the
nature of the court wherein the hidden affairs of conscience are tried.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[4] Body Para. 5/5
The well-being of confession requires that it should be "frequent"; and
"not delayed," i.e. that the sinner should confess at once.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: There is nothing unreasonable in one virtue being a
condition of the act of another virtue, through this act being commanded
by that virtue; or through the mean which belongs to one virtue
principally, belonging to other virtues by participation.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The condition "pure" excludes perversity of intention, from
which man is cleansed: but the condition "simple" excludes the
introduction of unnecessary matter.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[4] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: This is not necessary for confession, but is a condition of
its well-being.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[4] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: Confession should be made not publicly but privately, lest
others be scandalized, and led to do evil through hearing the sins
confessed. On the other hand, the penance enjoined in satisfaction does
not give rise to scandal, since like works of satisfaction are done
sometimes for slight sins, and sometimes for none at all.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[9] A[4] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: We must understand this to refer to tears of the heart.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[10] Out. Para. 1/1
OF THE EFFECT OF CONFESSION (FIVE ARTICLES)
We must now consider the effect of confession: under which head there
are five points of inquiry:
(1) Whether confession delivers one from the death of sin?
(2) Whether confession delivers one in any way from punishment?
(3) Whether confession opens Paradise to us?
(4) Whether confession gives hope of salvation?
(5) Whether a general confession blots out mortal sins that one has
forgotten?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[10] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether confession delivers one from the death of sin?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[10] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that confession does not deliver one from the death
of sin. For confession follows contrition. But contrition sufficiently
blots out guilt. Therefore confession does not deliver one from the death
of sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[10] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, just as mortal sin is a fault, so is venial. Now
confession renders venial that which was mortal before, as stated in the
text (Sent. iv, D, 17). Therefore confession does not blot out guilt, but
one guilt is changed into another.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[10] A[1] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, Confession is part of the sacrament of Penance. But
Penance deliver from guilt. Therefore confession does also.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[10] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Penance, as a sacrament, is perfected chiefly in
confession, because by the latter a man submits to the ministers of the
Church, who are the dispensers of the sacraments: for contrition has the
desire of confession united thereto, and satisfaction is enjoined
according to the judgment of the priest who hears the confession. And
since in the sacrament of Penance, as in Baptism, that grace is infused
whereby sins are forgiven, therefore confession in virtue of the
absolution granted remits guilt, even as Baptism does. Now Baptism
delivers one from the death of sin, not only by being received actually,
but also by being received in desire, as is evident with regard to those
who approach the sacrament of Baptism after being already sanctified. And
unless a man offers an obstacle, he receives, through the very fact of
being baptized, grace whereby his sins are remitted, if they are not
already remitted. The same is to be said of confession, to which
absolution is added because it delivered the penitent from guilt through
being previously in his desire. Afterwards at the time of actual
confession and absolution he receives an increase of grace, and
forgiveness of sins would also be granted to him, if his previous sorrow
for sin was not sufficient for contrition, and if at the time he offered
no obstacle to grace. Consequently just as it is said of Baptism that it
delivers from death, so can it be said of confession.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[10] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Contrition has the desire of confession attached to it, and
therefore it delivers penitents from death in the same way as the desire
of Baptism delivers those who are going to be baptized.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[10] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: In the text venial does not designate guilt, but punishment
that is easily expiated. and so it does not follow that one guilt is
changed into another but that it is wholly done away. For "venial" is
taken in three senses [*Cf. FS, Q[88], A[2]]: first, for what is venial
generically, e.g. an idle word: secondly, for what is venial in its
cause, i.e. having within itself a motive of pardon, e.g. sins due to
weakness: thirdly, for what is venial in the result, in which sense it is
understood here, because the result of confession is that man's past
guilt is pardoned.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[10] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether confession delivers from punishment in some way?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[10] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that confession nowise delivers from punishment.
For sin deserves no punishment but what is either eternal or temporal.
Now eternal punishment is remitted by contrition, and temporal punishment
by satisfaction. Therefore nothing of the punishment is remitted by
confession.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[10] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, "the will is taken for the deed" [*Cf. Can. Magna
Pietas, De Poenit., Dist. i], as stated in the text (Sent. iv, D, 17).
Now he that is contrite has the intention to confess. wherefore his
intention avails him as though he had already confessed, and so the
confession which he makes afterwards remits no part of the punishment.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[10] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, Confession is a penal work. But all penal works expiate
the punishment due to sin. Therefore confession does also.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[10] A[2] Body Para. 1/2
I answer that, Confession together with absolution has the power to
deliver from punishment, for two reasons. First, from the power of
absolution itself: and thus the very desire of absolution delivers a man
from eternal punishment, as also from the guilt. Now this punishment is
one of condemnation and total banishment: and when a man is delivered
therefrom he still remains bound to a temporal punishment, in so far as
punishment is a cleansing and perfecting remedy; and so this punishment
remains to be suffered in Purgatory by those who also have been delivered
from the punishment of hell. Which temporal punishment is beyond the
powers of the penitent dwelling in this world, but is so far diminished
by the power of the keys, that it is within the ability of the penitent,
and he is able, by making satisfaction, to cleanse himself in this life.
Secondly, confession diminishes the punishment in virtue of the very
nature of the act of the one who confesses, for this act has the
punishment of shame attached to it, so that the oftener one confesses the
same sins, the more is the punishment diminished.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[10] A[2] Body Para. 2/2
This suffices for the Reply to the First Objection.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[10] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The will is not taken for the deed, if this is done by
another, as in the case of Baptism: for the will to receive Baptism is
not worth as much as the reception of Baptism. But a man's will is taken
for the deed, when the latter is something done by him, entirely. Again,
this is true of the essential reward, but not of the removal of
punishment and the like, which come under the head of accidental and
secondary reward. Consequently one who has confessed and received
absolution will be less punished in Purgatory than one who has gone no
further than contrition.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[10] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether confession opens paradise?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[10] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that confession does not open Paradise. For
different sacraments have different effects. But it is the effect of
Baptism to open Paradise. Therefore it is not the effect of confession.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[10] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, it is impossible to enter by a closed door before it be
opened. But a dying man can enter heaven before making his confession.
Therefore confession does not open Paradise.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[10] A[3] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, Confession makes a man submit to the keys of the
Church. But Paradise is opened by those keys. Therefore it is opened by
confession.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[10] A[3] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Guilt and the debt of punishment prevent a man from
entering into Paradise: and since confession removes these obstacles, as
shown above (AA[1],2), it is said to open Paradise.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[10] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Although Baptism and Penance are different sacraments, they
act in virtue of Christ's one Passion, whereby a way was opened unto
Paradise.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[10] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: If the dying man was in mortal sin Paradise was closed to
him before he conceived the desire to confess his sin, although
afterwards it was opened by contrition implying a desire for confession,
even before he actually confessed. Nevertheless the obstacle of the debt
of punishment was not entirely removed before confession and satisfaction.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[10] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether confession gives hope of salvation?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[10] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that hope of salvation should not be reckoned an
effect of confession. For hope arises from all meritorious acts.
Therefore, seemingly, it is not the proper effect of confession.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[10] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, we arrive at hope through tribulation, as appears from
Rm. 5:3,4. Now man suffers tribulation chiefly in satisfaction.
Therefore, satisfaction rather than confession gives hope of salvation.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[10] A[4] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary," Confession makes a man more humble and more wary," as
the Master states in the text (Sent. iv, D, 17). But the result of this
is that man conceives a hope of salvation. Therefore it is the effect of
confession to give hope of salvation.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[10] A[4] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, We can have no hope for the forgiveness of our sins
except through Christ: and since by confession a man submits to the keys
of the Church which derive their power from Christ's Passion, therefore
do we say that confession gives hope of salvation.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[10] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: It is not our actions, but the grace of our Redeemer, that
is the principal cause of the hope of salvation: and since confession
relies upon the grace of our Redeemer, it gives hope of salvation, not
only as a meritorious act, but also as part of a sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[10] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Tribulation gives hope of salvation, by making us exercise
our own virtue, and by paying off the debt of punishment: while
confession does so also in the way mentioned above.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[10] A[5] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether a general confession suffices to blot out forgotten mortal sins?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[10] A[5] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that a general confession does not suffice to blot
out forgotten mortal sins. For there is no necessity to confess again a
sin which has been blotted out by confession. If, therefore, forgotten
sins were forgiven by a general confession, there would be no need to
confess them when they are called to mind.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[10] A[5] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, whoever is not conscious of sin, either is not guilty of
sin, or has forgotten his sin. If, therefore, mortal sins are forgiven by
a general confession, whoever is not conscious of a mortal sin, can be
certain that he is free from mortal sin, whenever he makes a general
confession: which is contrary to what the Apostle says (1 Cor. 4:4), "I
am not conscious to myself of anything, yet am I not hereby justified."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[10] A[5] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, no man profits by neglect. Now a man cannot forget a
mortal sin without neglect, before it is forgiven him. Therefore he does
not profit by his forgetfulness so that the sin is forgiven him without
special mention thereof in confession.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[10] A[5] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, that which the penitent knows nothing about is further
from his knowledge than that which he has forgotten. Now a general
confession does not blot out sins committed through ignorance, else
heretics, who are not aware that certain things they have done are
sinful, and certain simple people, would be absolved by a general
confession, which is false. Therefore a general confession does not take
away forgotten sins.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[10] A[5] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, It is written (Ps. 33:6): "Come ye to Him and be
enlightened, and your faces shall not be confounded." Now he who
confesses all the sins of which he is conscious, approaches to God as
much as he can: nor can more be required for him. Therefore he will not
be confounded by being repelled, but will be forgiven.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[10] A[5] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, he that confesses is pardoned unless he be insincere. But he
who confesses all the sins that he calls to mind, is not insincere
through forgetting some, because he suffers from ignorance of fact, which
excuses from sin. Therefore he receives forgiveness, and then the sins
which he has forgotten, are loosened, since it is wicked to hope for half
a pardon.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[10] A[5] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Confession produces its effect, on the presupposition
that there is contrition which blots out guilt: so that confession is
directly ordained to the remission of punishment, which it causes in
virtue of the shame which it includes, and by the power of the keys to
which a man submits by confessing. Now it happens sometimes that by
previous contrition a sin has been blotted out as to the guilt, either in
a general way (if it was not remembered at the time) or in particular
(and yet is forgotten before confession): and then general sacramental
confession works for the remission of the punishment in virtue of the
keys, to which man submits by confessing, provided he offers no obstacle
so far as he is concerned: but so far as the shame of confessing a sin
diminishes its punishment, the punishment for the sin for which a man
does not express his shame, through failing to confess it to the priest,
is not diminished.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[10] A[5] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: In sacramental confession, not only is absolution required,
but also the judgment of the priest who imposes satisfaction is awaited.
Wherefore although the latter has given absolution, nevertheless the
penitent is bound to confess in order to supply what was wanting to the
sacramental confession.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[10] A[5] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: As stated above, confession does not produce its effect,
unless contrition be presupposed; concerning which no man can know
whether it be true contrition, even as neither can one know for certain
if he has grace. Consequently a man cannot know for certain whether a
forgotten sin has been forgiven him in a general confession, although he
may think so on account of certain conjectural signs.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[10] A[5] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: He does not profit by his neglect, since he does not
receive such full pardon, as he would otherwise have received, nor is his
merit so great. Moreover he is bound to confess the sin when he calls it
to mind.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[10] A[5] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: Ignorance of the law does not excuse, because it is a sin
by itself: but ignorance of fact does excuse. Therefore if a man omits to
confess a sin, because he does not know it to be a sin, through ignorance
of the Divine law, he is not excused from insincerity. on the other hand,
he would be excused, if he did not know it to be a sin, through being
unaware of some particular circumstance, for instance, if he had
knowledge of another's wife, thinking her his own. Now forgetfulness of
an act of sin comes under the head of ignorance of fact, wherefore it
excuses from the sin of insincerity in confession, which is an obstacle
to the fruit of absolution and confession.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] Out. Para. 1/1
OF THE SEAL OF CONFESSION (FIVE ARTICLES)
We must now inquire about the seal of confession, about which there are
five points of inquiry:
(1) Whether in every case a man is bound to hide what he knows under the
seal of confession?
(2) Whether the seal of confession extends to other matters than those
which have reference to confession?
(3) Whether the priest alone is bound by the seal of confession?
(4) Whether, by permission of the penitent, the priest can make known to
another, a sin of his which he knew under the seal of confession?
(5) Whether he is bound to hide even what he knows through other sources
besides?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether in every case the priest is bound to hide the sins which he knows
under the seal of confession?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the priest is not bound in every case to hide
the sins which he knows under the seal of confession. For, as Bernard
says (De Proecep. et Dispens. ii), "that which is instituted for the sake
of charity does not militate against charity." Now the secret of
confession would militate against charity in certain cases: for instance,
if a man knew through confession that a certain man was a heretic, whom
he cannot persuade to desist from misleading the people; or, in like
manner, if a man knew, through confession, that certain people who wish
to marry are related to one another. Therefore such ought to reveal what
they know through confession.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, that which is obligatory solely on account of a precept
of the Church need not be observed, if the commandment be changed to the
contrary. Now the secret of confession was introduced solely by a precept
of the Church. If therefore the Church were to prescribe that anyone who
knows anything about such and such a sin must make it known, a man that
had such knowledge through confession would be bound to speak.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, a man is bound to safeguard his conscience rather than
the good name of another, because there is order in charity. Now it
happens sometimes that a man by hiding a sin injures his own
conscience---for instance, if he be called upon to give witness of a sin
of which he has knowledge through confession, and is forced to swear to
tell the truth---or when an abbot knows through confession the sin of a
prior who is subject to him, which sin would be an occasion of ruin to
the latter, if he suffers him to retain his priorship, wherefore he is
bound to deprive him of the dignity of his pastoral charge, and yet in
depriving him he seem to divulge the secret of confession. Therefore it
seems that in certain cases it is lawful to reveal a confession.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[1] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, it is possible for a priest through hearing a man's
confession to be conscious that the latter is unworthy of ecclesiastical
preferment. Now everyone is bound to prevent the promotion of the
unworthy, if it is his business. Since then by raising an objection he
seems to raise a suspicion of sin, and so to reveal the confession
somewhat, it seems that it is necessary sometimes to divulge a confession.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[1] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, The Decretal says (De Poenit. et Remiss., Cap. Omnis
utriusque): "Let the priest beware lest he betray the sinner, by word, or
sign, or in any other way whatever."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[1] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, the priest should conform himself to God, Whose minister he is.
But God does not reveal the sins which are made known to Him in
confession, but hides them. Neither, therefore, should the priest reveal
them.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Those things which are done outwardly in the sacraments
are the signs of what takes place inwardly: wherefore confession, whereby
a man subjects himself to a priest, is a sign of the inward submission,
whereby one submits to God. Now God hides the sins of those who submit to
Him by Penance; wherefore this also should be signified in the sacrament
of Penance, and consequently the sacrament demands that the confession
should remain hidden, and he who divulges a confession sins by violating
the sacrament. Besides this there are other advantages in this secrecy,
because thereby men are more attracted to confession, and confess their
sins with greater simplicity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Some say that the priest is not bound by the seal of
confession to hide other sins than those in respect of which the penitent
promises amendment; otherwise he may reveal them to one who can be a help
and not a hindrance. But this opinion seems erroneous, since it is
contrary to the truth of the sacrament; for just as, though the person
baptized be insincere, yet his Baptism is a sacrament, and there is no
change in the essentials of the sacrament on that account, so confession
does not cease to be sacramental although he that confesses, does not
purpose amendment. Therefore, this notwithstanding, it must be held
secret; nor does the seal of confession militate against charity on that
account, because charity does not require a man to find a remedy for a
sin which he knows not: and that which is known in confession, is, as it
were, unknown, since a man knows it, not as man, but as God knows it.
Nevertheless in the cases quoted one should apply some kind of remedy, so
far as this can be done without divulging the confession, e.g. by
admonishing the penitent, and by watching over the others lest they be
corrupted by heresy. He can also tell the prelate to watch over his flock
with great care, yet so as by neither word nor sign to betray the
penitent.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The precept concerning the secret of confession follows
from the sacrament itself. Wherefore just as the obligation of making a
sacramental confession is of Divine law, so that no human dispensation or
command can absolve one therefrom, even so, no man can be forced or
permitted by another man to divulge the secret of confession.
Consequently if he be commanded under pain of excommunication to be
incurred "ipso facto," to say whether he knows anything about such and
such a sin, he ought not to say it, because he should assume that the
intention of the person in commanding him thus, was that he should say
what he knew as man. And even if he were expressly interrogated about a
confession, he ought to say nothing, nor would he incur the
excommunication, for he is not subject to his superior, save as a man,
and he knows this not as a man, but as God knows it.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: A man is not called upon to witness except as a man,
wherefore without wronging his conscience he can swear that he knows not,
what he knows only as God knows it. In like manner a superior can,
without wronging his conscience, leave a sin unpunished which he knows
only as God knows it, or he may forbear to apply a remedy, since he is
not bound to apply a remedy, except according as it comes to his
knowledge. Wherefore with regard to matters which come to his knowledge
in the tribunal of Penance, he should apply the remedy, as far as he can,
in the same court: thus as to the case in point, the abbot should advise
the prior to resign his office, and if the latter refuse, he can absolve
him from the priorship on some other occasion, yet so as to avoid all
suspicion of divulging the confession.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[1] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: A man is rendered unworthy of ecclesiastical preferment, by
many other causes besides sin, for instance, by lack of knowledge, age,
or the like: so that by raising an objection one does not raise a
suspicion of crime or divulge the secret of confession.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the seal of confession extends to other matters than those which
have reference to confession?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the seal of confession extends to other
matters besides those which have reference to confession. For sins alone
have reference to confession. Now sometimes besides sins other matters
are told which have no reference to confession. Therefore, since such
things are told to the priest, as to God, it seems that the seal of
confession extends to them also.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, sometimes one person tells another a secret, which the
latter receives under the seal of confession. Therefore the seal of
confession extends to matters having no relation to confession.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, The seal of confession is connected with sacramental
confession. But those things which are connected with a sacrament, do not
extend outside the bounds of the sacrament. Therefore the seal of
confession does not extend to matters other than those which have
reference to sacramental confession.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[2] Body Para. 1/2
I answer that, The seal of confession does not extend directly to other
matters than those which have reference to sacramental confession, yet
indirectly matters also which are not connected with sacramental
confession are affected by the seal of confession, those, for instance,
which might lead to the discovery of a sinner or of his sin. Nevertheless
these matters also must be most carefully hidden, both on account of
scandal, and to avoid leading others into sin through their becoming
familiar with it.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[2] Body Para. 2/2
This suffices for the Reply to the First Objection.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: A confidence ought not easily to be accepted in this way:
but if it be done the secret must be kept in the way promised, as though
one had the secret through confession, though not through the seal of
confession.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the priest alone is bound by the seal of confession?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that not only the priest is bound by the seal of
confession. For sometimes a priest hears a confession through an
interpreter, if there be an urgent reason for so doing. But it seems that
the interpreter is bound to keep the confession secret. Therefore one who
is not a priest knows something under the seal of confession.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, it is possible sometimes in cases of urgency for a
layman to hear a confession. But he is bound to secrecy with regard to
those sins, since they are told to him as to God. Therefore not only the
priest is bound by the seal of confession.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, it may happen that a man pretends to be a priest, so
that by this deceit he may know what is on another's conscience: and it
would seem that he also sins if he divulges the confession. Therefore not
only the priest is bound by the seal of confession.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[3] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, A priest alone is the minister of this sacrament. But
the seal of confession is connected with this sacrament. Therefore the
priest alone is bound by the seal of confession.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[3] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, the reason why a man is bound to keep secret what he hears in
confession, is because he knows them, not as man but as God knows them.
But the priest alone is God's minister. Therefore he alone is bound to
secrecy.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[3] Body Para. 1/2
I answer that, The seal of confession affects the priest as minister of
this sacrament: which seal is nothing else than the obligation of keeping
the confession secret, even as the key is the power of absolving. Yet, as
one who is not a priest, in a particular case has a kind of share in the
act of the keys, when he hears a confession in a case of urgency, so also
does he have a certain share in the act of the seal of confession, and is
bound to secrecy, though, properly speaking, he is not bound by the seal
of confession.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[3] Body Para. 2/2
This suffices for the Replies to the Objections.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether by the penitent's permission, a priest may reveal to another a
sin which he knows under the seal of confession?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that a priest may not, by the penitent's
permission, reveal to another a sin which he knows under the seal of
confession. For an inferior may not do what his superior may not. Now the
Pope cannot give permission for anyone to divulge a sin which he knows
through confession. Neither therefore can the penitent give him such a
permission.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, that which is instituted for the common good of the
Church cannot be changed at the will of an individual. Now the secrecy of
confession was instituted for the good of the whole Church, in order that
men might have greater confidence in approaching the confessional.
Therefore the penitent cannot allow the priest to divulge his confession.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[4] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, if the priest could grant such a permission, this would
seem to palliate the wickedness of bad priests, for they might pretend to
have received the permission and so they might sin with impunity, which
would be unbecoming. Therefore it seems that the penitent cannot grant
this permission.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[4] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, the one to whom this sin is divulged does not know that
sin under the seal of confession, so that he may publish a sin which is
already blotted out, which is unbecoming. Therefore this permission
cannot be granted.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[4] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, If the sinner consent, a superior may refer him by
letter to an inferior priest. Therefore with the consent of the penitent,
the priest may reveal a sin of his to another.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[4] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, whosoever can do a thing of his own authority, can do it
through another. But the penitent can by his own authority reveal his sin
to another. Therefore he can do it through the priest.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[4] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that There are two reasons for which the priest is bound to
keep a sin secret: first and chiefly, because this very secrecy is
essential to the sacrament, in so far as the priest knows that sin, as it
is known to God, Whose place he holds in confession: secondly, in order
to avoid scandal. Now the penitent can make the priest know, as a man,
what he knew before only as God knows it, and he does this when he allows
him to divulge it: so that if the priest does reveal it, he does not
break the seal of confession. Nevertheless he should beware of giving
scandal by revealing the sin, lest he be deemed to have broken the seal.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The Pope cannot permit a priest to divulge a sin, because
he cannot make him to know it as a man, whereas he that has confessed it,
can.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: When that is told which was known through another source,
that which is instituted for the common good is not done away with,
because the seal of confession is not broken.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[4] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: This does not bestow impunity on wicked priests, because
they are in danger of having to prove that they had the penitent's
permission to reveal the sin, if they should be accused of the contrary.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[4] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: He that is informed of a sin through the priest with the
penitent's consent, shares in an act of the priest's, so that the same
applies to him as to an interpreter, unless perchance the penitent wish
him to know it unconditionally and freely.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[5] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether a man may reveal that which he knows through confession and
through some other source besides?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[5] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that a man may not reveal what he knows through
confession and through some other source besides. For the seal of
confession is not broken unless one reveals a sin known through
confession. If therefore a man divulges a sin which he knows through
confession, no matter how he knows it otherwise, he seems to break the
seal.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[5] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, whoever hears someone's confession, is under obligation
to him not to divulge his sins. Now if one were to promise someone to
keep something secret, he would be bound to do so, even if he knew it
through some other source. Therefore a man is bound to keep secret what
he knows through the confession, no matter how he knows it otherwise.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[5] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, the stronger of two things draws the other to itself.
Now the knowledge whereby a man knows a sin as God knows it, is stronger
and more excellent than the knowledge whereby he knows a sin as man.
Therefore it draws the latter to itself: and consequently a man cannot
reveal that sin, because this is demanded by his knowing it as God knows
it.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[5] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, the secrecy of confession was instituted in order to
avoid scandal, and to prevent men being shy of going to confession. But
if a man might say what he had heard in confession, though he knew it
otherwise, scandal would result all the same. Therefore he can nowise say
what he has heard.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[5] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, No one can put another under a new obligation, unless
he be his superior, who can bind him by a precept. Now he who knew of a
sin by witnessing it was not bound to keep it secret. Therefore he that
confesses to him, not being his superior, cannot put him under an
obligation of secrecy by confessing to him.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[5] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, the justice of the Church would be hindered if a man, in order
to escape a sentence of excommunication, incurred on account of some sin,
of which he has been convicted, were to confess to the person who has to
sentence him. Now the execution of justice falls under a precept.
Therefore a man is not bound to keep a sin secret, which he has heard in
confession, but knows from some other source.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[5] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, There are three opinions about this question. For some
say that a man can by no means tell another what he has heard in
confession, even if he knew it from some other source either before or
after the confession: while others assert that the confession debars him
from speaking of what he knew already, but not from saying what he knew
afterwards and in another way. Now both these opinions, by exaggerating
the seal of confession, are prejudicial to the truth and to the
safeguarding of justice. For a man might be more inclined to sin, if he
had no fear of being accused by his confessor supposing that he repeated
the sin in his presence: and furthermore it would be most prejudicial to
justice if a man could not bear witness to a deed which he has seen
committed again after being confessed to him. Nor does it matter that, as
some say, he ought to declare that he cannot keep it secret, for he
cannot make such a declaration until the sin has already been confessed
to him, and then every priest could, if he wished, divulge a sin, by
making such a declaration, if this made him free to divulge it.
Consequently there is a third and truer opinion, viz. that what a man
knows through another source either before or after confession, he is not
bound to keep secret, in so far as he knows it as a man, for he can say:
"I know so end so since I saw it." But he is bound to keep it secret in
so far as he knows it as God knows it, for he cannot say: "I heard so and
so in confession." Nevertheless, on account of the scandal he should
refrain from speaking of it unless there is an urgent reason.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[5] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: If a man says that he has seen what he has heard in the
confessional, he does not reveal what he heard in confession, save
indirectly: even as one who knows something through hearing and seeing
it, does not, properly speaking, divulge what he saw, if he says he heard
it, but only indirectly, because he says he has heard what he
incidentally saw. Wherefore he does not break the seal of confession.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[5] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The confessor is not forbidden to reveal a sin simply, but
to reveal it as heard in confession: for in no case is he allowed to say
that he has heard it in the confessional.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[5] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: This is true of things that are in opposition to one
another: whereas to know a sin as God knows it, and to know it as man
knows it, are not in opposition; so that the argument proves nothing.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[11] A[5] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: It would not be right to avoid scandal so as to desert
justice: for the truth should not be gainsayed for fear of scandal.
Wherefore when justice and truth are in the balance, a man should not be
deterred by the fear of giving scandal, from divulging what he has heard
in confession, provided he knows it from some other source: although he
ought to avoid giving scandal, as far as he is able.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[12] Out. Para. 1/2
OF SATISFACTION, AS TO ITS NATURE (THREE ARTICLES)
We must now consider satisfaction; about which four things have to be
considered: (1) Its nature; (2) Its possibility; (3) Its quality; (4) The
means whereby man offers satisfaction to God.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[12] Out. Para. 2/2
Under the first head there are three points of inquiry:
(1) Whether satisfaction is a virtue or an act of virtue?
(2) Whether it is an act of justice?
(3) Whether the definition of satisfaction contained in the text is
suitable?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[12] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether satisfaction is a virtue or an act of virtue?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[12] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that satisfaction is neither a virtue nor an act of
virtue. For every act of virtue is meritorious; whereas, seemingly,
satisfaction is not, since merit is gratuitous, while satisfaction
answers to a debt. Therefore satisfaction is not an act of virtue.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[12] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, every act of virtue is voluntary. But sometimes a man
has to make satisfaction for something against his will, as when anyone
is punished by the judge for an offense against another. Therefore
satisfaction is not an act of virtue.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[12] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, according to the Philosopher (Ethic. viii, 13): "Choice
holds the chief place in moral virtue." But satisfaction is not an act of
choice but regards chiefly external works. Therefore it is not an act of
virtue.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[12] A[1] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, Satisfaction belongs to penance. Now penance is a
virtue. Therefore satisfaction is also an act of virtue.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[12] A[1] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, none but an act of virtue has the effect of blotting out sin,
for one contrary is destroyed by the other. Now satisfaction destroys
sin altogether. Therefore it is an act of virtue.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[12] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, An act is said to be the act of a virtue in two ways.
First, materially; and thus any act which implies no malice, or defect of
a due circumstance, may be called an act of virtue, because virtue can
make use of any such act for its end, e.g. to walk, to speak, and so
forth. Secondly, an act is said to belong to a virtue formally, because
its very name implies the form and nature of virtue; thus to suffer
courageously is an act of courage. Now the formal element in every moral
virtue is the observance of a mean. wherefore every act that implies the
observance of a mean is formally an act of virtue. And since equality is
the mean implied in the name of satisfaction (for a thing is said to be
satisfied by reason of an equal proportion to something), it is evident
that satisfaction also is formally an act of virtue.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[12] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Although to make satisfaction is due in itself, yet, in so
far as the deed is done voluntarily by the one who offers satisfaction,
it becomes something gratuitous on the part of the agent, so that he
makes a virtue of necessity. For debt diminishes merit through being
necessary and consequently against the will, so that if the will consent
to the necessity, the element of merit is not forfeited.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[12] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: An act of virtue demands voluntariness not in the patient
but in the agent, for it is his act. Consequently since he on whom the
judge wreaks vengeance is the patient and not the agent as regards
satisfaction, it follows that satisfaction should be voluntary not in him
but in the judge as agent.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[12] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: The chief element of virtue can be understood in two ways.
First, as being the chief element of virtue as virtue, and thus the chief
element of virtue denotes whatever belongs to the nature of virtue or is
most akin thereto; thus choice and other internal acts hold the chief
place in virtue. Secondly, the chief element of virtue may be taken as
denoting that which holds the first place in such and such a virtue; and
then the first place belongs to that which gives its determination. Now
the interior act, in certain virtues, is determined by some external act,
since choice, which is common to all virtues, becomes proper to such and
such a virtue through being directed to such and such an act. Thus it is
that external acts hold the chief place in certain virtues; and this is
the case with satisfaction.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[12] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether satisfaction is an act of justice?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[12] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that satisfaction is not an act of justice. Because
the purpose of satisfaction is that one may be reconciled to the person
offended. But reconciliation, being an act of love, belongs to charity.
Therefore satisfaction is an act of charity and not of justice.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[12] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the causes of sin in us are the passions of the soul,
which incline us to evil. But justice, according to the Philosopher
(Ethic. v, 2,3), is not about passions, but about operations. Since
therefore satisfaction aims at removing the causes of sin, as stated in
the text (Sent. iv, D, 15), it seems that it is not an act of justice.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[12] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, to be careful about the future is not an act of justice
but of prudence of which caution is a part. But it belongs to
satisfaction, "to give no opening to the suggestions of sin" [*Cf.
XP/Q[12]/A[3]/OBJ[1]]. Therefore satisfaction is not an act of justice.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[12] A[2] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, No virtue but justice considers the notion of that
which is due. But satisfaction gives due honor to God, as Anselm states
(Cur Deus Homo i). Therefore satisfaction is an act of justice.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[12] A[2] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, no virtue save justice establishes equality between external
things. But this is done by satisfaction which establishes equality
between amendment and the previous offense. Therefore satisfaction is an
act of justice.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[12] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, According to the Philosopher (Ethic. v, 3,4), the mean of
justice is considered with regard to an equation between thing and thing
according to a certain proportion. Wherefore, since the very name of
satisfaction implies an equation of the kind, because the adverb "satis"
[enough] denotes an equality of proportion, it is evident that
satisfaction is formally an act of justice. Now the act of justice,
according to the Philosopher (Ethic. v, 2,4), is either an act done by
one man to another, as when a man pays another what he owes him, or an
act done by one man between two others, as when a judge does justice
between two men. When it is an act of justice of one man to another, the
equality is set up in the agent, while when it is something done between
two others, the equality is set up in the subject that has suffered an
injustice. And since satisfaction expresses equality in the agent, it
denotes, properly speaking, an act of justice of one man to another. Now
a man may do justice to another either in actions and passions or in
external things; even as one may do an injustice to another, either by
taking something away, or by a hurtful action. And since to give is to
use an external thing, the act of justice, in so far as it establishes
equality between external things, signifies, properly speaking, a giving
back: but to make satisfaction clearly points to equality between
actions, although sometimes one is put for the other. Now equalization
concerns only such things as are unequal, wherefore satisfaction
presupposes inequality among actions, which inequality constitutes an
offense; so that satisfaction regards a previous offense. But no part of
justice regards a previous offense, except vindictive justice, which
establishes equality indifferently, whether the patient be the same
subject as the agent, as when anyone punishes himself, or whether they be
distinct, as when a judge punishes another man, since vindictive justice
deals with both cases. The same applies to penance, which implies
equality in the agent only, since it is the penitent who holds to the
penance [poenam tenet], so that penance is in a way a species of
vindictive justice. This proves that satisfaction, which implies equality
in the agent with respect to a previous offense, is a work of justice, as
to that part which is called penance.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[12] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Satisfaction, as appears from what has been said, is
compensation for injury inflicted. Wherefore as the injury inflicted
entailed of itself an inequality of justice, and consequently an
inequality opposed to friendship, so satisfaction brings back directly
equality of justice, and consequently equality of friendship. And since
an act is elicited by the habit to whose end it is immediately directed,
but is commanded by that habit to whose end it is directed ultimately,
hence satisfaction is elicited by justice but is commanded by charity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[12] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Although justice is chiefly about operations, yet it is
consequently about passions, in so far as they are the causes of
operations. Wherefore as justice curbs anger, lest it inflict an unjust
injury on another, and concupiscence from invading another's marriage
right, so satisfaction removes the causes of other sins.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[12] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Each moral virtue shares in the act of prudence, because
this virtue completes in it the conditions essential to virtue, since
each moral virtue takes its mean according to the ruling of prudence, as
is evident from the definition of virtue given in Ethic. ii, 6.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[12] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the definition of satisfaction given in the text is suitable?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[12] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the definition of satisfaction given in the
text (Sent. iv, D, 15) and quoted from Augustine [*Gennadius
Massiliensis, De Eccl. Dogm. liv] is unsuitable---viz. that "satisfaction
is to uproot the causes of sins, and to give no opening to the
suggestions thereof." For the cause of actual sin is the fomes. [*"Fomes"
signifies literally "fuel," and metaphorically, "incentive." As used by
the theologian, it denotes the quasi-material element and effect of
original sin, and sometimes goes under the name of "concupiscence," Cf.
FS, Q[82], A[3].] But we cannot remove the "fomes" in this life.
Therefore satisfaction does not consist in removing the causes of sins.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[12] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the cause of sin is stronger than sin itself. But man by
himself cannot remove sin. Much less therefore can he remove the cause of
sin; and so the same conclusion follows.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[12] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, since satisfaction is a part of Penance, it regards the
past and not the future. Now "to give no opening to the suggestions of
sin" regards the future. Therefore it should not be put in the definition
of satisfaction.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[12] A[3] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, satisfaction regards a past offense. Yet no mention is
made of this. Therefore the definition of satisfaction is unsuitable.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[12] A[3] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, Anselm gives another definition (Cur Deus homo i):
"Satisfaction consists in giving God due honor," wherein no reference is
made to the things mentioned by Augustine [*Gennadius, OBJ[1]] in this
definition. Therefore one or the other is unsuitable.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[12] A[3] Obj. 6 Para. 1/1
OBJ 6: Further, an innocent man can give due honor to God: whereas
satisfaction is not compatible with innocence. Therefore Anselm's
definition is faulty.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[12] A[3] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Justice aims not only at removing inequality already
existing, by punishing the past fault, but also at safeguarding equality
for the future, because according to the Philosopher (Ethic. ii, 3)
"punishments are medicinal." Wherefore satisfaction which is the act of
justice inflicting punishment, is a medicine healing past sins and
preserving from future sins: so that when one man makes satisfaction to
another, he offers compensation for the past, and takes heed for the
future. Accordingly satisfaction may be defined in two ways, first with
regard to past sin, which it heals by making compensation, and thus it is
defined as "compensation for an inflicted injury according to the
equality of justice." The definition of Anselm amounts to the same, for
he says that "satisfaction consists in giving God due honor"; where duty
is considered in respect of the sin committed. Secondly, satisfaction may
be defined, considered as preserving us from future sins; and as
Augustine (Cf. OBJ[1]) defines it. Now preservation from bodily sickness
is assured by removing the causes from which the sickness may ensue, for
if they be taken away the sickness cannot follow. But it is not thus in
spiritual diseases, for the free-will cannot be forced, so that even in
the presence of their causes, they can, though with difficulty, be
avoided, while they can be incurred even when their causes are removed.
Hence he puts two things in the definition of satisfaction, viz. removal
of the causes, as to the first, and the free-will's refusal to sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[12] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: By "causes" we must understand the proximate causes of
actual sin, which are twofold: viz. the lust of sin through the habit or
act of a sin that has been given up, and those things which are called
the remnants of past sin; and external occasions of sin, such as place,
bad company and so forth. Such causes are removed by satisfaction in this
life, albeit the "fomes," which is the remote cause of actual sin, is not
entirely removed by satisfaction in this life though it is weakened.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[12] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Since the cause of evil or of privation (according as it
has a cause) is nothing else than a defective good, and since it is
easier to destroy good than to set it up, it follows that it is easier to
uproot the causes of privation and of evil than to remove the evil
itself, which can only be removed by setting up good, as may be seen in
the case of blindness and its causes. Yet the aforesaid are not
sufficient causes of sin, for sin does not, of necessity, ensue
therefrom, but they are occasions of sin. Nor again can satisfaction be
made without God's help, since it is not possible without charity, as we
shall state further on (Q[14], A[2]).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[12] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Although Penance was primarily instituted and intended with
a view to the past, yet, as a consequence, it regards the future, in so
far as it is a safeguarding remedy; and the same applies to satisfaction.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[12] A[3] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: Augustine [*Gennadius Massiliensis, De Eccl. Dogm. liv]
defined satisfaction, as made to God, from Whom, in reality, nothing can
be taken, though the sinner, for his own part, takes something away.
Consequently in such like satisfaction, amendment for future time is of
greater weight than compensation for the past. Hence Augustine defines
satisfaction from this point of view. And yet it is possible to gauge the
compensation for the past from the heed taken for the future, for the
latter regards the same object as the former, but in the opposite way:
since when looking at the past we detest the causes of sins on account of
the sins themselves, which are the starting-point of the movement of
detestation: whereas when taking heed of the future, we begin from the
causes, that by their removal we may avoid sins the more easily.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[12] A[3] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: There is no reason why the same thing should not be
described in different ways according to the various things found in it:
and such is the case here, as explained above.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[12] A[3] R.O. 6 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 6: By debt is meant the debt we owe to God by reason of the
sins we have committed, because Penance regards a debt, as stated above
(A[2]).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[13] Out. Para. 1/1
OF THE POSSIBILITY OF SATISFACTION (TWO ARTICLES)
We must now consider the possibility of satisfaction, under which head
there are two points of inquiry:
(1) Whether man can make satisfaction to God?
(2) Whether one man can make satisfaction for another?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[13] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether man can make satisfaction to God?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[13] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that man cannot make satisfaction to God. For
satisfaction should balance the offense, as shown above (Q[12], AA[2],3).
But an offense against God is infinite, since it is measured by the
person against whom it is committed, for it is a greater offense to
strike a prince than anyone else. Therefore, as no action of man can be
infinite, it seems that he cannot make satisfaction to God.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[13] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, a slave cannot make compensation for a debt, since all
that he has is his master's. But we are the slaves of God, and whatever
good we have, we owe to Him. Therefore, as satisfaction is compensation
for a past offense, it seems that we cannot offer it to God.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[13] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, if all that a man has suffices not to pay one debt, he
cannot pay another debt. Now all that man is, all that he can do, and all
that he has, does not suffice to pay what he owes for the blessing of
creation, wherefore it is written (Is. 40:16) that "the wood of Libanus
shall not be enough for a burnt offering [*Vulg.: 'Libanus shall not be
enough to burn, nor the beasts thereof for a burnt offering']." Therefore
by no means can he make satisfaction for the debt resulting from the
offense committed.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[13] A[1] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, man is bound to spend all his time in the service of
God. Now time once lost cannot be recovered, wherefore, as Seneca
observes (Lib. i, Ep. i, ad Lucilium) loss of time is a very grievous
matter. Therefore man cannot make compensation to God, and the same
conclusion follows as before.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[13] A[1] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, mortal actual sin is more grievous than original sin.
But none could satisfy for original sin unless he were both God and man.
Neither, therefore, can he satisfy for actual sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[13] A[1] OTC Para. 1/3
On the contrary, Jerome [*Pelagius, Expos. Fidei ad Damasum] says:
"Whoever maintains that God has commanded anything impossible to man, let
him be anathema." But satisfaction is commanded (Lk. 3:8): "Bring forth .
. fruits worthy of penance." Therefore it is possible to make
satisfaction to God.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[13] A[1] OTC Para. 2/3
Further, God is more merciful than any man. But it is possible to make
satisfaction to a man. Therefore it is possible to make satisfaction to
God.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[13] A[1] OTC Para. 3/3
Further, there is due satisfaction when the punishment balances the
fault, since "justice is the same as counterpassion," as the Pythagoreans
said [*Aristotle, Ethic. v, 5; Cf. SS, Q[61], A[4]]. Now punishment may
equal the pleasure contained in a sin committed. Therefore satisfaction
can be made to God.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[13] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Man becomes God's debtor in two ways; first, by reason of
favors received, secondly, by reason of sin committed: and just as
thanksgiving or worship or the like regard the debt for favors received,
so satisfaction regards the debt for sin committed. Now in giving honor
to one's parents or to the gods, as indeed the Philosopher says (Ethic.
viii, 14), it is impossible to repay them measure for measure, but it
suffices that man repay as much as he can, for friendship does not demand
measure for measure, but what is possible. Yet even this is equal
somewhat, viz. according to proportion, for as the debt due to God is, in
comparison with God, so is what man can do, in comparison with himself,
so that in another way the form of justice is preserved. It is the same
as regards satisfaction. Consequently man cannot make satisfaction to God
if "satis" [enough] denotes quantitative equality; but he can, if it
denote proportionate equality, as explained above, and as this suffices
for justice, so does it suffice for satisfaction.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[13] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Just as the offense derived a certain infinity from the
infinity of the Divine majesty, so does satisfaction derive a certain
infinity from the infinity of Divine mercy, in so far as it is quickened
by grace, whereby whatever man is able to repay becomes acceptable.
Others, however, say that the offense is infinite as regards the
aversion, and in this respect it is pardoned gratuitously, but that it is
finite as turning to a mutable good, in which respect it is possible to
make satisfaction for it. But this is not to the point, since
satisfaction does not answer to sin, except as this is an offense against
God, which is a matter, not of turning to a creature but of turning away
from God. Others again say that even as regards the aversion it is
possible to make satisfaction for sin in virtue of Christ's merit, which
was, in a way, infinite. And this comes to the same as what we said
before, since grace is given to believers through faith in the Mediator.
If, however, He were to give grace otherwise, satisfaction would suffice
in the way explained above.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[13] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Man, who was made to God's image, has a certain share of
liberty, in so far as he is master of his actions through his free-will;
so that, through acting by his free-will, he can make satisfaction to
God, for though it belongs to God, in so far as it was bestowed on him by
God, yet it was freely bestowed on him, that he might be his own master,
which cannot be said of a slave.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[13] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: This argument proves that it is impossible to make
equivalent satisfaction to God, but not that it is impossible to make
sufficient satisfaction to Him. For though man owes God all that he is
able to give Him, yet it is not necessary for his salvation that he
should actually do the whole of what he is able to do, for it is
impossible for him, according to his present state of life, to put forth
his whole power into any one single thing, since he has to be heedful
about many things. And so his conduct is subject to a certain measure,
viz. the fulfillment of God's commandments, over and above which he can
offer something by way of satisfaction.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[13] A[1] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: Though man cannot recover the time that is past, he can in
the time that follows make compensation for what he should have done in
the past, since the commandment did not exact from him the fulfillment of
his whole power, as stated above (ad 3).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[13] A[1] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: Though original sin has less of the nature of sin than
actual sin has, yet it is a more grievous evil, because it is an
infection of human nature itself, so that, unlike actual sin, it could
not be expiated by the satisfaction of a mere man.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[13] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether one man can fulfill satisfactory punishment for another?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[13] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that one man cannot fulfill satisfactory punishment
for another. Because merit is requisite for satisfaction. Now one man
cannot merit or demerit for another, since it is written (Ps. 61:12):
"Thou wilt render to every man according to his works." Therefore one man
cannot make satisfaction for another.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[13] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, satisfaction is condivided with contrition and
confession. But one man cannot be contrite or confess for another.
Neither therefore can one make satisfaction for another.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[13] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, by praying for another one merits also for oneself. If
therefore a man can make satisfaction for another, he satisfies for
himself by satisfying for another, so that if a man satisfy for another
he need not make satisfaction for his own sins.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[13] A[2] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, if one can satisfy for another, as soon as he takes the
debt of punishment on himself, this other is freed from his debt.
Therefore the latter will go straight to heaven, if he die after the
whole of his debt of punishment has been taken up by another; else, if he
be punished all the same, a double punishment will be paid for the same
sin, viz. by him who has begun to make satisfaction, and by him who is
punished in Purgatory.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[13] A[2] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, It is written (Gal. 6:2): "Bear ye one another's
burdens." Therefore it seems that one can bear the burden of punishment
laid upon another.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[13] A[2] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, charity avails more before God than before man. Now before man,
one can pay another's debt for love of him. Much more, therefore, can
this be done before the judgment seat of God.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[13] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Satisfactory punishment has a twofold purpose, viz. to
pay the debt, and to serve as a remedy for the avoidance of sin.
Accordingly, as a remedy against future sin, the satisfaction of one does
not profit another, for the flesh of one man is not tamed by another's
fast; nor does one man acquire the habit of well-doing, through the
actions of another, except accidentally, in so far as a man, by his good
actions, may merit an increase of grace for another, since grace is the
most efficacious remedy for the avoidance of sin. But this is by way of
merit rather than of satisfaction. on the other hand, as regards the
payment of the debt, one man can satisfy for another, provided he be in a
state of charity, so that his works may avail for satisfaction. Nor is it
necessary that he who satisfies for another should undergo a greater
punishment than the principal would have to undergo (as some maintain,
who argue that a man profits more by his own punishment than by
another's), because punishment derives its power of satisfaction chiefly
from charity whereby man bears it. And since greater charity is evidenced
by a man satisfying for another than for himself, less punishment is
required of him who satisfies for another, than of the principal:
wherefore we read in the Lives of the Fathers (v, 5) of one who for love
of his brother did penance for a sin which his brother had not
committed, and that on account of his charity his brother was released
from a sin which he had committed. Nor is it necessary that the one for
whom satisfaction is made should be unable to make satisfaction himself,
for even if he were able, he would be released from his debt when the
other satisfied in his stead. But this is necessary in so far as the
satisfactory punishment is medicinal: so that a man is not to be allowed
to do penance for another, unless there be evidence of some defect in the
penitent, either bodily, so that he is unable to bear it, or spiritual,
so that he is not ready to undergo it.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[13] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The essential reward is bestowed on a man according to his
disposition, because the fulness of the sight of God will be according to
the capacity of those who see Him. Wherefore just as one man is not
disposed thereto by another's act, so one man does not merit the
essential reward for another, unless his merit has infinite efficacy, as
the merit of Christ, whereby children come to eternal life through
Baptism. On the other hand, the temporal punishment due to sin after the
guilt has been forgiven is not measured according to the disposition of
the man to whom it is due, since sometimes the better man owes a greater
debt of punishment. Consequently one man can merit for another as regards
release from punishment, and one man's act becomes another's, by means of
charity whereby we are "all one in Christ" (Gal. 3:28).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[13] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Contrition is ordained against the guilt which affects a
man's disposition to goodness or malice, so that one man is not freed
from guilt by another's contrition. In like manner by confession a man
submits to the sacraments of the Church: nor can one man receive a
sacrament instead of another, since in a sacrament grace is given to the
recipient, not to another. Consequently there is no comparison between
satisfaction and contrition and confession.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[13] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: In the payment of the debt we consider the measure of the
punishment, whereas in merit we regard the root which is charity:
wherefore he that, through charity, merits for another, at least
congruously, merits more for himself; yet he that satisfies for another
does not also satisfy for himself, because the measure of the punishment
does not suffice for the sins of both, although by satisfying for another
he merits something greater than the release from punishment, viz.
eternal life.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[13] A[2] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: If this man bound himself to undergo a certain punishment,
he would not be released from the debt before paying it: wherefore he
himself will suffer the punishment, as long as the other makes
satisfaction for him: and if he do not this, then both are debtors in
respect of fulfilling this punishment, one for the sin committed, the
other for his omission, so that it does not follow that one sin is twice
punished.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] Out. Para. 1/1
OF THE QUALITY OF SATISFACTION (FIVE ARTICLES)
We must now consider the quality of satisfaction, under which head there
are five points of inquiry:
(1) Whether a man can satisfy for one sin without satisfying for another?
(2) Whether if a man fall into sin after being contrite for all his
sins, he can, now that he has lost charity, satisfy for his other sins
which were pardoned him through his contrition?
(3) Whether a man's previous satisfaction begins to avail when he
recovers charity?
(4) Whether works done without charity merit any good?
(5) Whether such works avail for the mitigation of the pains of hell?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether a man can satisfy for one sin without satisfying for another?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that a man can satisfy for one sin without
satisfying for another. Because when several things are not connected
together one can be taken away without another. Now sins are not
connected together, else whoever had one would have them all. Therefore
one sin can be expiated by satisfaction, without another.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, God is more merciful than man. But man accepts the
payment of one debt without the payment of another. Therefore God accepts
satisfaction for one sin without the other.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, as stated in the text (Sent. iv, D, 15), "satisfaction
is to uproot the causes of sin, and give no opening to the suggestions
thereof." Now this can be done with regard to one sin and not another, as
when a mall curbs his lust and perseveres in covetousness. Therefore we
can make satisfaction for one sin without satisfying for another.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[1] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, The fast of those who fasted "for debates and strifes"
(Is. 58:4,5) was not acceptable to God, though fasting be a work of
satisfaction. Now satisfaction cannot be made save by works that are
acceptable to God. Therefore he that has a sin on his conscience cannot
make satisfaction to God.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[1] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, satisfaction is a remedy for the healing of past sins, and for
preserving from future sins, as stated above (Q[12], A[3]). But without
grace it is impossible to avoid sins. Therefore, since each sin excludes
grace, it is not possible to make satisfaction for one sin and not for
another.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Some have held that it is possible to make satisfaction
for one sin and not for another, as the Master states (Sent. iv, D, 15).
But this cannot be. For since the previous offense has to be removed by
satisfaction, the mode of satisfaction must needs be consistent with the
removal of the offense. Now removal of offense is renewal of friendship:
wherefore if there be anything to hinder the renewal of friendship there
can be no satisfaction. Since, therefore, every sin is a hindrance to
the friendship of charity, which is the friendship of man for God, it is
impossible for man to make satisfaction for one sin while holding to
another: even as neither would a man make satisfaction to another for a
blow, if while throwing himself at his feet he were to give him another.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: As sins are not connected together in some single one, a
man can incur one without incurring another; whereas all sins are
remitted by reason of one same thing, so that the remissions of various
sins are connected together. Consequently satisfaction cannot be made for
one and not for another.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: When a man is under obligation to another by reason of a
debt, the only inequality between them is that which is opposed to
justice, so that for restitution nothing further is required than that
the equality of justice should be reinstated, and this can be done in
respect of one debt without another. But when the obligation is based on
an offense, there is inequality not only of justice but also of
friendship, so that for the offense to be removed by satisfaction, not
only must the equality of justice be restored by the payment of a
punishment equal to the offense, but also the equality of friendship must
be reinstated, which is impossible so long as an obstacle to friendship
remains.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: By its weight, one sin drags us down to another, as Gregory
says (Moral. xxv): so that when a man holds to one sin, he does not
sufficiently cut himself off from the causes of further sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether, when deprived of charity, a man can make satisfaction for sins
for which he was previously contrite?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that if a man fall into sin after being contrite
for all his sins, he can, now that he has lost charity, satisfy for his
other sins which were already pardoned him through his contrition. For
Daniel said to Nabuchodonosor (Dan. 4:24): "Redeem thou thy sins with
alms." Yet he was still a sinner, as is shown by his subsequent
punishment. Therefore a man can make satisfaction while in a state of sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, "Man knoweth not whether he be worthy of love or hatred"
(Eccles. 9:1). If therefore one cannot make satisfaction unless one be in
a state of charity, it would be impossible to know whether one had made
satisfaction, which would be unseemly.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, a man's entire action takes its form from the intention
which he had at the beginning. But a penitent is in a state of charity
when he begins to repent. Therefore his whole subsequent satisfaction
will derive its efficacy from the charity which quickens his intention.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[2] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, satisfaction consists in a certain equalization of
guilt to punishment. But these things can be equalized even in one who is
devoid of charity. Therefore, etc.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[2] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, "Charity covereth all sins" (Prov. 10:12). But
satisfaction has the power of blotting out sins. Therefore it is
powerless without charity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[2] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, the chief work of satisfaction is almsdeeds. But alms given by
one who is devoid of charity avail nothing, as is clearly stated 1 Cor.
13:3, "If I should distribute all my goods to feed the poor . . . and
have not charity, it profiteth me nothing." Therefore there can be no
satisfaction with mortal sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[2] Body Para. 1/2
I answer that, Some have said that if, when all a man's sins have been
pardoned through contrition, and before he has made satisfaction for
them, he falls into sin, and then makes satisfaction, such satisfaction
will be valid, so that if he die in that sin, he will not be punished in
hell for the other sins.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[2] Body Para. 2/2
But this cannot be, because satisfaction requires the reinstatement of
friendship and the restoration of the equality of justice, the contrary
of which destroys friendship, as the Philosopher states (Ethic. ix, 1,3).
Now in satisfaction made to God, the equality is based, not on
equivalence but rather on God's acceptation: so that, although the
offense be already removed by previous contrition, the works of
satisfaction must be acceptable to God, and for this they are dependent
on charity. Consequently works done without charity are not satisfactory.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Daniel's advice meant that he should give up sin and
repent, and so make satisfaction by giving alms.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Even as man knows not for certain whether he had charity
when making satisfaction, or whether he has it now, so too he knows not
for certain whether he made full satisfaction: wherefore it is written
(Ecclus. 5:5): "Be not without fear about sin forgiven." And yet man need
not, on account of that fear, repeat the satisfaction made, if he is not
conscious of a mortal sin. For although he may not have expiated his
punishment by that satisfaction, he does not incur the guilt of omission
through neglecting to make satisfaction; even as he who receives the
Eucharist without being conscious of a mortal sin of which he is guilty,
does not incur the guilt of receiving unworthily.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: His intention was interrupted by his subsequent sin, so
that it gives no virtue to the works done after that sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[2] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: Sufficient equalization is impossible both as to the Divine
acceptation and as to equivalence: so that the argument proves nothing.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether previous satisfaction begins to avail after man is restored to
charity?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that when a man has recovered charity his previous
satisfaction begins to avail, because a gloss on Lev. 25:25, "If thy
brother being impoverished," etc., says that "the fruit of a man's good
works should be counted from the time when he sinned." But they would not
be counted, unless they derived some efficacy from his subsequent
charity. Therefore they begin to avail after he recovers charity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, as the efficacy of satisfaction is hindered by sin, so
the efficacy of Baptism is hindered by insincerity. Now Baptism begins to
avail when insincerity ceases. Therefore satisfaction begins to avail
when sin is taken away.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, if a man is given as a penance for the sins he has
committed, to fast for several days, and then, after falling again into
sin, he completes his penance, he is not told, when he goes to confession
a second time, to fast once again. But he would be told to do so, if he
did not fulfill his duty of satisfaction by them. Therefore his previous
works become valid unto satisfaction, through his subsequent repentance.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[3] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, Works done without charity were not satisfactory,
through being dead works. But they are not quickened by penance.
Therefore they do not begin to be satisfactory.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[3] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, charity does not quicken a work, unless in some way that work
proceeds therefrom. But works cannot be acceptable to God, and therefore
cannot be satisfactory, unless they be quickened by charity. Since then
the works done without charity, in no way proceeded from charity, nor
ever can proceed therefrom, they can by no means count towards
satisfaction.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[3] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Some have said that works done while in a state of
charity, which are called living works, are meritorious in respect of
eternal life, and satisfactory in respect of paying off the debt of
punishment; and that by subsequent charity, works done without charity
are quickened so as to be satisfactory, but not so as to be meritorious
of eternal life. But this is impossible, because works done in charity
produce both these effects for the same reason, viz. because they are
pleasing to God: wherefore just as charity by its advent cannot make
works done without charity to be pleasing in one respect, so neither can
it make them pleasing in the other respect.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: This means that the fruits are reckoned, not from the time
when he was first in sin, but from the time when he ceased to sin, when,
to wit, he was last in sin; unless he was contrite as soon as he had
sinned, and did many good actions before he confessed. Or we may say that
the greater the contrition the more it alleviates the punishment, and the
more good actions a man does while in sin, the more he disposes himself
to the grace of contrition, so that it is probable that he owes a smaller
debt of punishment. For this reason the priest should use discretion in
taking them into account, so as to give him a lighter penance, according
as he finds him better disposed.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Baptism imprints a character on the soul, whereas
satisfaction does not. Hence on the advent of charity, which removes both
insincerity and sin, it causes Baptism to have its effect, whereas it
does not do this for satisfaction. Moreover Baptism confers justification
in virtue of the deed [ex opere operato] which is not man's deed but
God's, wherefore it does not become a lifeless deed as satisfaction does,
which is a deed of man.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Sometimes satisfaction is such as to leave an effect in the
person who makes satisfaction, even after the act of satisfaction has
been done; thus fasting leaves the body weak, and almsdeeds result in a
diminution of a person's substance, and so on. In such cases there is no
need to repeat the works of satisfaction if they have been done while in
a state of sin, because through penance they are acceptable to God in the
result they leave behind. But when a work of satisfaction leaves behind
no effect in the person that does satisfaction, it needs to be repeated,
as in the case of prayer and so forth. Interior works, since they pass
away altogether, are nowise quickened, and must be repeated.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether works done without charity merit any, at least temporal, good?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that works done without charity merit some, at
least a temporal, good. For as punishment is to the evil act, so is
reward to a good act. Now no evil deed is unpunished by God the just
judge. Therefore no good deed is unrewarded, and so every good deed
merits some good.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, reward is not given except for merit. Now some reward is
given for works done without charity, wherefore it is written (Mt.
6:2,5,16) of those who do good actions for the sake of human glory, that
"they have received their reward." Therefore those works merit some good.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[4] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, if there be two men both in sin, one of whom does many
deeds that are good in themselves and in their circumstances, while the
other does none, they are not equally near to the reception of good
things from Gods else the latter need not be advised to do any good
deeds. Now he that is nearer to God receives more of His good things.
Therefore the former, on account of his good works, merits some good from
God.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[4] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, Augustine says that "the sinner is not worthy of the
bread he eats." Therefore he cannot merit anything from God.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[4] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, he that is nothing, can merit nothing. But a sinner, through
not having charity, is nothing in respect of spiritual being, according
to 1 Cor. 13:2. Therefore he can merit nothing.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[4] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Properly speaking a merit is an action on account of
which it is just that the agent should be given something. Now justice is
twofold: first, there is justice properly so called, which regards
something due on the part of the recipient. Secondly, there is
metaphorical justice, so to speak, which regards something due on the
part of the giver, for it may be right for the giver to give something to
which the receiver has no claim. In this sense the "fitness of the Divine
goodness" is justice; thus Anselm says (Proslog. x) that "God is just
when He spares the sinner, because this is befitting." And in this way
merit is also twofold. The first is an act in respect of which the agent
himself has a claim to receive something, and this is called merit of
"condignity." The second is an act the result of which is that there is a
duty of giving in the giver by reason of fittingness, wherefore it is
called merit of "congruity." Now since in all gratuitous givings, the
primary reason of the giving is love, it is impossible for anyone,
properly speaking, to lay claim to a gift, if he lack friendship.
Wherefore, as all things, whether temporal or eternal, are bestowed on us
by the bounty of God, no one can acquire a claim to any of them, save
through charity towards God: so that works done without charity are not
condignly meritorious of any good from God either eternal or temporal.
But since it is befitting the goodness of God, that wherever He finds a
disposition He should grant the perfection, a man is said to merit
congruously some good by means of good works done without charity.
Accordingly suchlike works avail for a threefold good, acquisition of
temporal goods, disposition to grace, habituation to good works. Since,
however, this is not merit properly so called, we should grant that such
works are not meritorious of any good, rather than that they are.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: As the Philosopher states (Ethic. viii, 14), since no
matter what a son may do, he can never give back to his father the equal
of what he has received from him a father can never become his son's
debtor: and much less can man make God his debtor on account of
equivalence of work. Consequently no work of ours can merit a reward by
reason of its measure of goodness, but it can by reason of charity, which
makes friends hold their possessions in common. Therefore, no matter how
good a work may be, if it be done without charity, it does not give man a
claim to receive anything from God. On the other hand, an evil deed
deserves an equivalent punishment according to the measure of its malice,
because no evil has been done to us on the part of God, like the good
which He has done. Therefore, although an evil deed deserves condign
punishment, nevertheless a good deed without charity does not merit
condign reward.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2 and 3: These arguments consider merit of congruity; while
the other arguments consider merit of condignity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[5] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the aforesaid works avail for the mitigation of the pains of
hell?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[5] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the aforesaid works do not avail for the
mitigation of the pains of hell. For the measure of punishment in hell
will answer to the measure of guilt. But works done without charity do
not diminish the measure of guilt. Neither, therefore, do they lessen the
pains of hell.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[5] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the pain of hell, though infinite in duration, is
nevertheless finite in intensity. Now anything finite is done away with
by finite subtraction. If therefore works done without charity canceled
any of the punishment due for sins, those works might be so numerous,
that the pain of hell would be done away with altogether: which is false.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[5] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, the suffrages of the Church are more efficacious than
works done without charity. But, according to Augustine (Enchiridion cx),
"the suffrages of the Church do not profit the damned in hell." Much less
therefore are those pains mitigated by works done without charity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[5] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, Augustine also says (Enchiridion cx): "Whomsoever they
profit, either receive a full pardon, or at least find damnation itself
more tolerable."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[5] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, it is a greater thing to do a good deed than to omit an evil
deed. But the omission of an evil deed always avoids a punishment, even
in one who lacks charity. Much more, therefore, do good deeds void
punishment.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[5] Body Para. 1/5
I answer that, Mitigation of the pains of hell can be understood in two
ways: first, as though one were delivered from the punishment which he
already deserved, and thus, since no one is delivered from punishment
unless he be absolved from guilt, (for an effect is not diminished or
taken away unless its cause be diminished or taken away), the pain of
hell cannot be mitigated by works done without charity, since they are
unable to remove or diminish guilt. Secondly, so that the demerit of
punishment is hindered; and thus the aforesaid works diminish the pain of
hell---first because he who does such works escapes being guilty of
omitting them---secondly, because such works dispose one somewhat to
good, so that a man sins from less contempt, and indeed is drawn away
from many sins thereby.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[5] Body Para. 2/5
These works do, however merit a diminution or postponement of temporal
punishment, as in the case of Achab (3 Kgs. 21:27, seqq.), as also the
acquisition of temporal goods.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[5] Body Para. 3/5
Some, however, say that they mitigate the pains of hell, not by
subtracting any of their substance, but by strengthening the subject, so
that he is more able to bear them. But this is impossible, because there
is no strengthening without a diminution of passibility. Now passibility
is according to the measure of guilt, wherefore if guilt is not removed,
neither can the subject be strengthened.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[5] Body Para. 4/5
Some again say that the punishment is mitigated as to the remorse of
conscience, though not as to the pain of fire. But neither will this
stand, because as the pain of fire is equal to the guilt, so also is the
pain of the remorse of conscience: so that what applies to one applies to
the other.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[14] A[5] Body Para. 5/5
This suffices for the Replies to the Objections.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[15] Out. Para. 1/1
OF THE MEANS OF MAKING SATISFACTION (THREE ARTICLES)
We must now consider the means of making satisfaction, under which head
there are three points of inquiry:
(1) Whether satisfaction must be made by means of penal works?
(2) Whether the scourges whereby God punishes man in this life, are
satisfactory?
(3) Whether the works of satisfaction are suitably reckoned, by saying
that there are three, viz. almsdeeds, fasting, and prayer?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[15] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether satisfaction must be made by means of penal works?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[15] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that satisfaction need not be made by means of
penal works. For satisfaction should make compensation for the offense
committed against God. Now, seemingly, no compensation is given to God by
penal works, for God does not delight in our sufferings, as appears from
Tobias 3:22. Therefore satisfaction need not be made by means of penal
works.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[15] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the greater the charity from which a work proceeds, the
less penal is that work, for "charity hath no pain [*Vulg.: 'Perfect
charity casteth out fear, because fear hath pain']" according to 1 Jn.
4:18. If therefore works of satisfaction need to be penal, the more they
proceed from charity, the less satisfactory will they be: which is false.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[15] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, "Satisfaction," as Anselm states (Cur Deus homo i)
"consists in giving due honor to God." But this can be done by other
means than penal works. Therefore satisfaction needs not to be made by
means of penal works.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[15] A[1] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, Gregory says (Hom. in Evang. xx): "It is just that the
sinner, by his repentance, should inflict on himself so much the greater
suffering, as he has brought greater harm on himself by his sin."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[15] A[1] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, the wound caused by sin should be perfectly healed by
satisfaction. Now punishment is the remedy for sins, as the Philosopher
says (Ethic. ii, 3). Therefore satisfaction should be made by means of
penal works.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[15] A[1] Body Para. 1/2
I answer that, As stated above (Q[12], A[3]), satisfaction regards both
the past offense, for which compensation is made by its means, and also
future sin wherefrom we are preserved thereby: and in both respects
satisfaction needs to be made by means of penal works. For compensation
for an offense implies equality, which must needs be between the offender
and the person whom he offends. Now equalization in human justice
consists in taking away from one that which he has too much of, and
giving it to the person from whom something has been taken. And, although
nothing can be taken away from God, so far as He is concerned, yet the
sinner, for his part, deprives Him of something by sinning as stated
above (Q[12], AA[3],4). Consequently, in order that compensation be made,
something by way of satisfaction that may conduce to the glory of God
must be taken away from the sinner. Now a good work, as such, does not
deprive the agent of anything, but perfects him: so that the deprivation
cannot be effected by a good work unless it be penal. Therefore, in order
that a work be satisfactory it needs to be good that it may conduce to
God's honor, and it must be penal, so that something may be taken away
from the sinner thereby.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[15] A[1] Body Para. 2/2
Again punishment preserves from future sin, because a man does not
easily fall back into sin when he has had experience of the punishment.
Wherefore, according to the Philosopher (Ethic. ii, 3) punishments are
medicinal.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[15] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Though God does not delight in our punishments as such, yet
He does, in so far as they are just, and thus they can be satisfactory.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[15] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Just as, in satisfaction, we have to note the penality of
the work, so, in merit, we must observe its difficulty. Now if the
difficulty of the work itself be diminished, other things being equal,
the merit is also diminished; but if the difficulty be diminished on the
part of the promptitude of the will, this does not diminish the merit,
but increases it; and, in like manner, diminution of the penality of a
work, on account of the will being made more prompt by charity, does not
lessen the efficacy of satisfaction, but increases it.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[15] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: That which is due for sin is compensation for the offense,
and this cannot be done without punishment of the sinner. It is of this
debt that Anselm speaks.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[15] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the scourges of the present life are satisfactory?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[15] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the scourges whereby we are punished by God in
this life, cannot be satisfactory. For nothing but what is meritorious
can be satisfactory, as is clear from what has been said (Q[14], A[2]).
But we do not merit except by what is in our own power. Since therefore
the scourges with which God punishes us are not in our power, it seems
that they cannot be satisfactory.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[15] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, only the good make satisfaction. But these scourges are
inflicted on the wicked also, and are deserved by them most of all.
Therefore they cannot be satisfactory.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[15] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, satisfaction regards past sins. But these scourges are
sometimes inflicted on those who have no sins, as in the case of Job.
Therefore it seems that they are not satisfactory.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[15] A[2] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, It is written (Rm. 5:3,4): "Tribulation worketh
patience, and patience trial, i.e. deliverance from sin," as a gloss
explains it.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[15] A[2] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, Ambrose says (Super Ps. 118): "Although faith," i.e. the
consciousness of sin, "be lacking, the punishment satisfies." Therefore
the scourges of this life are satisfactory.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[15] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Compensation for a past offense can be enforced either by
the offender or by another. When it is enforced by another, such
compensation is of a vindictive rather than of a satisfactory nature,
whereas when it is made by the offender, it is also satisfactory.
Consequently, if the scourges, which are inflicted by God on account of
sin, become in some way the act of the sufferer they acquire a
satisfactory character. Now they become the act of the sufferer in so far
as he accepts them for the cleansing of his sins, by taking advantage of
them patiently. If, however, he refuse to submit to them patiently, then
they do not become his personal act in any way, and are not of a
satisfactory, but merely of a vindictive character.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[15] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Although these scourges are not altogether in our power,
yet in some respect they are, in so far as we use them patiently. In this
way man makes a virtue of necessity, so that such things can become both
meritorious and satisfactory.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[15] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: As Augustine observes (De Civ. Dei i, 8), even as "the same
fire makes gold glisten and straw reek," so by the same scourges are the
good cleansed and the wicked worsened on account of their impatience.
Hence, though the scourges are common to both, satisfaction is only on
the side of the good.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[15] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: These scourges always regard past guilt, not always the
guilt of the person, but sometimes the guilt of nature. For had there not
been guilt in human nature, there would have been no punishment. But
since guilt preceded in nature, punishment is inflicted by God on a
person without the person's fault, that his virtue may be meritorious,
and that he may avoid future sin. Moreover, these two things are
necessary in satisfaction. For the work needs to be meritorious, that
honor may be given to God, and it must be a safeguard of virtue, that we
may be preserved from future sins.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[15] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the works of satisfaction are suitably enumerated?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[15] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the works of satisfaction are unsuitably
enumerated by saying that there are three, viz. almsdeeds, fasting, and
prayer. For a work of satisfaction should be penal. But prayer is not
penal, since it is a remedy against penal sorrow, and is a source of
pleasure, wherefore it is written (James 5:13): "Is any of you sad? Let
him pray. Is he cheerful in mind? Let him sing." Therefore prayer should
not be reckoned among the works of satisfaction.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[15] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, every sin is either carnal or spiritual. Now, as Jerome
says on Mk. 9:28, "This kind" of demons "can go out by nothing, but by
prayer and fasting: Diseases of the body are healed by fasting, diseases
of the mind, by prayer." Therefore no other work of satisfaction is
necessary.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[15] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, satisfaction is necessary in order for us to be cleansed
from our sins. But almsgiving cleanses from all sins, according to Lk.
11:41: "Give alms, and behold all things are clean unto you." Therefore
the other two are in excess.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[15] A[3] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: On the other hand, it seems that there should be more. For
contrary heals contrary. But there are many more than three kinds of sin.
Therefore more works of satisfaction should be enumerated.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[15] A[3] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, pilgrimages and scourgings are also enjoined as works of
satisfaction, and are not included among the above. Therefore they are
not sufficiently enumerated.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[15] A[3] Body Para. 1/3
I answer that, Satisfaction should be of such a nature as to involve
something taken away from us for the honor of God. Now we have but three
kinds of goods, bodily, spiritual, and goods of fortune, or external
goods. By alms-deeds we deprive ourselves of some goods of fortune, and
by fasting we retrench goods of the body. As to goods of the soul, there
is no need to deprive ourselves of any of them, either in whole or in
part, since thereby we become acceptable to God, but we should submit
them entirely to God, which is done by prayer.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[15] A[3] Body Para. 2/3
This number is shown to be suitable in so far as satisfaction uproots
the causes of sin, for these are reckoned to be three (1 Jn. 2:16), viz.
"concupiscence of the flesh," "concupiscence of the eyes," and "pride of
life." Fasting is directed against concupiscence of the "flesh,"
alms-deeds against concupiscence of the "eyes," and "prayer" against
"pride of life," as Augustine says (Enarr. in Ps. 42).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[15] A[3] Body Para. 3/3
This number is also shown to be suitable in so far as satisfaction does
not open a way to the suggestions of sin, because every sin is committed
either against God, and this is prevented by "prayer," or against our
neighbor, and this is remedied by "alms-deeds," or against ourselves, and
this is forestalled by "fasting."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[15] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/2
Reply OBJ 1: According to some, prayer is twofold. There is the prayer
of contemplatives whose "conversation is in heaven": and this, since it
is altogether delightful, is not a work of satisfaction. The other is a
prayer which pours forth sighs for sin; this is penal and a part of
satisfaction.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[15] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 2/2
It may also be replied, and better, that every prayer has the character
of satisfaction, for though it be sweet to the soul it is painful to the
body, since, as Gregory says (Super Ezech., Hom. xiv), "doubtless, when
our soul's love is strengthened, our body's strength is weakened"; hence
we read (Gn. 32:25) that the sinew of Jacob's thigh shrank through his
wrestling with the angel.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[15] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Carnal sin is twofold; one which is completed in carnal
delectation, as gluttony and lust. and, another which is completed in
things relating to the flesh, though it be completed in the delectation
of the soul rather than of the flesh, as covetousness. Hence such like
sins are between spiritual and carnal sins, so that they need a
satisfaction proper to them, viz. almsdeeds.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[15] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Although each of these three, by a kind of likeness, is
appropriated to some particular kind of sin because it is reasonable
that, whereby a man sins, in that he should be punished, and that
satisfaction should cut out the very root of the sin committed, yet each
of them can satisfy for any kind of sin. Hence if a man is unable to
perform one of the above, another is imposed on him, chiefly almsdeeds,
which can take the place of the others, in so far as in those to whom a
man gives alms he purchases other works of satisfaction thereby.
Consequently even if almsgiving washes all sins away, it does not follow
that other works are in excess.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[15] A[3] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: Though there are many kinds of sins, all are reduced to
those three roots or to those three kinds of sin, to which, as we have
said, the aforesaid works of satisfaction correspond.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[15] A[3] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: Whatever relates to affliction of the body is all referred
to fasting, and whatever is spent for the benefit of one's neighbor is a
kind of alms, and whatever act of worship is given to God becomes a kind
of prayer, so that even one work can be satisfactory in several ways.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[16] Out. Para. 1/1
OF THOSE WHO RECEIVE THE SACRAMENT OF PENANCE (THREE ARTICLES)
We must now consider the recipients of the sacrament of Penance: under
which head there are three points of inquiry:
(1) Whether penance can be in the innocent?
(2) Whether it can be in the saints in glory?
(3) Whether in the good or bad angels?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[16] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether penance can be in the innocent?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[16] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that penance cannot be in the innocent. For
penance consists in bewailing one's evil deeds: whereas the innocent have
done no evil. Therefore penance cannot be in them.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[16] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the very name of penance [poenitentia] implies
punishment [poena]. But the innocent do not deserve punishment. Therefore
penance is not in them.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[16] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, penance coincides with vindictive justice. But if all
were innocent, there would be no room for vindictive justice. Therefore
there would be no penance, so that there is none in the innocent.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[16] A[1] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, All the virtues are infused together. But penance is a
virtue. Since, therefore, other virtues are infused into the innocent at
Baptism, penance is infused with them.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[16] A[1] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, a man is said to be curable though he has never been sick in
body: therefore in like manner, one who has never been sick spiritually.
Now even as there can be no actual cure from the wound of sin without an
act of penance, so is there no possibility of cure without the habit of
penance. Therefore one who has never had the disease of sin, has the
habit of penance.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[16] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Habit comes between power and act: and since the removal
of what precedes entails the removal of what follows, but not conversely,
the removal of the habit ensues from the removal of the power to act, but
not from the removal of the act. And because removal of the matter
entails the removal of the act, since there can be no act without the
matter into which it passes, hence the habit of a virtue is possible in
one for whom the matter is not available, for the reason that it can be
available, so that the habit can proceed to its act---thus a poor man can
have the habit of magnificence, but not the act, because he is not
possessed of great wealth which is the matter of magnificence, but he can
be possessed thereof.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[16] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Although the innocent have committed no sin, nevertheless
they can, so that they are competent to have the habit of penance. Yet
this habit can never proceed to its act, except perhaps with regard to
their venial sins, because mortal sins destroy the habit. Nevertheless it
is not without its purpose, because it is a perfection of the natural
power.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[16] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Although they deserve no punishment actually, yet it is
possible for something to be in them for which they would deserve to be
punished.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[16] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: So long as the power to sin remains, there would be room
for vindictive justice as to the habit, though not as to the act, if
there were no actual sins.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[16] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the saints in glory have penance?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[16] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the saints in glory have not penance. For, as
Gregory says (Moral. iv), "the blessed remember their sins, even as we,
without grief, remember our griefs after we have been healed." But
penance is grief of the heart. Therefore the saints in heaven have not
penance.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[16] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the saints in heaven are conformed to Christ. But there
was no penance in Christ, since there was no faith which is the principle
of penance. Therefore there will be no penance in the saints in heaven.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[16] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, a habit is useless if it is not reduced to its act. But
the saints in heaven will not repent actually, because, if they did,
there would be something in them against their wish. Therefore the habit
of penance will not be in them.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[16] A[2] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: On the other hand, penance is a part of justice. But justice is
"perpetual and immortal" (Wis. 1:15), and will remain in heaven.
Therefore penance will also.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[16] A[2] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, we read in the Lives of the Fathers, that one of them
said that even Abraham will repent of not having done more good. But one
ought to repent of evil done more than of good left undone, and which one
was not bound to do, for such is the good in question. Therefore
repentance will be there of evil done.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[16] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, The cardinal virtues will remain in heaven, but only as
regards the acts which they exercise in respect of their end. Wherefore,
since the virtue of penance is a part of justice which is a cardinal
virtue, whoever has the habit of penance in this life, will have it in
the life to come: but he will not have the same act as now, but another,
viz. thanksgiving to God for His mercy in pardoning his sins.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[16] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: This argument proves that they do not have the same act as
penance has now; and we grant this.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[16] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Christ could not sin, wherefore the matter of this virtue
was lacking in His respect both actually and potentially: so that there
is no comparison between Him and others.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[16] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Repentance, properly speaking, considered as that act of
penance which is in this life, will not be in heaven: and yet the habit
will not be without its use, for it will have another act.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[16] A[2] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4,5: We grant the Fourth argument. But since the Fifth
Objection proves that there will be the same act of penance in heaven as
now, we answer the latter by saying that in heaven one will be altogether
conformed to the will of God. Wherefore, as God, by His antecedent will,
but not by His consequent will, wishes that all things should be good,
and therefore that there should be no evil, so is it with the blessed. It
is this will that this holy father improperly calls penance.
�Aquin.: SMT XP Q[16] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether an angel can be the subject of penance?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[16] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that even a good or bad angel can be a subject of
penance. For fear is the beginning of penance. But fear is in the angels,
according to James 2:19: "The devils . . . believe and tremble."
Therefore there can be penance in them.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[16] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the Philosopher says (Ethic. ix, 4) that "evil men are
full of repentance, and this is a great punishment for them." Now the
devils are exceeding evil, nor is there any punishment that they lack.
Therefore they can repent.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[16] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, a thing is more easily moved to that which is according
to its nature than to that which is against its nature: thus water which
has by violence been heated, of itself returns to its natural property.
Now angels can be moved to sin which is contrary to their common nature.
Much more therefore can they return to that which is in accord with their
nature. But this is done by penance. Therefore they are susceptible to
penance.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[16] A[3] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, what applies to angels, applies equally to separated
souls, as Damascene says (De Fide Orth. ii, 4). But there can be penance
in separated souls, as some say, as in the souls of the blessed in
heaven. Therefore there can be penance in the angels.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[16] A[3] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, By penance man obtains pardon for the sin he has
committed. But this is impossible in the angels. Therefore they are not
subjects of penance.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[16] A[3] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, Damascene says (De Fide Orth. ii, 4) that man is subject to
penance on account of the weakness of his body. But the angels are not
united to a body. Therefore no penance can be in them.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[16] A[3] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, In us, penance is taken in two senses; first, as a
passion, and thus it is nothing but pain or sorrow on account of a sin
committed: and though, as a passion it is only in the concupiscible part,
yet, by way of comparison, the name of penance is given to that act of
the will, whereby a man detests what he has done, even as love and other
passions are spoken of as though they were in the intellectual appetite.
Secondly, penance is taken as a virtue, and in this way its act consists
in the detestation of evil done, together with the purpose of amendment
and the intention of expiating the evil, or of placating God for the
offense committed. Now detestation of evil befits a person according as
he is naturally ordained to good. And since this order or inclination is
not entirely destroyed in any creature, it remains even in the damned,
and consequently the passion of repentance, or something like it, remains
in them too, as stated in Wis. 5:3 "(saying) within themselves,
repenting," etc. This repentance, as it is not a habit, but a passion or
act, can by no means be in the blessed angels, who have not committed any
sins: but it is in the wicked angels, since the same applies to them as
to the lost souls, for, according to Damascene (De Fide Orth. ii, 4),
"death is to men what sin is to an angel." But no forgiveness is possible
for the sin of an angel. Now sin is the proper object of the virtue
itself which we call penance, in so far as it can be pardoned or
expiated. Therefore, since the wicked angels cannot have the matter, they
have not the power to produce the act, so that neither can they have the
habit. Hence the angels cannot be subjects of the virtue of penance.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[16] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/2
Reply OBJ 1: A certain movement of penance is engendered in them from
fear, but not such as is a virtue.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[16] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 2/2
This suffices for the Reply to the Second Objection.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[16] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Whatever is natural in them is entirely good, and inclines
to good: but their free-will is fixed on evil. And since the movement of
virtue and vice follows the inclination, not of nature, but of the
free-will, there is no need that there should be movements of virtue in
them either actually or possibly, although they are inclined to good by
nature.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[16] A[3] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: There is no parity between the holy angels and the
beatified souls, because in the latter there has been or could have been
a sin that could be pardoned, but not in the former: so that though they
are like as to their present state, they differ as to their previous
states, which penance regards directly.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[17] Out. Para. 1/2
OF THE POWER OF THE KEYS (THREE ARTICLES)
We must now consider the power of the ministers of this sacrament, which
power depends on the keys. As to this matter, in the first place we shall
treat of the keys, secondly, of excommunication, thirdly, of indulgences,
since these two things are connected with the power of the keys. The
first of these considerations will be fourfold: (1) the nature and
meaning of the keys. (2) the use of the keys; (3) the ministers of the
keys; (4) those on whom the use of the keys can be exercised.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[17] Out. Para. 2/2
Under the first head there are three points of inquiry:
(1) Whether there ought to be keys in the Church?
(2) Whether the key is the power of binding and loosing, etc.?
(3) Whether there are two keys or only one?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[17] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether there should be keys in the Church?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[17] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that there is no necessity for keys in the Church.
For there is no need for keys that one may enter a house the door of
which is open. But it is written (Apoc. 4:1): "I looked and behold a door
was opened in heaven," which door is Christ, for He said of Himself (Jn.
10:7): "I am the door." Therefore the Church needs no keys for the
entrance into heaven.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[17] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, a key is needed for opening and shutting. But this
belongs to Christ alone, "Who openeth and no man shutteth, shutteth and
no man openeth" (Apoc. 3:7). Therefore the Church has no keys in the
hands of her ministers.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[17] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, hell is opened to whomever heaven is closed, and vice
versa. Therefore whoever has the keys of heaven, has the keys of hell.
But the Church is not said to have the keys of hell. Therefore neither
has she the keys of heaven.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[17] A[1] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, It is written (Mt. 16:19): "To thee will I give the
keys of the kingdom of heaven."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[17] A[1] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, every dispenser should have the keys of the things that he
dispenses. But the ministers of the Church are the dispensers of the
divine mysteries, as appears from 1 Cor. 4:1. Therefore they ought to
have the keys.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[17] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, In material things a key is an instrument for opening a
door. Now the door of the kingdom is closed to us through sin, both as to
the stain and as to the debt of punishment. Wherefore the power of
removing this obstacle is called a key. Now this power is in the Divine
Trinity by authority; hence some say that God has the key of "authority."
But Christ Man had the power to remove the above obstacle, through the
merit of His Passion, which also is said to open the door; hence some say
that He has the keys of "excellence." And since "the sacraments of which
the Church is built, flowed from the side of Christ while He lay asleep
on the cross" [*Augustine, Enarr. in Ps. 138], the efficacy of the
Passion abides in the sacraments of the Church. Wherefore a certain power
for the removal of the aforesaid obstacle is bestowed on the ministers of
the Church, who are the dispensers of the sacraments, not by their own,
but by a Divine power and by the Passion of Christ. This power is called
metaphorically the Church's key, and is the key of "ministry."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[17] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The door of heaven, considered in itself, is ever open, but
it is said to be closed to someone, on account of some obstacle against
entering therein, which is in himself. The obstacle which the entire
human nature inherited from the sin of the first man was removed by
Christ's Passion; hence, after the Passion, John saw an opened door in
heaven. Yet that door still remains closed to this or that man, on
account of the original sin which he has contracted, or the actual sin
which he has committed: hence we need the sacraments and the keys of the
Church.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[17] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: This refers to His closing Limbo, so that thenceforth no
one should go there, and to His opening of Paradise, the obstacle of
nature being removed by His Passion.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[17] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/2
Reply OBJ 3: The key whereby hell is opened and closed, is the power of
bestowing grace, whereby hell is opened to man, so that he is taken out
from sin which is the door of hell, and closed, so that by the help of
grace man should no more fall into sin. Now the power of bestowing grace
belongs to God alone, wherefore He kept this key to Himself. But the key
of the kingdom is also the power to remit the debt of temporal
punishment, which debt prevents man from entering the kingdom
Consequently the key of the kingdom can be given to man rather than the
key of hell, for they are not the same, as is clear from what has been
said. For a man may be set free from hell by the remission of the debt of
eternal punishment, without being at once admitted to the kingdom, on
account of his yet owing a debt of temporal punishment.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[17] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 2/2
It may also be replied, as some state, that the key of heaven is also
the key of hell, since if one is opened to a man, the other, for that
very reason, is closed to him, but it takes its name from the better of
the two.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[17] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the key is the power of binding and loosing, etc.?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[17] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the key is not the power of binding and
loosing, whereby "the ecclesiastical judge has to admit the worthy to the
kingdom and exclude the unworthy" therefrom, as stated in the text (Sent.
iv, D, 16). For the spiritual power conferred in a sacrament is the same
as the character. But the key and the character do not seem to be the
same, since by the character man is referred to God, whereas by the key
he is referred to his subjects. Therefore the key is not a power.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[17] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, an ecclesiastical judge is only one who has
jurisdiction, which is not given at the same time as orders. But the keys
are given in the conferring of orders. Therefore there should have been
no mention of the ecclesiastical judge in the definition of the keys.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[17] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, when a man has something of himself, he needs not to be
reduced to act by some active power. Now a man is admitted to the kingdom
from the very fact that he is worthy. Therefore it does not concern the
power of the keys to admit the worthy to the kingdom.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[17] A[2] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, sinners are unworthy of the kingdom. But the Church
prays for sinners, that they may go to heaven. Therefore she does not
exclude the unworthy, but admits them, so far as she is concerned.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[17] A[2] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, in every ordered series of agents, the last end belongs
to the principal and not to the instrumental agent. But the principal
agent in view of man's salvation is God. Therefore admission to the
kingdom, which is the last end, belongs to Him, and not to those who have
the keys, who are as instrumental or ministerial agents.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[17] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, According to the Philosopher (De Anima ii, text. 33),
"powers are defined from their acts." Wherefore, since the key is a kind
of power, it should be defined from its act or use, and reference to the
act should include its object from which it takes its species, and the
mode of acting whereby the power is shown to be well-ordered. Now the act
of the spiritual power is to open heaven, not absolutely, since it is
already open, as stated above (A[1], ad 1), but for this or that man; and
this cannot be done in an orderly manner without due consideration of the
worthiness of the one to be admitted to heaven. Hence the aforesaid
definition of the key gives the genus, viz. "power," the subject of the
power, viz. the "ecclesiastical judge," and the act, viz. "of excluding
or admitting," corresponding to the two acts of a material key which are
to open and shut; the object of which act is referred to in the words
"from the kingdom," and the mode, in the words, "worthy" and "unworthy,"
because account is taken of the worthiness or unworthiness of those on
whom the act is exercised.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[17] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The same power is directed to two things, of which one is
the cause of the other, as heat, in fire, is directed to make a thing hot
and to melt it. And since every grace and remission in a mystical body
comes to it from its head, it seems that it is essentially the same power
whereby a priest can consecrate, and whereby he can loose and bind, if he
has jurisdiction, and that there is only a logical difference, according
as it is referred to different effects, even as fire in one respect is
said to have the power of heating, and in another, the power of melting.
And because the character of the priestly order is nothing else than the
power of exercising that act to which the priestly order is chiefly
ordained (if we maintain that it is the same as a spiritual power),
therefore the character, the power of consecrating, and the power of the
keys are one and the same essentially, but differ logically.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[17] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: All spiritual power is conferred by some kind of
consecration. Therefore the key is given together with the order: yet the
use of the key requires due matter, i.e. a people subject through
jurisdiction, so that until he has jurisdiction, the priest has the keys,
but he cannot exercise the act of the keys. And since the key is defined
from its act, its definition contains a reference to jurisdiction.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[17] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: A person may be worthy to have something in two ways,
either so as to have a right to possess it, and thus whoever is worthy
has heaven already opened to him---or so that it is meet that he should
receive it, and thus the power of the keys admits those who are worthy,
but to whom heaven is not yet altogether opened.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[17] A[2] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: Even as God hardens not by imparting malice, but by
withholding grace, so a priest is said to exclude, not as though he
placed an obstacle to entrance, but because he does not remove an
obstacle which is there, since he cannot remove it unless God has already
removed it. [*St. Thomas here follows the opinion of Peter Lombard, and
replies in the negative. Later in life he altered his opinion. Cf. TP,
Q[62], A[1]; TP, Q[64], A[1]; TP, Q[86], A[6].] Hence God is prayed that
He may absolve, so that there may be room for the priest's absolution.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[17] A[2] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: The priest's act does not bear immediately on the kingdom,
but on the sacraments, by means of which man wins to the kingdom.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[17] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether there are two keys or only one?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[17] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that there are not two keys but only one. For one
lock requires but one key. Now the lock for the removal of which the keys
of the Church are required, is sin. Therefore the Church does not require
two keys for one sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[17] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the keys are given when orders are conferred. But
knowledge is not always due to infusion, but sometimes is acquired, nor
is it possessed by all those who are ordained, and is possessed by some
who are not ordained. Therefore knowledge is not a key, so that there is
but one key, viz. the power of judging.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[17] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, the power which the priest has over the mystic body of
Christ flows from the power which he has over Christ's true body. Now the
power of consecrating Christ's true body is but one. Therefore the power
which regards Christ's mystic body is but one. But this is a key.
Therefore, etc.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[17] A[3] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: On the other hand, It seems that there are more than two keys.
For just as knowledge and power are requisite for man to act, so is will.
But the knowledge of discretion is reckoned as a key, and so is the power
of judging. Therefore the will to absolve should be counted as a key.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[17] A[3] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, all three Divine Persons remit sins. Now the priest,
through the keys, is the minister for the remission of sins. Therefore he
should have three keys, so that he may be conformed to the Trinity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[17] A[3] Body Para. 1/2
I answer that, Whenever an act requires fitness on the part of the
recipient, two things are necessary in the one who has to perform the
act, viz. judgment of the fitness of the recipient, and accomplishment of
the act. Therefore in the act of justice whereby a man is given what he
deserves, there needs to be a judgment in order to discern whether he
deserves to receive. Again, an authority or power is necessary for both
these things, for we cannot give save what we have in our power; nor can
there be judgment, without the right to enforce it, since judgment is
determined to one particular thing, which determination it derives, in
speculative matters, from the first principles which cannot be gainsaid,
and, in practical matters, from the power of command vested in the one
who judges. And since the act of the key requires fitness in the person
on whom it is exercised---because the ecclesiastical judge, by means of
the key, "admits the worthy and excludes the unworthy," as may be seen
from the definition given above (A[2])---therefore the judge requires
both judgment of discretion whereby he judges a man to be worthy, and
also the very act of receiving (that man's confession); and for both
these things a certain power or authority is necessary. Accordingly we
may distinguish two keys, the first of which regards the judgment about
the worthiness of the person to be absolved, while the other regards the
absolution.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[17] A[3] Body Para. 2/2
These two keys are distinct, not in the essence of authority, since both
belong to the minister by virtue of his office, but in comparison with
their respective acts, one of which presupposes the other.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[17] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: One key is ordained immediately to the opening of one lock,
but it is not unfitting that one key should be ordained to the act of
another. Thus it is in the case in point. For it is the second key, which
is the power of binding and loosing, that opens the lock of sin
immediately, but the key of knowledge shows to whom that lock should be
opened.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[17] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/2
Reply OBJ 2: There are two opinions about the key of knowledge. For some
say that knowledge considered as a habit, acquired or infused, is the key
in this case, and that it is not the principal key, but is called a key
through being subordinate to another key: so that it is not called a key
when the other key is wanting, for instance, in an educated man who is
not a priest. And although priests lack this key at times, through being
without knowledge, acquired or infused, of loosing and binding, yet
sometimes they make use of their natural endeavors, which they who hold
this opinion call a little key, so that although knowledge be not
bestowed together with orders, yet with the conferring of orders the
knowledge becomes a key which it was not before. This seems to have been
the opinion of the Master (Sent. iv, D, 19).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[17] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 2/2
But this does not seem to agree with the words of the Gospel, whereby
the keys are promised to Peter (Mt. 16:19), so that not only one but two
are given in orders. For which reason the other opinion holds that the
key is not knowledge considered as a habit, but the authority to exercise
the act of knowledge, which authority is sometimes without knowledge,
while the knowledge is sometimes present without the authority. This may
be seen even in secular courts, for a secular judge may have the
authority to judge, without having the knowledge of the law, while
another man, on the contrary, has knowledge of the law without having the
authority to judge. And since the act of judging to which a man is bound
through the authority which is vested in him, and not through his habit
of knowledge, cannot be well performed without both of the above, the
authority to judge, which is the key of knowledge, cannot be accepted
without sin by one who lacks knowledge; whereas knowledge void of
authority can be possessed without sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[17] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: The power of consecrating is directed to only one act of
another kind, wherefore it is not numbered among the keys, nor is it
multiplied as the power of the keys, which is directed to different acts,
although as to the essence of power and authority it is but one, as
stated above.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[17] A[3] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: Everyone is free to will, so that no one needs authority to
will; wherefore will is not reckoned as a key.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[17] A[3] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: All three Persons remit sins in the same way as one Person,
wherefore there is no need for the priest, who is the minister of the
Trinity, to have three keys: and all the more, since the will, which is
appropriated to the Holy Ghost, requires no key, as stated above (ad 4).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] Out. Para. 1/1
OF THE EFFECT OF THE KEYS (FOUR ARTICLES)
We must now consider the effect of the keys under which head there are
four points of inquiry:
(1) Whether the power of the keys extends to the remission of guilt?
(2) Whether a priest can remit sin as to the punishment?
(3) Whether a priest can bind in virtue of the power of the keys?
(4) Whether he can loose and bind according to his own judgment?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the power of the keys extends to the remission of guilt? [*St.
Thomas here follows the opinion of Peter Lombard, and replies in the
negative. Later in life he altered his opinion. Cf. TP, Q[62], A[1]; TP,
Q[64], A[1]; TP, Q[86], A[6]]
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the power of the keys extends to the remission
of guilt. For it was said to the disciples (Jn. 20:23): "Whose sins you
shall forgive, they are forgiven them." Now this was not said in
reference to the declaration only, as the Master states (Sent. iv, D,
18), for in that case the priest of the New Testament would have no more
power than the priest of the Old Testament. Therefore he exercises a
power over the remission of the guilt.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, in Penance grace is given for the remission of sin. Now
the priest is the dispenser of this sacrament by virtue of the keys.
Therefore, since grace is opposed to sin, not on the part of the
punishment, but on the part of the guilt, it seems that the priest
operates unto the remission of sin by virtue of the keys.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, the priest receives more power by his consecration than
the baptismal water by its sanctification. Now the baptismal water
receives the power "to touch the body and cleanse the heart," as
Augustine says (Tract. lxxx in Joan.). Much more, therefore, does the
priest, in his consecration, receive the power to cleanse the heart from
the stain of sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] A[1] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, The Master stated above (Sent. iv, D, 18) that God has
not bestowed on the minister the power to co-operate with Him in the
inward cleansing. Now if he remitted sins as to the guilt, he would
co-operate with God in the inward cleansing. Therefore the power of the
keys does not extend to the remission of guilt.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] A[1] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, sin is not remitted save by the Holy Ghost. But no man has the
power to give the Holy Ghost, as the Master said above (Sent. i, D, 14).
Neither therefore can he remit sins as to their guilt.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, According to Hugh (De Sacram. ii), "the sacraments, by
virtue of their sanctification, contain an invisible grace." Now this
sanctification is sometimes essential to the sacrament both as regards
the matter and as regards the minister, as may be seen in Confirmation,
and then the sacramental virtue is in both together. Sometimes, however,
the essence of the sacrament requires only sanctification of the matter,
as in Baptism, which has no fixed minister on whom it depends
necessarily, and then the whole virtue of the sacrament is in the matter.
Again, sometimes the essence of the sacrament requires the consecration
or sanctification of the minister without any sanctification of the
matter, and then the entire sacramental virtue is in the minister, as in
Penance. Hence the power of the keys which is in the priest, stands in
the same relation to the effect of Penance, as the virtue in the
baptismal water does to the effect of Baptism. Now Baptism and the
sacrament of Penance agree somewhat in their effect, since each is
directly ordained against guilt, which is not the case in the other
sacraments: yet they differ in this, that the sacrament of Penance, since
the acts of the recipient are as its matter, cannot be given save to
adults, who need to be disposed for the reception of the sacramental
effect; whereas Baptism is given, sometimes to adults, sometimes to
children and others who lack the use of reason, so that by Baptism
children receive grace and remission of sin without any previous
disposition, while adults do not, for they require to be disposed by the
removal of insincerity. This disposition sometimes precedes their Baptism
by priority of time, being sufficient for the reception of grace, before
they are actually baptized, but not before they have come to the
knowledge of the truth and have conceived the desire for Baptism. At
other times this disposition does not precede the reception of Baptism by
a priority of time, but is simultaneous with it, and then the grace of
the remission of guilt is bestowed through the reception of Baptism. On
the other hand, grace is never given through the sacrament of Penance
unless the recipient be disposed either simultaneously or before. Hence
the power of the keys operates unto the remission of guilt, either
through being desired or through being actually exercised, even as the
waters of Baptism. But just as Baptism acts, not as a principal agent but
as an instrument, and does not go so far as to cause the reception itself
of grace, even instrumentally [*See note at beginning of this article],
but merely disposes the recipient to the grace whereby his guilt is
remitted, so is it with the power of the keys. Wherefore God alone
directly remits guilt, and Baptism acts through His power instrumentally,
as an inanimate instrument, and the priest as an animate instrument, such
as a servant is, according to the Philosopher (Ethic. viii, 11): and
consequently the priest acts as a minister. Hence it is clear that the
power of the keys is ordained, in a manner, to the remission of guilt,
not as causing that remission, but as disposing thereto. Consequently if
a man, before receiving absolution, were not perfectly disposed for the
reception of grace, he would receive grace at the very time of
sacramental confession and absolution, provided he offered no obstacle.
For if the key were in no way ordained to the remission of guilt, but
only to the remission of punishment, as some hold, it would not be
necessary to have a desire of receiving the effect of the keys in order
to have one's sins forgiven, just as it is not necessary to have a desire
of receiving the other sacraments which are ordained, not to the
remission of guilt, but against punishment. But this enables us to see
that it is not ordained unto the remission of guilt, because the use of
the keys, in order to be effective, always requires a disposition on the
part of the recipient of the sacrament. And the same would apply to
Baptism, were it never given save to adults.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: As the Master says in the text (Sent. iv, D, 18), the power
of forgiving sins was entrusted to priests, not that they may forgive
them, by their own power, for this belongs to God, but that, as
ministers, they may declare [*See note at the beginning of this article]
the operation of God Who forgives. Now this happens in three ways. First,
by a declaration, not of present, but of future forgiveness, without
co-operating therein in any way: and thus the sacraments of the Old Law
signified the Divine operation, so that the priest of the Old Law did but
declare and did not operate the forgiveness of sins. Secondly, by a
declaration of present forgiveness without co-operating in it at all: and
thus some say that the sacraments of the New Law signify the bestowal of
grace, which God gives when the sacraments are conferred, without the
sacraments containing any power productive of grace, according to which
opinion, even the power of the keys would merely declare the Divine
operation that has its effect in the remission of guilt when the
sacrament is conferred. Thirdly, by signifying the Divine operation
causing then and there the remission of guilt, and by co-operating
towards this effect dispositively and instrumentally: and then, according
to another and more common opinion, the sacraments of the New Law declare
the cleansing effected by God. In this way also the priest of the New
Testament declares the recipient to be absolved from guilt, because in
speaking of the sacraments, what is ascribed to the power of the
ministers must be consistent with the sacrament. Nor is it unreasonable
that the keys of the Church should dispose the penitent to the remission
of his guilt, from the fact that the guilt is already remitted, even as
neither is it unreasonable that Baptism, considered in itself, causes a
disposition in one who is already sanctified.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/2
Reply OBJ 2: Neither the sacrament of Penance, nor the sacrament of
Baptism, by its operation, causes grace, or the remission of guilt,
directly, but only dispositively [*St. Thomas here follows the opinion of
Peter Lombard, and replies in the negative. Later in life he altered his
opinion. Cf. TP, Q[62], A[1]; TP, Q[64], A[1]; TP, Q[86], A[6]]. Hence
the Reply to the Third Objection is evident.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 2/2
The other arguments show that the power of the keys does not effect the
remission of guilt directly, and this is to be granted.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether a priest can remit sin as to the punishment?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that a priest cannot remit sin as to the
punishment. For sin deserves eternal and temporal punishment. But after
the priest's absolution the penitent is still obliged to undergo temporal
punishment either in Purgatory or in this world. Therefore the priest
does not remit the punishment in any way.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the priest cannot anticipate the judgment of God. But
Divine justice appoints the punishment which penitents have to undergo.
Therefore the priest cannot remit any part of it.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, a man who has committed a slight sin, is not less
susceptible to the power of the keys, than one who has committed a graver
sin. Now if the punishment for the graver sin be lessened in any way
through the priestly administrations, it would be possible for a sin to
be so slight that the punishment which it deserves is no greater than
that which has been remitted for the graver sin. Therefore the priest
would be able to remit the entire punishment due for the slight sin:
which is false.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] A[2] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, the whole of the temporal punishment due for a sin is of
one kind. If, therefore, by a first absolution something is taken away
from the punishment, it will be possible for something more to be taken
away by a second absolution, so that the absolution can be so often
repeated, that by virtue of the keys the whole punishment will be taken
away, since the second absolution is not less efficacious than the first:
and consequently that sin will be altogether unpunished, which is absurd.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] A[2] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, The key is the power of binding and loosing. But the
priest can enjoin a temporal punishment. Therefore he can absolve from
punishment.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] A[2] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, the priest cannot remit sin either as to the guilt [*St. Thomas
here follows the opinion of Peter Lombard, and replies in the negative.
Later in life he altered his opinion. Cf. TP, Q[62], A[1]; TP, Q[64],
A[1]; TP, Q[86], A[6]], as stated in the text (Sent. iv, D, 18), or as to
the eternal punishment, for a like reason. If therefore he cannot remit
sin as to the temporal punishment, he would be unable to remit sin in any
way, which is altogether contrary to the words of the Gospel.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Whatever may be said of the effect of Baptism conferred
on one who has already received grace, applies equally to the effect of
the actual exercise of the power of the keys on one who has already been
contrite. For a man may obtain the grace of the remission of his sins as
to their guilt, through faith and contrition, previous to Baptism; but
when, afterwards, he actually receives Baptism, his grace is increased,
and he is entirely absolved from the debt of punishment, since he is then
made a partaker of the Passion of Christ. In like manner when a man,
through contrition, has received the pardon of his sins as to their
guilt, and consequently as to the debt of eternal punishment, (which is
remitted together with the guilt) by virtue of the keys which derive
their efficacy from the Passion of Christ, his grace is increased and the
temporal punishment is remitted, the debt of which remained after the
guilt had been forgiven. However, this temporal punishment is not
entirely remitted, as in Baptism, but only partly, because the man who is
regenerated in Baptism is conformed to the Passion of Christ, by
receiving into himself entirely the efficacy of Christ's Passion, which
suffices for the blotting out of all punishment, so that nothing remains
of the punishment due to his preceding actual sins. For nothing should be
imputed to a man unto punishment, save what he has done himself, and in
Baptism man begins a new life, and by the baptismal water becomes a new
man, as that no debt for previous sin remains in him. on the other hand,
in Penance, a man does not take on a new life, since therein he is not
born again, but healed. Consequently by virtue of the keys which produce
their effect in the sacrament of Penance, the punishment is not entirely
remitted, but something is taken off the temporal punishment, the debt of
which could remain after the eternal punishment had been remitted. Nor
does this apply only to the temporal punishment which the penitent owes
at the time of confession, as some hold, (for then confession and
sacramental absolution would be mere burdens, which cannot be said of the
sacraments of the New Law), but also to the punishment due in Purgatory,
so that one who has been absolved and dies before making satisfaction, is
less punished in Purgatory, than if he had died before receiving
absolution.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The priest does not remit the entire temporal punishment,
but part of it; wherefore the penitent still remains obliged to undergo
satisfactory punishment.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Christ's Passion was sufficiently satisfactory for the sins
of the whole world, so that without prejudice to Divine justice something
can be remitted from the punishment which a sinner deserves, in so far as
the effect of Christ's Passion reaches him through the sacraments of the
Church.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Some satisfactory punishment must remain for each sin, so
as to provide a remedy against it. Wherefore though, by virtue of the
absolution some measure of the punishment due to a grave sin is remitted,
it does not follow that the same measure of punishment is remitted for
each sin, because in that case some sin would remain without any
punishment at all: but, by virtue of the keys, the punishments due to
various sins are remitted in due proportion.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] A[2] R.O. 4 Para. 1/3
Reply OBJ 4: Some say that at the first absolution, as much as possible
is remitted by virtue of the keys, and that, nevertheless, the second
confession is valid, on account of the instruction received, on account
of the additional surety, on account of the prayers of the priest or
confessor, and lastly on account of the merit of the shame.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] A[2] R.O. 4 Para. 2/3
But this does not seem to be true, for though there might be a reason
for repeating the confession, there would be no reason for repeating the
absolution, especially if the penitent has no cause to doubt about his
previous absolution; for he might just as well doubt after the second as
after the first absolution: even as we see that the sacrament of Extreme
Unction is not repeated during the same sickness, for the reason that all
that could be done through the sacrament, has been done once. Moreover,
in the second confession, there would be no need for the confessor to
have the keys, if the power of the keys had no effect therein.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] A[2] R.O. 4 Para. 3/3
For these reasons others say that even in the second absolution
something of the punishment is remitted by virtue of the keys, because
when absolution is given a second time, grace is increased, and the
greater the grace received, the less there remains of the blemish of the
previous sin, and the less punishment is required to remove that blemish.
Wherefore even when a man is first absolved, his punishment is more or
less remitted by virtue of the keys, according as he disposes himself
more or less to receive grace; and this disposition may be so great, that
even by virtue of his contrition the whole punishment is remitted, as we
have already stated (Q[5], A[2]). Consequently it is not unreasonable, if
by frequent confession even the whole punishment be remitted, that a sin
remain altogether unpunished, since Christ made satisfaction for its
punishment.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the priest can bind through the power of the keys?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the priest cannot bind by virtue of the power
of the keys. For the sacramental power is ordained as a remedy against
sin. Now binding is not a remedy for sin, but seemingly is rather
conducive to an aggravation of the disease. Therefore, by the power of
the keys, which is a sacramental power, the priest cannot bind.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, just as to loose or to open is to remove an obstacle, so
to bind is to place an obstacle. Now an obstacle to heaven is sin, which
cannot be placed on us by an extrinsic cause, since no sin is committed
except by the will. Therefore the priest cannot bind.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, the keys derive their efficacy from Christ's Passion.
But binding is not an effect of the Passion. Therefore the priest cannot
bind by the power of the keys.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] A[3] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, It is written (Mt. 16:19): "Whatsoever thou shalt bind
on earth, shall be bound also in heaven."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] A[3] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, rational powers are directed to opposites. But the power of
the keys is a rational power, since it has discretion connected with it.
Therefore it is directed to opposites. Therefore if it can loose, it can
bind.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] A[3] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, The operation of the priest in using the keys, is
conformed to God's operation, Whose minister he is. Now God's operation
extends both to guilt and to punishment; to the guilt indeed, so as to
loose it directly. but to bind it indirectly, in so far as He is said to
harden, when He withholds His grace; whereas His operation extends to
punishment directly, in both respects, because He both spares and
inflicts it. In like manner, therefore, although the priest, in
absolving, exercises an operation ordained to the remission of guilt, in
the way mentioned above (A[1]), nevertheless, in binding, he exercises no
operation on the guilt; (unless he be said to bind by not absolving the
penitent and by declaring him to be bound), but he has the power both of
binding and of loosing with regard to the punishment. For he looses from
the punishment which he remits, while he binds as to the punishment which
remains. This he does in two ways---first as regards the quantity of the
punishment considered in general, and thus he does not bind save by not
loosing, and declaring the penitent to be bound, secondly, as regards
this or that particular punishment, and thus he binds to punishment by
imposing it.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The remainder of the punishment to which the priest binds
the penitent, is the medicine which cleanses the latter from the blemish
of sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Not only sin, but also punishment is an obstacle to heaven:
and how the latter is enjoined by the priest, has been said in the
article.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Even the Passion of Christ binds us to some punishment
whereby we are conformed to Him.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the priest can bind and loose according to his own judgment?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It seems that the priest can bind and loose according to his own
judgment. For Jerome [*Cf. Can. 86, Mensuram, De Poenit. Dist. i] says:
"The canons do not fix the length of time for doing penance so precisely
as to say how each sin is to be amended, but leave the decision of this
matter to the judgment of a discreet priest." Therefore it seems that he
can bind and loose according to his own judgment.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, "The Lord commended the unjust steward, forasmuch as he
had done wisely" (Lk. 16:5), because he had allowed a liberal discount to
his master's debtors. But God is more inclined to mercy than any temporal
lord. Therefore it seems that the more punishment the priest remits, the
more he is to be commended.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] A[4] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, Christ's every action is our instruction. Now on some
sinners He imposed no punishment, but only amendment of life, as in the
case of the adulterous woman (Jn. 8). Therefore it seems that the priest
also, who is the vicar of Christ, can, according to his own judgment,
remit the punishment, either wholly or in part.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] A[4] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, Gregory VII [*Cf. Act. Concil. Rom. v, Can. 5] says:
"We declare it a mock penance if it is not imposed according to the
authority of the holy fathers in proportion to the sin." Therefore it
seems that it does not altogether depend on the priest's judgment.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] A[4] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, the act of the keys requires discretion. Now if the priest
could remit and impose as much as he liked of a penance, he would have no
need of discretion, because there would be no room for indiscretion.
Therefore it does not altogether depend on the priest's judgment.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] A[4] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, In using the keys, the priest acts as the instrument and
minister of God. Now no instrument can have an efficacious act, except in
so far as it is moved by the principal agent. Wherefore, Dionysius says
(Hier. Eccl. cap. ult.) that "priests should use their hierarchical
powers, according as they are moved by God." A sign of this is that
before the power of the keys was conferred on Peter (Mt. 16:19) mention
is made of the revelation vouchsafed to him of the Godhead; and the gift
of the Holy Ghost, whereby "the sons of God are led" (Rm. 8:14), is
mentioned before power was given to the apostles to forgive sins.
Consequently if anyone were to presume to use his power against that
Divine motion, he would not realize the effect, as Dionysius states
(Hier. Eccl., cap. ult.), and, besides, he would be turned away from the
Divine order, and consequently would be guilty of a sin. Moreover, since
satisfactory punishments are medicinal, just as the medicines prescribed
by the medical art are not suitable to all, but have to be changed
according to the judgment of a medical man, who follows not his own will,
but his medical science, so the satisfactory punishments appointed by the
canons are not suitable to all, but have to be varied according to the
judgment of the priest guided by the Divine instinct. Therefore just as
sometimes the physician prudently refrains from giving a medicine
sufficiently efficacious to heal the disease, lest a greater danger
should arise on account of the weakness of nature so the priest, moved by
Divine instinct, some times refrains from enjoining the entire punishment
due to one sin, lest by the severity of the punishment, the sick man come
to despair and turn away altogether from repentance.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: This judgment should be guided entirely by the Divine
instinct.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The steward is commended also for having done wisely.
Therefore in the remission of the due punishment, there is need for
discretion.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[18] A[4] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Christ had the power of "excellence" in the sacraments, so
that, by His own authority, He could remit the punishment wholly or in
part, just as He chose. Therefore there is no comparison between Him and
those who act merely as ministers.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] Out. Para. 1/1
OF THE MINISTERS OF THE KEYS (SIX ARTICLES)
We must now consider the ministers and the use of the keys: under which
head there are six points of inquiry:
(1) Whether the priest of the Law had the keys?
(2) Whether Christ had the keys?
(3) Whether priests alone have the keys?
(4) Whether holy men who are not priests have the keys or their use?
(5) Whether wicked priests have the effective use of the keys?
(6) Whether those who are schismatics, heretics, excommunicate,
suspended or degraded, have the use of the keys?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the priest of the Law had the keys?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the priests of the Law had the keys. For the
possession of the keys results from having orders. But they had orders
since they were called priests. Therefore the priests of the Law had the
keys.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, as the Master states (Sent. iv, D, 18), there are two
keys, knowledge of discretion, and power of judgment. But the priests of
the Law had authority for both of these: therefore they had the keys.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, the priests of the Law had some power over the rest of
the people, which power was not temporal, else the kingly power would not
have differed from the priestly power. Therefore it was a spiritual
power; and this is the key. Therefore they had the key.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[1] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, The keys are ordained to the opening of the heavenly
kingdom, which could not be opened before Christ's Passion. Therefore the
priest of the Law had not the keys. Further, the sacraments of the old
Law did not confer grace. Now the gate of the heavenly kingdom could not
be opened except by means of grace. Therefore it could not be opened by
means of those sacraments, so that the priests who administered them, had
not the keys of the heavenly kingdom.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[1] Body Para. 1/2
I answer that, Some have held that, under the Old Law, the keys of the
kingdom were in the hands of the priests, because the right of imposing
punishment for sin was conferred on them, as related in Lev. 5, which
right seems to belong to the keys; but that these keys were incomplete
then, whereas now they are complete as bestowed by Christ on the priests
of the New Law.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[1] Body Para. 2/2
But this seems to be contrary to the intent of the Apostle in the
Epistle to the Hebrews (Heb. 9:11-12). For there the priesthood of Christ
is given the preference over the priesthood of the Law, inasmuch as
Christ came, "a high priest of the good things to come," and brought us
"by His own blood" into a tabernacle not made with hand, whither the
priesthood of the Old Law brought men "by the blood of goats and of
oxen." Hence it is clear that the power of that priesthood did not reach
to heavenly things but to the shadow of heavenly things: and so, we must
say with others that they had not the keys, but that the keys were
foreshadowed in them.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The keys of the kingdom go with the priesthood whereby man
is brought into the heavenly kingdom, but such was not the priesthood of
Levi; hence it had the keys, not of heaven, but of an earthly tabernacle.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The priests of the Old Law had authority to discern and
judge, but not to admit those they judged into heaven, but only into the
shadow of heavenly things.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: They had no spiritual power, since, by the sacraments of
the Law, they cleansed men not from their sins but from irregularities,
so that those who were cleansed by them could enter into a tabernacle
which was "made with hand."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether Christ had the key?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that Christ did not have the key. For the key goes
with the character of order. But Christ did not have a character.
Therefore He had not the key.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, Christ had power of "excellence" in the sacraments, so
that He could produce the sacramental effect without the sacramental
rite. Now the key is something sacramental. Therefore He needed no key,
and it would have been useless to Him to have it.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, It is written (Apoc. 3:7): "These things saith . . . He
that hath the key of David," etc.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, The power to do a thing is both in the instrument and in
the principal agent, but not in the same way since it is more perfectly
in the latter. Now the power of the keys which we have, like other
sacramental powers, is instrumental: whereas it is in Christ as principal
agent in the matter of our salvation, by authority, if we consider Him as
God, by merit, if we consider Him as man [*For St. Thomas' later teaching
on this point, Cf. TP, Q[48], A[6]; FS, Q[112], A[1], AD 1]. But the very
notion of a key expresses a power to open and shut, whether this be done
by the principal agent or by an instrument. Consequently we must admit
that Christ had the key, but in a higher way than His ministers,
wherefore He is said to have the key of "excellence."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: A character implies the notion of something derived from
another, hence the power of the keys which we receive from Christ results
from the character whereby we are conformed to Christ, whereas in Christ
it results not from a character, but from the principal form.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The key, which Christ had was not sacramental, but the
origin of the sacramental key.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether priests alone have the keys?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that not only priests have the keys. For Isidore
says (Etym. vii, 12) that the "doorkeepers have to tell the good from the
bad, so as to admit the good and keep out the bad." Now this is the
definition of the keys, as appears from what has been said (Q[17], A[2]).
Therefore not only priests but even doorkeepers have the keys.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the keys are conferred on priests when by being anointed
they receive power from God. But kings of Christian peoples also receive
power from God and are consecrated by being anointed. Therefore not only
priests have the keys.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, the priesthood is an order belonging to an individual
person. But sometimes a number of people together seem to have the key,
because certain Chapters can pass a sentence of excommunication, which
pertains to the power of the keys. Therefore not only priests have the
key.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[3] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, a woman is not capable of receiving the priesthood,
since she is not competent to teach, according to the Apostle (1 Cor.
14:34). But some women (abbesses, for instance, who exercise a spiritual
power over their subjects), seem to have the keys. Therefore not only
priests have the keys.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[3] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, Ambrose says (De Poenit. i): "This right," viz. of
binding and loosing, "is granted to priests alone."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[3] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, by receiving the power of the keys, a man is set up between the
people and God. But this belongs to the priest alone, who is "ordained .
. in the things that appertain to God, that he may offer up gifts and
sacrifices for sins" (Heb. 5:1). Therefore only priests have the keys.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[3] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, There are two kinds of key. one reaches to heaven itself
directly, by remitting sin and thus removing the obstacles to the
entrance into heaven; and this is called the key of "order." Priests
alone have this key, because they alone are ordained for the people in
the things which appertain to God directly. The other key reaches to
heaven, not directly but through the medium of the Church Militant. By
this key a man goes to heaven, since, by its means, a man is shut out
from or admitted to the fellowship of the Church Militant, by
excommunication or absolution. This is called the key of "jurisdiction"
in the external court, wherefore even those who are not priests can have
this key, e.g. archdeacons, bishops elect, and others who can
excommunicate. But it is not properly called a key of heaven, but a
disposition thereto.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The doorkeepers have the key for taking care of those
things which are contained in a material temple, and they have to judge
whether a person should be excluded from or admitted to that temple;
which judgment they pronounce, not by their own authority, but in
pursuance to the priest's judgment, so that they appear to be the
administrators of the priestly power.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Kings have no power in spiritual matters, so that they do
not receive the key of the heavenly kingdom. Their power is confined to
temporal matters, and this too can only come to them from God, as appears
from Rm. 13:1. Nor are they consecrated by the unction of a sacred order:
their anointing is merely a sign that the excellence of their power comes
down to them from Christ, and that, under Christ, they reign over the
Christian people.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Just as in civil matters the whole power is sometimes
vested in a judge, as in a kingdom, whereas sometimes it is vested in
many exercising various offices but acting together with equal rights
(Ethic. viii, 10,11), so too, spiritual jurisdiction may be exercised
both by one alone, e.g. a bishop, and by many together, e.g. by a
Chapter, and thus they have the key of jurisdiction, but they have not
all together the key of order.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[3] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: According to the Apostle (1 Tim. 2:11; Titus 2:5), woman is
in a state of subjection: wherefore she can have no spiritual
jurisdiction, since the Philosopher also says (Ethic. viii) that it is a
corruption of public life when the government comes into the hands of a
woman. Consequently a woman has neither the key of order nor the key of
jurisdiction. Nevertheless a certain use of the keys is allowed to women,
such as the right to correct other women who are under them, on account
of the danger that might threaten if men were to dwell under the same
roof.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether holy men who are not priests have the keys?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that holy men, even those who are not priests, have
the use of the keys. For loosing and binding, which are the effects of
the keys, derive their efficacy from the merit of Christ's Passion. Now
those are most conformed to Christ's Passion, who follow Christ,
suffering by patience and other virtues. Therefore it seems that even if
they have not the priestly order, they can bind and loose.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, it is written (Heb. 7:7): "Without all contradiction,
that which is less is blessed by the greater [Vulg.: 'better']." Now "in
spiritual matters," according to Augustine (De Trin. vi, 8), "to be
better is to be greater." Therefore those who are better, i.e. who have
more charity, can bless others by absolving them. Hence the same
conclusion follows.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[4] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, "Action belongs to that which has the power," as the
Philosopher says (De Somno et Vigil. i). But the key which is a spiritual
power belongs to priests alone. Therefore priests alone are competent to
have the use of the keys.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[4] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, There is this difference between a principal and an
instrumental agent, that the latter does not produce, in the effect, its
own likeness, but the likeness of the principal agent, whereas the
principal agent produces its own likeness. Consequently a thing becomes a
principal agent through having a form, which it can reproduce in another,
whereas an instrumental agent is not constituted thus, but through being
applied by the principal agent in order to produce a certain effect.
Since therefore in the act of the keys the principal agent by authority
is Christ as God, and by merit is Christ as man,* it follows that on
account of the very fulness of Divine goodness in Him, and of the
perfection of His grace, He is competent to exercise the act of the keys.
[*For St. Thomas' later teaching on this point, cf. TP, Q[48], A[6]; FS,
Q[112], A[1], ad 1]. But another man is not competent to exercise this
act as principal agent, since neither can he give another man grace
whereby sins are remitted, nor can he merit sufficiently, so that he is
nothing more than an instrumental agent. Consequently the recipient of
the effect of the keys, is likened, not to the one who uses the keys, but
to Christ. Therefore, no matter how much grace a man may have, he cannot
produce the effect of the keys, unless he be appointed to that purpose by
receiving orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Just as between instrument and effect there is need or
likeness, not of a similar form, but of aptitude in the instrument for
the effect, so is it as regards the instrument and the principal agent.
The former is the likeness between holy men and the suffering Christ, nor
does it bestow on them the use of the keys.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Although a mere man cannot merit grace for another man
condignly, yet the merit of one man can co-operate in the salvation of
another. Hence there is a twofold blessing. One proceeds from a mere man,
as meriting by his own act: this blessing can be conferred by any holy
person in whom Christ dwells by His grace, in so far as he excels in
goodness the person whom he blesses. The other blessing is when a man
blesses, as applying a blessing instrumentally through the merit of
Christ, and this requires excellence of order and not of virtue.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[5] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether wicked priests have the use of the keys?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[5] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that wicked priests have not the use of the keys.
For in the passage where the use of the keys is bestowed on the apostles
(Jn. 20:22,23), the gift of the Holy Ghost is promised. But wicked men
have not the Holy Ghost. Therefore they have not the use of the keys.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[5] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, no wise king entrusts his enemy with the dispensation of
his treasure. Now the use of the keys consists in dispensing the treasure
of the King of heaven, Who is Wisdom itself. Therefore the wicked, who
are His enemies on account of sin, have not the use of the keys.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[5] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, Augustine says (De Bapt. v, 21) that God "gives the
sacrament of grace even through wicked men, but grace itself only by
Himself or through His saints." Hence He forgives sin by Himself, or by
those who are members of the Dove. But the remission of sins is the use
of the keys. Therefore sinners, who are not "members of the Dove," have
not the use of the keys.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[5] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, the prayer of a wicked priest cannot effect
reconciliation, for, as Gregory says (Pastor. i, 11), "if an unacceptable
person is sent to intercede, anger is provoked to yet greater severity."
But the use of the keys implies a kind of intercession, as appears in the
form of absolution. Therefore wicked priests cannot use the keys
effectively.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[5] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, No man can know whether another man is in the state of
grace. If, therefore, no one could use the keys in giving absolution
unless he were in a state of grace, no one would know that he had been
absolved, which would be very unfitting.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[5] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, the wickedness of the minister cannot void the liberality of
his lord. But the priest is no more than a minister. Therefore he cannot
by his wickedness take away from us the gift which God has given through
him.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[5] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Just as participation of a form to be induced into an
effect does not make a thing to be an instrument, so neither does the
loss of that form prevent that thing being used as an instrument.
Consequently, since man is merely an instrument in the use of the keys,
however much he may through sin be deprived of grace, whereby sins are
forgiven, yet he is by no means deprived of the use of the keys.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[5] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The gift of the Holy Ghost is requisite for the use of the
keys, not as being indispensable for the purpose, but because it is
unbecoming for the user to use them without it, though he that submits to
them receives their effect.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[5] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: An earthly king can be cheated and deceived in the matter
of his treasure, and so he does not entrust his enemy with the
dispensation thereof. But the King of heaven cannot be cheated, because
all tends to His own glory, even the abuse of the keys by some, for He
can make good come out of evil, and produce many good effects through
evil men. Hence the comparison fails.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[5] R.O. 3 Para. 1/2
Reply OBJ 3: Augustine speaks of the remission of sins in so far as holy
men co-operate therein, not by virtue of the keys, but by merit of
congruity. Hence He says that God confers the sacraments even through
evil men, and among the other sacraments, absolution which is the use of
the keys should be reckoned: but that through "members of the Dove," i.e.
holy men, He grants forgiveness of sins, in so far as He remits sins on
account of their intercession.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[5] R.O. 3 Para. 2/2
We might also reply that by "members of the Dove" he means all who are
not cut off from the Church, for those who receive the sacraments from
them, receive grace, whereas those who receive the sacraments from those
who are cut off from the Church, do not receive grace, because they sin
in so doing, except in the case of Baptism, which, in cases of necessity,
may be received even from one who is excommunicate.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[5] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: The prayer which the wicked priest proffers on his own
account, is not efficacious: but that which he makes as a minister of the
Church, is efficacious through the merit of Christ. Yet in both ways the
priest's prayer should profit those who are subject to him.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[6] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether those who are schismatics, heretics, excommunicate, suspended or
degraded have the use of the keys?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[6] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that those who are schismatics, heretics,
excommunicate, suspended or degraded have the use of the keys. For just
as the power of the keys results from orders, so does the power of
consecration. But the above cannot lose the use of the power of
consecration, since if they do consecrate it is valid, though they sin in
doing so. Therefore neither can they lose the use of the keys.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[6] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, any active spiritual power in one who has the use of his
free-will can be exercised by him when he wills. Now the power of the
keys remains in the aforesaid, for, since it is only conferred with
orders, they would have to be reordained when they return to the Church.
Therefore, since it is an active power, they can exercise it when they
will.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[6] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, spiritual grace is hindered by guilt more than by
punishment. Now excommunication, suspension and degradation are
punishments. Therefore, since a man does not lose the use of the keys on
account of guilt, it seems that he does not lose it on account of the
aforesaid.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[6] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, Augustine says (Tract. cxxi in Joan.) that the "charity
of the Church forgives sins." Now it is the charity of the Church which
unites its members. Since therefore the above are disunited from the
Church, it seems that they have not the use of the keys in remitting sins.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[6] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, no man is absolved from sin by sinning. Now it is a sin for
anyone to seek absolution of his sins from the above, for he disobeys
the Church in so doing. Therefore he cannot be absolved by them: and so
the same conclusion follows.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[6] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, In all the above the power of the keys remains as to its
essence, but its use is hindered on account of the lack of matter. For
since the use of the keys requires in the user authority over the person
on whom they are used, as stated above (Q[17], A[2], ad 2), the proper
matter on whom one can exercise the use of the keys is a man under one's
authority. And since it is by appointment of the Church that one man has
authority over another, so a man may be deprived of his authority over
another by his ecclesiastical superiors. Consequently, since the Church
deprives heretics, schismatics and the like, by withdrawing their
subjects from them either altogether or in some respect, in so far as
they are thus deprived, they cannot have the use of the keys.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[6] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The matter of the sacrament of the Eucharist, on which the
priest exercises his power, is not a man but wheaten bread, and in
Baptism, the matter is simply a man. Wherefore, just as, were a heretic
to be without wheaten bread, he could not consecrate, so neither can a
prelate absolve if he be deprived of his authority, yet he can baptize
and consecrate, albeit to his own damnation.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[6] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The assertion is true, provided matter be not lacking as it
is in the case in point.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[19] A[6] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Sin, of itself, does not remove matter, as certain
punishments do: so that punishment is a hindrance not because it is
contrary to the effect, but for the reason stated.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[20] Out. Para. 1/1
OF THOSE ON WHOM THE POWER OF THE KEYS CAN BE EXERCISED (THREE ARTICLES)
We must now consider those on whom the power of the keys can be
exercised. Under this head there are three points of inquiry:
(1) Whether a priest can use the key, which he has, on any man?
(2) Whether a priest can always absolve his subject?
(3) Whether anyone can use the keys on his superior?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[20] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether a priest can use the key which he has, on any man?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[20] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that a priest can use the key which he has, on any
man. For the power of the keys was bestowed on priests by Divine
authority in the words: "Receive ye the Holy Ghost; whose sins you shall
forgive, they are forgiven them" (Jn. 20:22,23). But this was said
without any restriction. Therefore he that has the key, can use it on any
without restriction.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[20] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, a material key that opens one lock, opens all locks of
the same pattern. Now every sin of every man is the same kind of obstacle
against entering into heaven. Therefore if a priest can, by means of the
key which he has, absolve one man, he can do the same for all others.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[20] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, the priesthood of the New Testament is more perfect than
that of the Old Testament. But the priest of the Old Testament could use
the power which he had of discerning between different kinds of leprosy,
with regard to all indiscriminately. Much more therefore can the priest
of the Gospel use his power with regard to all.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[20] A[1] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, It is written in the Appendix of Gratian: "It is not
lawful for every priest to loose or bind another priest's parishioner."
Therefore a priest cannot absolve everybody.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[20] A[1] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, judgment in spiritual matters should be better regulated than
in temporal matters. But in temporal matters a judge cannot judge
everybody. Therefore, since the use of the keys is a kind of judgment, it
is not within the competency of a priest to use his key with regard to
everyone.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[20] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, That which has to do with singular matters is not equally
in the power of all. Thus, even as besides the general principles of
medicine, it is necessary to have physicians, who adapt those general
principles to individual patients or diseases, according to their various
requirements, so in every kingdom, besides that one who proclaims the
universal precepts of law, there is need for others to adapt those
precepts to individual cases, according as each case demands. For this
reason, in the heavenly hierarchy also, under the Powers who rule
indiscriminately, a place is given to the Principalities, who are
appointed to individual kingdoms, and to the Angels who are given charge
over individual men, as we have explained above (FP, Q[113], AA[1],2).
Consequently there should be a like order of authority in the Church
Militant, so that an indiscriminate authority over all should be vested
in one individual, and that there should be others under him, having
distinct authority over various people. Now the use of the keys implies a
certain power to exercise authority, whereby the one on whom the keys are
used, becomes the proper matter of that act. Therefore he that has power
over all indiscriminately, can use the keys on all, whereas those who
have received authority over distinct persons, cannot use the keys on
everyone, but only on those over whom they are appointed, except in cases
of necessity, when the sacraments should be refused to no one.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[20] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: A twofold power is required in order to absolve from sins,
namely, power of order and power of jurisdiction. The former power is
equally in all priests, but not the latter. And therefore, when our Lord
(Jn. 20:23) gave all the apostles in general, the power of forgiving
sins, this is to be understood of the power which results from receiving
orders, wherefore these words are addressed to priests when they are
ordained. But to Peter in particular He gave the power of forgiving sins
(Mt. 16:19), that we may understand that he has the power of jurisdiction
before the others. But the power of orders, considered in itself, extends
to all who can be absolved: wherefore our Lord said indeterminately,
"Whose sins you shall forgive, they are forgiven them," on the
understanding that this power should be used in dependence on the power
given to Peter, according to His appointment.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[20] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: A material key can open only its own lock. nor can any
active force act save on its own matter. Now a man becomes the matter of
the power of order by jurisdiction: and consequently no one can use the
key in respect of another over whom he has not jurisdiction.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[20] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: The people of Israel were one people, and had but one
temple, so that there was no need for a distinction in priestly
jurisdiction, as there is now in the Church which comprises various
peoples and nations.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[20] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether a priest can always absolve his subject?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[20] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that a priest cannot always absolve his subject.
For, as Augustine says (De vera et false Poenitentia [*Work of an unknown
author]), "no man should exercise the priestly office, unless he be free
from those things which he condemns in others." But a priest might happen
to share in a sin committed by his subject, e.g. by knowledge of a woman
who is his subject. Therefore it seems that he cannot always use the
power of the keys on his subjects.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[20] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, by the power of the keys a man is healed of all his
shortcomings. Now it happens sometimes that a sin has attached to it a
defect of irregularity or a sentence of excommunication, from which a
simple priest cannot absolve. Therefore it seems that he cannot use the
power of the keys on such as are shackled by these things in the above
manner.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[20] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, the judgment and power of our priesthood was
foreshadowed by the judgment of the ancient priesthood. Now according to
the Law, the lesser judges were not competent to decide all cases, and
had recourse to the higher judges, according to Ex. 24:14: "If any
question shall arise" among you, "you shall refer it to them." It seems,
therefore, that a priest cannot absolve his subject from graver sins, but
should refer him to his superior.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[20] A[2] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, Whoever has charge of the principal has charge of the
accessory. Now priests are charged with the dispensation of the Eucharist
to their subjects, to which sacrament the absolution of sins is
subordinate [*Cf. Q[17], A[2], ad 1]. Therefore, as far as the power of
the keys is concerned, a priest can absolve his subject from any sins
whatever.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[20] A[2] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, grace, however small, removes all sin. But a priest dispenses
sacraments whereby grace is given. Therefore, as far as the power of the
keys is concerned, he can absolve from all sins.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[20] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, The power of order, considered in itself, extends to the
remission of all sins. But since, as stated above, the use of this power
requires jurisdiction which inferiors derive from their superiors, it
follows that the superior can reserve certain matters to himself, the
judgment of which he does not commit to his inferior; otherwise any
simple priest who has jurisdiction can absolve from any sin. Now there
are five cases in which a simple priest must refer his penitent to his
superior. The first is when a public penance has to be imposed, because
in that case the bishop is the proper minister of the sacrament. The
second is the case of those who are excommunicated when the inferior
priest cannot absolve a penitent through the latter being excommunicated
by his superior. The third case is when he finds that an irregularity has
been contracted, for the dispensation of which he has to have recourse to
his superior. The fourth is the case of arson. The fifth is when it is
the custom in a diocese for the more heinous crimes to be reserved to the
bishop, in order to inspire fear, because custom in these cases either
gives the power or takes it away.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[20] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: In this case the priest should not hear the confession of
his accomplice, with regard to that particular sin, but must refer her to
another: nor should she confess to him but should ask permission to go to
another, or should have recourse to his superior if he refused, both on
account of the danger, and for the sake of less shame. If, however, he
were to absolve her it would be valid*: because when Augustine says that
they should not be guilty of the same sin, he is speaking of what is
congruous, not of what is essential to the sacrament. [*Benedict XIV
declared the absolution of an accomplice "in materia turpi" to be
invalid.]
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[20] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Penance delivers man from all defects of guilt, but not
from all defects of punishment, since even after doing penance for
murder, a man remains irregular. Hence a priest can absolve from a crime,
but for the remission of the punishment he must refer the penitent to the
superior, except in the case of excommunication, absolution from which
should precede absolution from sin, for as long as a man is
excommunicated, he cannot receive any sacrament of the Church.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[20] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: This objection considers those cases in which superiors
reserve the power of jurisdiction to themselves.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[20] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether a man can use the keys with regard to his superior?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[20] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that a man cannot use the keys in respect of a
superior. For every sacramental act requires its proper matter. Now the
proper matter for the use of the keys, is a person who is subject, as
stated above (Q[19], A[6]). Therefore a priest cannot use the keys in
respect of one who is not his subject.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[20] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the Church Militant is an image of the Church
Triumphant. Now in the heavenly Church an inferior angel never cleanses,
enlightens or perfects a higher angel. Therefore neither can an inferior
priest exercise on a superior a hierarchical action such as absolution.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[20] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, the judgment of Penance should be better regulated than
the judgment of an external court. Now in the external court an inferior
cannot excommunicate or absolve his superior. Therefore, seemingly,
neither can he do so in the penitential court.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[20] A[3] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, The higher prelate is also "compassed with infirmity,"
and may happen to sin. Now the power of the keys is the remedy for sin.
Therefore, since he cannot use the key on himself, for he cannot be both
judge and accused at the same time, it seems that an inferior can use the
power of the keys on him.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[20] A[3] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, absolution which is given through the power of the keys, is
ordained to the reception of the Eucharist. But an inferior can give
Communion to his superior, if the latter asks him to. Therefore he can
use the power of the keys on him if he submit to him.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[20] A[3] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, The power of the keys, considered in itself, is
applicable to all, as stated above (A[2]): and that a priest is unable to
use the keys on some particular person is due to his power being limited
to certain individuals. Therefore he who limited his power can extend it
to whom he wills, so that he can give him power over himself, although he
cannot use the power of the keys on himself, because this power requires
to be exercised on a subject, and therefore on someone else, for no man
can be subject to himself.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[20] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Although the bishop whom a simple priest absolves is his
superior absolutely speaking, yet he is beneath him in so far as he
submits himself as a sinner to him.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[20] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: In the angels there can be no defect by reason of which the
higher angel can submit to the lower, such as there can happen to be
among men; and so there is no comparison.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[20] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/2
Reply OBJ 3: External judgment is according to men, whereas the judgment
of confession is according to God, in Whose sight a man is lessened by
sinning, which is not the case in human prelacy. Therefore just as in
external judgment no man can pass sentence of excommunication on himself,
so neither can he empower another to excommunicate him. On the other
hand, in the tribunal of conscience he can give another the power to
absolve him, though he cannot use that power himself.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[20] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 2/2
It may also be replied that absolution in the tribunal of the
confessional belongs principally to the power of the keys and
consequently to the power of jurisdiction, whereas excommunication
regards jurisdiction exclusively. And, as to the power of orders, all
are equal, but not as to jurisdiction. Wherefore there is no comparison.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[21] Out. Para. 1/2
OF THE DEFINITION, CONGRUITY AND CAUSE OF EXCOMMUNICATION (FOUR ARTICLES)
We must now treat of excommunication: we shall consider: (1) the
definition, congruity and cause of excommunication; (2) who has the power
to excommunicate; (3) communication with excommunicated persons; (4)
absolution from excommunication.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[21] Out. Para. 2/2
Under the first head there are four points of inquiry:
(1) Whether excommunication is suitably defined?
(2) Whether the Church should excommunicate anyone?
(3) Whether anyone should be excommunicated for inflicting temporal harm?
(4) Whether an excommunication unjustly pronounced has any effect?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[21] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether excommunication is suitably defined as separation from the
communion of the Church, etc?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[21] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that excommunication is unsuitably defined by some
thus: "Excommunication is separation from the communion of the Church, as
to fruit and general suffrages." For the suffrages of the Church avail
for those for whom they are offered. But the Church prays for those who
are outside the Church, as, for instance, for heretics and pagans.
Therefore she prays also for the excommunicated, since they are outside
the Church, and so the suffrages of the Church avail for them.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[21] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, no one loses the suffrages of the Church except by his
own fault. Now excommunication is not a fault, but a punishment.
Therefore excommunication does not deprive a man of the general suffrages
of the Church.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[21] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, the fruit of the Church seems to be the same as the
Church's suffrages, for it cannot mean the fruit of temporal goods, since
excommunication does not deprive a man of these. Therefore there is no
reason for mentioning both.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[21] A[1] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, there is a kind of excommunication called minor*, by
which man is not deprived of the suffrages of the Church. [*Minor
excommunication is no longer recognized by Canon Law.] Therefore this
definition is unsuitable.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[21] A[1] Body Para. 1/2
I answer that, When a man enters the Church by Baptism, he is admitted
to two things, viz. the body of the faithful and the participation of the
sacraments: and this latter presupposes the former, since the faithful
are united together in the participation of the sacraments. Consequently
a person may be expelled from the Church in two ways. First, by being
deprived merely of the participation of the sacraments, and this is the
minor excommunication. Secondly, by being deprived of both, and this is
the major excommunication, of which the above is the definition. Nor can
there be a third, consisting in the privation of communion with the
faithful, but not of the participation of the sacraments, for the reason
already given, because, to wit, the faithful communicate together in the
sacraments. Now communion with the faithful is twofold. One consists in
spiritual things, such as their praying for one another, and meeting
together for the reception of sacred things; while another consists in
certain legitimate bodily actions. These different manners of communion
are signified in the verse which declares that those who are
excommunicate are deprived of---
"os, orare, vale, communio, mensa."
"Os," i.e. we must not give them tokens of goodwill; "orare," i.e. we
must not pray with them; "vale," we must not give them marks of respect;
"communio," i.e. we must not communicate with them in the sacraments;
"mensa," i.e. we must not take meals with them. Accordingly the above
definition includes privation of the sacraments in the words "as to the
fruit," and from partaking together with the faithful in spiritual
things, in the words, "and the general prayers of the Church."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[21] A[1] Body Para. 2/2
Another definition is given which expresses the privation of both kinds
of acts, and is as follows: "Excommunication is the privation of all
lawful communion with the faithful."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[21] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Prayers are said for unbelievers, but they do not receive
the fruit of those prayers unless they be converted to the faith. In like
manner prayers may be offered up for those who are excommunicated, but
not among the prayers that are said for the members of the Church. Yet
they do not receive the fruit so long as they remain under the
excommunication, but prayers are said for them that they may receive the
spirit of repentance, so that they may be loosed from excommunication.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[21] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: One man's prayers profit another in so far as they can
reach to him. Now the action of one man may reach to another in two ways.
First, by virtue of charity which unites all the faithful, making them
one in God, according to Ps. 118:63: "I am a partaker with all them that
fear Thee." Now excommunication does not interrupt this union, since no
man can be justly excommunicated except for a mortal sin, whereby a man
is already separated from charity, even without being excommunicated. An
unjust excommunication cannot deprive a man of charity, since this is one
of the greatest of all goods, of which a man cannot be deprived against
his will. Secondly, through the intention of the one who prays, which
intention is directed to the person he prays for, and this union is
interrupted by excommunication, because by passing sentence of
excommunication, the Church severs a man from the whole body of the
faithful, for whom she prays. Hence those prayers of the Church which are
offered up for the whole Church, do not profit those who are
excommunicated. Nor can prayers be said for them among the members of
the Church as speaking in the Church's name, although a private
individual may say a prayer with the intention of offering it for their
conversion.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[21] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: The spiritual fruit of the Church is derived not only from
her prayers, but also from the sacraments received and from the faithful
dwelling together.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[21] A[1] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: The minor excommunication does not fulfill all the
conditions of excommunication but only a part of them, hence the
definition of excommunication need not apply to it in every respect, but
only in some.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[21] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the Church should excommunicate anyone?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[21] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the Church ought not to excommunicate anyone,
because excommunication is a kind of curse, and we are forbidden to curse
(Rm. 12:14). Therefore the Church should not excommunicate.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[21] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the Church Militant should imitate the Church
Triumphant. Now we read in the epistle of Jude (verse 9) that "when
Michael the Archangel disputing with the devil contended about the body
of Moses, he durst not bring against him the judgment of railing speech,
but said: The Lord command thee." Therefore the Church Militant ought not
to judge any man by cursing or excommunicating him.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[21] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, no man should be given into the hands of his enemies,
unless there be no hope for him. Now by excommunication a man is given
into the hands of Satan, as is clear from 1 Cor. 5:5. Since then we
should never give up hope about anyone in this life, the Church should
not excommunicate anyone.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[21] A[2] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, The Apostle (1 Cor. 5:5) ordered a man to be
excommunicated.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[21] A[2] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, it is written (Mt. 18:17) about the man who refuses to hear the
Church: "Let him be to thee as the heathen or publican." But heathens are
outside the Church. Therefore they also who refuse to hear the Church,
should be banished from the Church by excommunication.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[21] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, The judgment of the Church should be conformed to the
judgment of God. Now God punishes the sinner in many ways, in order to
draw him to good, either by chastising him with stripes, or by leaving
him to himself so that being deprived of those helps whereby he was kept
out of evil, he may acknowledge his weakness, and humbly return to God
Whom he had abandoned in his pride. In both these respects the Church by
passing sentence of excommunication imitates the judgment of God. For by
severing a man from the communion of the faithful that he may blush with
shame, she imitates the judgment whereby God chastises man with stripes;
and by depriving him of prayers and other spiritual things, she imitates
the judgment of God in leaving man to himself, in order that by humility
he may learn to know himself and return to God.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[21] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: A curse may be pronounced in two ways: first, so that the
intention of the one who curses is fixed on the evil which he invokes or
pronounces, and cursing in this sense is altogether forbidden. Secondly,
so that the evil which a man invokes in cursing is intended for the good
of the one who is cursed, and thus cursing is sometimes lawful and
salutary: thus a physician makes a sick man undergo pain, by cutting him,
for instance, in order to deliver him from his sickness.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[21] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The devil cannot be brought to repentance, wherefore the
pain of excommunication cannot do him any good.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[21] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: From the very fact that a man is deprived of the prayers of
the Church, he incurs a triple loss, corresponding to the three things
which a man acquires through the Church's prayers. For they bring an
increase of grace to those who have it, or merit grace for those who have
it not; and in this respect the Master of the Sentences says (Sent. iv,
D, 18): "The grace of God is taken away by excommunication." They also
prove a safeguard of virtue; and in this respect he says that "protection
is taken away," not that the excommunicated person is withdrawn
altogether from God's providence, but that he is excluded from that
protection with which He watches over the children of the Church in a
more special way. Moreover, they are useful as a defense against the
enemy, and in this respect he says that "the devil receives greater power
of assaulting the excommunicated person, both spiritually and
corporally." Hence in the early Church, when men had to be enticed to the
faith by means of outward signs (thus the gift of the Holy Ghost was
shown openly by a visible sign), so too excommunication was evidenced by
a person being troubled in his body by the devil. Nor is it unreasonable
that one, for whom there is still hope, be given over to the enemy, for
he is surrendered, not unto damnation, but unto correction, since the
Church has the power to rescue him from the hands of the enemy, whenever
he is willing.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[21] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether anyone should be excommunicated for inflicting temporal harm?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[21] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that no man should be excommunicated for inflicting
a temporal harm. For the punishment should not exceed the fault. But the
punishment of excommunication is the privation of a spiritual good, which
surpasses all temporal goods. Therefore no man should be excommunicated
for temporal injuries.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[21] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, we should render to no man evil for evil, according to
the precept of the Apostle (Rm. 12:17). But this would be rendering evil
for evil, if a man were to be excommunicated for doing such an injury.
Therefore this ought by no means to be done.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[21] A[3] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, Peter sentenced Ananias and Saphira to death for
keeping back the price of their piece of land (Acts 5:1-10). Therefore it
is lawful for the Church to excommunicate for temporal injuries.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[21] A[3] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, By excommunication the ecclesiastical judge excludes a
man, in a sense, from the kingdom. Wherefore, since he ought not to
exclude from the kingdom others than the unworthy, as was made clear from
the definition of the keys (Q[17], A[2]), and since no one becomes
unworthy, unless, through committing a mortal sin, he lose charity which
is the way leading to the kingdom, it follows that no man should be
excommunicated except for a mortal sin. And since by injuring a man in
his body or in his temporalities, one may sin mortally and act against
charity, the Church can excommunicate a man for having inflicted temporal
injury on anyone. Yet, as excommunication is the most severe punishment,
and since punishments are intended as remedies, according to the
Philosopher (Ethic. ii), and again since a prudent physician begins with
lighter and less risky remedies, therefore excommunication should not be
inflicted, even for a mortal sin, unless the sinner be obstinate, either
by not coming up for judgment, or by going away before judgment is
pronounced, or by failing to obey the decision of the court. For then,
if, after due warning, he refuse to obey, he is reckoned to be obstinate,
and the judge, not being able to proceed otherwise against him, must
excommunicate him.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[21] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: A fault is not measured by the extent of the damage a man
does, but by the will with which he does it, acting against charity.
Wherefore, though the punishment of excommunication exceeds the harm
done, it does not exceed the measure of the sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[21] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: When a man is corrected by being punished, evil is not
rendered to him, but good: since punishments are remedies, as stated
above.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[21] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether an excommunication unjustly pronounced has any effect?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[21] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that an excommunication which is pronounced
unjustly has no effect at all. Because excommunication deprives a man of
the protection and grace of God, which cannot be forfeited unjustly.
Therefore excommunication has no effect if it be unjustly pronounced.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[21] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, Jerome says (on Mt. 16:19: "I will give to thee the
keys"): "It is a pharisaical severity to reckon as really bound or
loosed, that which is bound or loosed unjustly." But that severity was
proud and erroneous. Therefore an unjust excommunication has no effect.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[21] A[4] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, According to Gregory (Hom. xxvi in Evang.), "the
sentence of the pastor is to be feared whether it be just or unjust." Now
there would be no reason to fear an unjust excommunication if it did not
hurt. Therefore, etc.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[21] A[4] Body Para. 1/2
I answer that, An excommunication may be unjust for two reasons. First,
on the part of its author, as when anyone excommunicates through hatred
or anger, and then, nevertheless, the excommunication takes effect,
though its author sins, because the one who is excommunicated suffers
justly, even if the author act wrongly in excommunicating him. Secondly,
on the part of the excommunication, through there being no proper cause,
or through the sentence being passed without the forms of law being
observed. In this case, if the error, on the part of the sentence, be
such as to render the sentence void, this has no effect, for there is no
excommunication; but if the error does not annul the sentence, this takes
effect, and the person excommunicated should humbly submit (which will be
credited to him as a merit), and either seek absolution from the person
who has excommunicated him, or appeal to a higher judge. If, however, he
were to contemn the sentence, he would "ipso facto" sin mortally.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[21] A[4] Body Para. 2/2
But sometimes it happens that there is sufficient cause on the part of
the excommunicator, but not on the part of the excommunicated, as when a
man is excommunicated for a crime which he has not committed, but which
has been proved against him: in this case, if he submit humbly, the merit
of his humility will compensate him for the harm of excommunication.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[21] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Although a man cannot lose God's grace unjustly, yet he can
unjustly lose those things which on our part dispose us to receive grace.
for instance, a man may be deprived of the instruction which he ought to
have. It is in this sense that excommunication is said to deprive a man
of God's grace, as was explained above (A[2], ad 3).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[21] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Jerome is speaking of sin not of its punishments, which can
be inflicted unjustly by ecclesiastical superiors.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] Out. Para. 1/1
OF THOSE WHO CAN EXCOMMUNICATE OR BE EXCOMMUNICATED (SIX ARTICLES)
We must now consider those who can excommunicate or be excommunicated.
Under this head there are six points of inquiry:
(1) Whether every priest can excommunicate?
(2) Whether one who is not a priest can excommunicate?
(3) Whether one who is excommunicated or suspended, can excommunicate?
(4) Whether anyone can excommunicate himself, or an equal, or a superior?
(5) Whether a multitude can be excommunicated?
(6) Whether one who is already excommunicated can be excommunicated
again?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether every priest can excommunicate?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that every priest can excommunicate. For
excommunication is an act of the keys. But every priest has the keys.
Therefore every priest can excommunicate.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, it is a greater thing to loose and bind in the tribunal
of penance than in the tribunal of judgment. But every priest can loose
and bind his subjects in the tribunal of Penance. Therefore every priest
can excommunicate his subjects.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] A[1] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, Matters fraught with danger should be left to the
decision of superiors. Now the punishment of excommunication is fraught
with many dangers, unless it be inflicted with moderation. Therefore it
should not be entrusted to every priest.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, In the tribunal of conscience the plea is between man and
God, whereas in the outward tribunal it is between man and man. Wherefore
the loosing or binding of one man in relation to God alone, belongs to
the tribunal of Penance, whereas the binding or loosing of a man in
relation to other men, belongs to the public tribunal of external
judgment. And since excommunication severs a man from the communion of
the faithful, it belongs to the external tribunal. Consequently those
alone can excommunicate who have jurisdiction in the judicial tribunal.
Hence, of their own authority, only bishops and higher prelates,
according to the more common opinion can excommunicate, whereas parish
priests can do so only by commission or in certain cases, as those of
theft, rapine and the like, in which the law allows them to
excommunicate. Others, however, have maintained that even parish priests
can excommunicate: but the former opinion is more reasonable.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Excommunication is an act of the keys not directly, but
with respect to the external judgment. The sentence of excommunication,
however, though it is promulgated by an external verdict, still, as it
belongs somewhat to the entrance to the kingdom, in so far as the Church
Militant is the way to the Church Triumphant, this jurisdiction whereby a
man is competent to excommunicate, can be called a key. It is in this
sense that some distinguish between the key of orders, which all priests
have, and the key of jurisdiction in the tribunal of judgment, which none
have but the judges of the external tribunal. Nevertheless God bestowed
both on Peter (Mt. 16:19), from whom they are derived by others,
whichever of them they have.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Parish priests have jurisdiction indeed over their
subjects, in the tribunal of conscience, but not in the judicial
tribunal, for they cannot summons them in contentious cases. Hence they
cannot excommunicate, but they can absolve them in the tribunal of
Penance. And though the tribunal of Penance is higher, yet more solemnity
is requisite in the judicial tribunal, because therein it is necessary to
make satisfaction not only to God but also to man.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether those who are not priests can excommunicate?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that those who are not priests cannot
excommunicate. Because excommunication is an act of the keys, as stated
in Sent. iv, D, 18. But those who are not priests have not the keys.
Therefore they cannot excommunicate.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, more is required for excommunication than for absolution
in the tribunal of Penance. But one who is not a priest cannot absolve in
the tribunal of Penance. Neither therefore can he excommunicate.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, Archdeacons, legates and bishops-elect excommunicate,
and yet sometimes they are not priests. Therefore not only priests can
excommunicate.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Priests alone are competent to dispense the sacraments
wherein grace is given: wherefore they alone can loose and bind in the
tribunal of Penance. On the other hand excommunication regards grace, not
directly but consequently, in so far as it deprives a man of the Church's
prayers, by which he is disposed for grace or preserved therein.
Consequently even those who are not priests, provided they have
jurisdiction in a contentious court, can excommunicate.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Though they have not the key of orders, they have the key
of jurisdiction.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: These two are related to one another as something exceeding
and something exceeded [*Cf. A[1], a[2]; Q[24], A[1], ad 1], and
consequently one of them may be within the competency of someone while
the other is not.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether a man who is excommunicated or suspended can excommunicate
another?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that one who is excommunicated or suspended can
excommunicate another. For such a one has lost neither orders nor
jurisdiction, since neither is he ordained anew when he is absolved, nor
is his jurisdiction renewed. But excommunication requires nothing more
than orders or jurisdiction. Therefore even one who is excommunicated or
suspended can excommunicate.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further. it is a greater thing to consecrate the body of Christ
than to excommunicate. But such persons can consecrate. Therefore they
can excommunicate.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] A[3] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, one whose body is bound cannot bind another. But
spiritual gyves are stronger than bodily fetters. Therefore one who is
excommunicated cannot excommunicate another, since excommunication is a
spiritual chain.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] A[3] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Jurisdiction can only be used in relation to another
man. Consequently, since every excommunicated person is severed from the
communion of the faithful, he is deprived of the use of jurisdiction. And
as excommunication requires jurisdiction, an excommunicated person cannot
excommunicate, and the same reason applies to one who is suspended from
jurisdiction. For if he be suspended from orders only, then he cannot
exercise his order, but he can use his jurisdiction, while, on the other
hand, if he be suspended from jurisdiction and not from orders. he cannot
use his jurisdiction, though he can exercise his order: and if he be
suspended from both, he can exercise neither.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Although an excommunicated or suspended person does not
lose his jurisdiction, yet he does lose its use.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The power of consecration results from the power of the
character which is indelible, wherefore, from the very fact that a man
has the character of order, he can always consecrate, though not always
lawfully. It is different with the power of excommunication which results
from jurisdiction, for this can be taken away and bound.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether a man can excommunicate himself, his equal, or his superior?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that a man can excommunicate himself, his equal, or
his superior. For an angel of God was greater than Paul, according to Mt.
11:11: "He that is lesser in the kingdom of heaven is greater then he, a
greater" than whom "hath not risen among men that are born of women." Now
Paul excommunicated an angel from heaven (Gal. 1:8). Therefore a man can
excommunicate his superior.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, sometimes a priest pronounces a general excommunication
for theft or the like. But it might happen that he, or his equal, or a
superior has done such things. Therefore a man can excommunicate himself,
his equal, or a superior.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] A[4] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, a man can absolve his superior or his equal in the
tribunal of Penance, as when a bishop confesses to his subject, or one
priest confesses venial sins to another. Therefore it seems that a man
may also excommunicate his superior, or his equal.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] A[4] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, Excommunication is an act of jurisdiction. But no man
has jurisdiction over himself (since one cannot be both judge and
defendant in the same trial), or over his superior, or over an equal.
Therefore a man cannot excommunicate his superior, or his equal, or
himself.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] A[4] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Since, by jurisdiction, a man is placed above those over
whom he has jurisdiction, through being their judge, it follows that no
man has jurisdiction over himself, his superior, or his equal, and that,
consequently, no one can excommunicate either himself, or his superior,
or his equal.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The Apostle is speaking hypothetically, i.e. supposing an
angel were to sin, for in that case he would not be higher than the
Apostle, but lower. Nor is it absurd that, if the antecedent of a
conditional sentence be impossible, the consequence be impossible also.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: In that case no one would be excommunicated, since no man
has power over his peer.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] A[4] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Loosing and binding in the tribunal of confession affects
our relation to God only, in Whose sight a man from being above another
sinks below him through sin; while on the other hand excommunication is
the affair of an external tribunal in which a man does not forfeit his
superiority on account of sin. Hence there is no comparison between the
two tribunals. Nevertheless, even in the tribunal of confession, a man
cannot absolve himself, or his superior, or his equal, unless the power
to do so be committed to him. This does not apply to venial sins, because
they can be remitted through any sacraments which confer grace, hence
remission of venial sins follows the power of orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] A[5] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether a sentence of excommunication can be passed on a body of men?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] A[5] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that sentence of excommunication can be passed on a
body of men. Because it is possible for a number of people to be united
together in wickedness. Now when a man is obstinate in his wickedness he
should be excommunicated. Therefore a body of men can be excommunicated.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] A[5] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the most grievous effect of an excommunication is
privation of the sacraments of the Church. But sometimes a whole country
is laid under an interdict. Therefore a body of people can be
excommunicated.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] A[5] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, A gloss of Augustine [*Cf. Ep. ccl] on Mt. 12 asserts
that the sovereign and a body of people cannot be excommunicated.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] A[5] Body Para. 1/2
I answer that, No man should be excommunicated except for a mortal sin.
Now sin consists in an act: and acts do not belong to communities, but,
generally speaking, to individuals. Wherefore individual members of a
community can be excommunicated, but not the community itself. And
although sometimes an act belongs to a whole multitude, as when many draw
a boat, which none of them could draw by himself, yet it is not probable
that a community would so wholly consent to evil that there would be no
dissentients. Now God, Who judges all the earth, does not condemn the
just with the wicked (Gn. 18:25). Therefore the Church, who should
imitate the judgments of God, prudently decided that a community should
not be excommunicated, lest the wheat be uprooted together with the tares
and cockle.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] A[5] Body Para. 2/2
The Reply to the First Objection is evident from what has been said.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] A[5] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Suspension is not so great a punishment as excommunication,
since those who are suspended are not deprived of the prayers of the
Church, as the excommunicated are. Wherefore a man can be suspended
without having committed a sin himself, just as a whole kingdom is laid
under an interdict on account of the king's crime. Hence there is no
comparison between excommunication and suspension.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] A[6] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether a man can be excommunicated who is already under sentence of
excommunication?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] A[6] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that a man who is already under sentence of
excommunication cannot be excommunicated any further. For the Apostle
says (1 Cor. 5:12): "What have I to do to judge them that are without?"
Now those who are excommunicated are already outside the Church.
Therefore the Church cannot exercise any further judgment on them, so as
to excommunicate them again.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] A[6] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, excommunication is privation of divine things and of the
communion of the faithful. But when a man has been deprived of a thing,
he cannot be deprived of it again. Therefore one who is excommunicated
cannot be excommunicated again
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] A[6] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, Excommunication is a punishment and a healing medicine.
Now punishments and medicines are repeated when necessary. Therefore
excommunication can be repeated.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] A[6] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, A man who is under sentence of one excommunication, can
be excommunicated again, either by a repetition of the same
excommunication, for his greater confusion, so that he may renounce sin,
or for some other cause. And then there are as many principal
excommunications, as there are causes for his being excommunicated.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] A[6] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The Apostle is speaking of heathens and of other
unbelievers who have no (sacramental) character, whereby they are
numbered among the people of God. But since the baptismal character
whereby a man is numbered among God's people, is indelible, one who is
baptized always belongs to the Church in some way, so that the Church is
always competent to sit in judgment on him.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[22] A[6] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Although privation does not receive more or less in itself,
yet it can, as regards its cause. In this way an excommunication can be
repeated, and a man who has been excommunicated several times is further
from the Church's prayers than one who has been excommunicated only once.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[23] Out. Para. 1/1
OF COMMUNICATION WITH EXCOMMUNICATED PERSONS (THREE ARTICLES)
We must now consider communication with those who are excommunicated.
Under this head there are three points of inquiry:
(1) Whether it is lawful to communicate in matters purely corporal with
one who is excommunicated?
(2) Whether one who communicates with an excommunicated person is
excommunicated?
(3) Whether it is always a mortal sin to communicate with an
excommunicated person in matters not permitted by law?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[23] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether it is lawful, in matters purely corporal, to communicate with an
excommunicated person?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[23] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that it is lawful, in matters purely corporal, to
communicate with an excommunicated person. For excommunication is an act
of the keys. But the power of the keys extends only to spiritual matters.
Therefore excommunication does not prevent one from communicating with
another in matters corporal.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[23] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, "What is instituted for the sake of charity, does not
militate against charity" (Cf. Q[11], A[1], OBJ[1]). But we are bound by
the precept of charity to succor our enemies, which is impossible without
some sort of communication. Therefore it is lawful to communicate with an
excommunicated person in corporal matters.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[23] A[1] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, It is written (1 Cor. 5:11): "With such an one not so
much as to eat."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[23] A[1] Body Para. 1/2
I answer that, Excommunication is twofold: there is minor
excommunication, which deprives a man merely of a share in the
sacraments, but not of the communion of the faithful. Wherefore it is
lawful to communicate with a person lying under an excommunication of
this kind, but not to give him the sacraments. The other is major
excommunication which deprives a man of the sacraments of the Church and
of the communion of the faithful. Wherefore it is not lawful to
communicate with one who lies under such an excommunication. But, since
the Church resorts to excommunication to repair and not to destroy,
exception is made from this general law, in certain matters wherein
communication is lawful, viz. in those which concern salvation, for one
is allowed to speak of such matters with an excommunicated person; and
one may even speak of other matters so as to put him at his ease and to
make the words of salvation more acceptable. Moreover exception is made
in favor of certain people whose business it is to be in attendance on
the excommunicated person, viz. his wife, child, slave, vassal or
subordinate. This, however, is to be understood of children who have not
attained their majority, else they are forbidden to communicate with
their father: and as to the others, the exception applies to them if they
have entered his service before his excommunication, but not if they did
so afterwards.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[23] A[1] Body Para. 2/2
Some understand this exception to apply in the opposite way, viz. that
the master can communicate with his subjects: while others hold the
contrary. At any rate it is lawful for them to communicate with others
in matters wherein they are under an obligation to them, for just as
subjects are bound to serve their master, so is the master bound to look
after his subjects. Again certain cases are excepted; as when the fact of
the excommunication is unknown, or in the case of strangers or travelers
in the country of those who are excommunicated, for they are allowed to
buy from them, or to receive alms from them. Likewise if anyone were to
see an excommunicated person in distress: for then he would be bound by
the precept of charity to assist him. These are all contained in the
following line: "Utility, law, lowliness, ignorance of fact, necessity,"
where "utility" refers to salutary words, "law" to marriage, "lowliness"
to subjection. The others need no explanation.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[23] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Corporal matters are subordinate to spiritual matters.
Wherefore the power which extends to spiritual things, can also extend to
matters touching the body: even as the art which considers the end
commands in matters ordained to the end.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[23] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: In a case where one is bound by the precept of charity to
hold communication, the prohibition ceases, as is clear from what has
been said.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[23] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether a person incurs excommunication for communicating with one who is
excommunicated?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[23] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that a person does not incur excommunication for
communicating with one who is excommunicated. For a heathen or a Jew is
more separated from the Church than a person who is excommunicated. But
one does not incur excommunication for communicating with a heathen or a
Jew. Neither, therefore, does one for communicating with an
excommunicated Christian.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[23] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, if a man incurs excommunication for communicating with
an excommunicated person, for the same reason a third would incur
excommunication for communicating with him, and thus one might go on
indefinitely, which would seem absurd. Therefore one does not incur
excommunication for communicating with one who is excommunicated.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[23] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, An excommunicated person is banished from communion.
Therefore whoever communicates with him leaves the communion of the
Church: and hence he seems to be excommunicated.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[23] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, A person may incur excommunication in two ways. First, so
that the excommunication includes both himself and whosoever communicates
with him: and then, without any doubt, whoever communicates with him,
incurs a major excommunication. Secondly, so that the excommunication is
simply pronounced on him; and then a man may communicate with him either
in his crime, by counsel, help or favor, in which case again he incurs
the major excommunication, or he may communicate with him in other things
by speaking to him, greeting him, or eating with him, in which case he
incurs the minor excommunication.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[23] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The Church has no intention of correcting unbelievers as
well as the faithful who are under her care: hence she does not sever
those, whom she excommunicates, from the fellowship of unbelievers, as
she does from the communion of the faithful over whom she exercises a
certain power.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[23] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: It is lawful to hold communion with one who has incurred a
minor excommunication, so that excommunication does not pass on to a
third person.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[23] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether it is always a mortal sin to communicate with an excommunicated
person in other cases than those in which it is allowed?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[23] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that it is always a mortal sin to hold communion
with an excommunicated person in other cases than those in which it is
allowed. Because a certain decretal (Cap. Sacris: De his quae vi, metuve,
etc.) declares that "not even through fear of death should anyone hold
communion with an excommunicated person, since one ought to die rather
than commit a mortal sin." But this would be no reason unless it were
always a mortal sin to hold communion with an excommunicated person.
Therefore, etc.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[23] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, it is a mortal sin to act against a commandment of the
Church. But the Church forbids anyone to hold communion with an
excommunicated person. Therefore it is a mortal sin to hold communion
with one who is excommunicated.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[23] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, no man is debarred from receiving the Eucharist on
account of a venial sin. But a man who holds communion with an
excommunicated person, outside those cases in which it is allowed, is
debarred from receiving the Eucharist, since he incurs a minor
excommunication. Therefore it is a mortal sin to hold communion with an
excommunicated person, save in those cases in which it is allowed.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[23] A[3] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, no one should incur a major excommunication save for a
mortal sin. Now according to the law (Can. Praecipue, seqq., caus. xi) a
man may incur a major excommunication for holding communion with an
excommunicated person. Therefore it is a mortal sin to hold communion
with one who is excommunicated.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[23] A[3] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, None can absolve a man from mortal sin unless he have
jurisdiction over him. But any priest can absolve a man for holding
communion with those who are excommunicated. Therefore it is not a mortal
sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[23] A[3] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, the measure of the penalty should be according to the measure
of the sin, as stated in Dt. 25:3. Now the punishment appointed by common
custom for holding communion with an excommunicated person is not that
which is inflicted for mortal sin, but rather that which is due for
venial sin. Therefore it is not a mortal sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[23] A[3] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Some hold that it is always a mortal sin to hold
communion with an excommunicated person, by word or in any of the
forbidden ways mentioned above (A[2]), except in those cases allowed by
law (Cap. Quoniam). But since it seems very hard that a man should be
guilty of a mortal sin by uttering just a slight word to an
excommunicated person, and that by excommunicating a person one would
endanger the salvation of many, and lay a snare which might turn to one's
own hurt, it seems to others more probable that he is not always guilty
of a mortal sin, but only when he holds communion with him in a criminal
deed, or in an act of Divine worship, or through contempt of the Church.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[23] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: This decretal is speaking of holding communion in Divine
worship. It may also be replied that the same reason applies both to
mortal and venial sin, since just as one cannot do well by committing a
mortal sin, so neither can one by committing a venial sin: so that just
as it is a man's duty to suffer death rather than commit a mortal sin, so
is it his duty to do so sooner than commit a venial sin, inasmuch as it
is his duty to avoid venial sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[23] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The commandment of the Church regards spiritual matters
directly, and legitimate actions as a consequence: hence by holding
communion in Divine worship one acts against the commandment, and commits
a mortal sin; but by holding communion in other matters, one acts beside
the commandment, and sins venially.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[23] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Sometimes a man is debarred from the Eucharist even without
his own fault, as in the case of those who are suspended or under an
interdict, because these penalties are sometimes inflicted on one person
for the sin of another who is thus punished.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[23] A[3] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: Although it is a venial sin to hold communion with one who
is excommunicated, yet to do so obstinately is a mortal sin: and for this
reason one may be excommunicated according to the law.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[24] Out. Para. 1/1
OF ABSOLUTION FROM EXCOMMUNICATION (THREE ARTICLES)
We must now consider absolution from excommunication: under which head
there are three points of inquiry:
(1) Whether any priest can absolve his subject from excommunication?
(2) Whether a man can be absolved from excommunication against his will?
(3) Whether a man can be absolved from one excommunication without being
absolved from another?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[24] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether any priest can absolve his subject from excommunication?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[24] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that any priest can absolve his subject from
excommunication. For the chains of sin are stronger than those of
excommunication. But any priest can absolve his subject from sin.
Therefore much more can he absolve him from excommunication.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[24] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, if the cause is removed the effect is removed. But the
cause of excommunication is a mortal sin. Therefore since any priest can
absolve (his subject) from that mortal sin, he is able likewise to
absolve him from the excommunication.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[24] A[1] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, It belongs to the same power to excommunicate as to
absolve from excommunication. But priests of inferior degree cannot
excommunicate their subjects. Neither, therefore, can they absolve them.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[24] A[1] Body Para. 1/3
I answer that, Anyone can absolve from minor excommunication who can
absolve from the sin of participation in the sin of another. But in the
case of a major excommunication, this is pronounced either by a judge,
and then he who pronounced sentence or his superior can absolve---or it
is pronounced by law, and then the bishop or even a priest can absolve
except in the six cases which the Pope, who is the maker of laws,
reserves to himself: the first is the case of a man who lays hands on a
cleric or a religious; the second is of one who breaks into a church and
is denounced for so doing; the third is of the man who sets fire to a
church and is denounced for the deed; the fourth is of one who knowingly
communicates in the Divine worship with those whom the Pope has
excommunicated by name; the fifth is the case of one who tampers with the
letters of the Holy See; the sixth is the case of one who communicates in
a crime of one who is excommunicated. For he should not be absolved
except by the person who excommunicated him, even though he be not
subject to him, unless, by reason of the difficulty of appearing before
him, he be absolved by the bishop or by his own priest, after binding
himself by oath to submit to the command of the judge who pronounced the
excommunication on him.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[24] A[1] Body Para. 2/3
There are however eight exceptions to the first case: (1) In the hour of
death, when a person can be absolved by any priest from any
excommunication; (2) if the striker be the doorkeeper of a man in
authority, and the blow be given neither through hatred nor of set
purpose; (3) if the striker be a woman; (4) if the striker be a servant,
whose master is not at fault and would suffer from his absence; (5) if a
religious strike a religious, unless he strike him very grievously; (6)
if the striker be a poor man; (7) if he be a minor, an old man, or an
invalid; (8) if there be a deadly feud between them.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[24] A[1] Body Para. 3/3
There are, besides, seven cases in which the person who strikes a cleric
does not incur excommunication: (1) if he do it for the sake of
discipline, as a teacher or a superior; (2) if it be done for fun; (3) if
the striker find the cleric behaving with impropriety towards his wife
his mother, his sister or his daughter; (4) if he return blow for blow at
once; (5) if the striker be not aware that he is striking a cleric; (6)
if the latter be guilty of apostasy after the triple admonition; (7) if
the cleric exercise an act which is altogether contrary to the clerical
life, e.g. if he become a soldier, or if he be guilty of bigamy [*Namely,
that which is known by canonists as "similar bigamy"].
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[24] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Although the chains of sin are in themselves greater than
those of excommunication, yet in a certain respect the chains of
excommunication are greater, inasmuch as they bind a man not only in the
sight of God, but also in the eye of the Church. Hence absolution from
excommunication requires jurisdiction in the external forum, whereas
absolution from sin does not. Nor is there need of giving one's word by
oath, as in the case of absolution from excommunication, because, as the
Apostle declares (Heb. 6:16), controversies between men are decided by
oath.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[24] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: As an excommunicated person has no share in the sacraments
of the Church, a priest cannot absolve him from his guilt, unless he be
first absolved from excommunication.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[24] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether anyone can be absolved against his will?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[24] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that no man can be absolved against his will. For
spiritual things are not conferred on anyone against his will. Now
absolution from excommunication is a spiritual favor. Therefore it cannot
be granted to a man against his will.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[24] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the cause of excommunication is contumacy. But when,
through contempt of the excommunication, a man is unwilling to be
absolved, he shows a high degree of contumacy. Therefore he cannot be
absolved.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[24] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, Excommunication can be pronounced on a man against his
will. Now things that happen to a man against his will, can be removed
from him against his will, as in the case of the goods of fortune.
Therefore excommunication can be removed from a man against his will.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[24] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Evil of fault and evil of punishment differ in this, that
the origin of fault is within us, since all sin is voluntary, whereas the
origin of punishment is sometimes without, since punishment does not need
to be voluntary, in fact the nature of punishment is rather to be against
the will. Wherefore, just as a man commits no sin except willingly, so no
sin is forgiven him against his will. On the other hand just as a person
can be excommunicated against his will, so can he be absolved therefrom.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[24] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The assertion is true of those spiritual goods which depend
on our will, such as the virtues, which we cannot lose unwillingly; for
knowledge, although a spiritual good, can be lost by a man against his
will through sickness. Hence the argument is not to the point.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[24] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: It is possible for excommunication to be removed from a man
even though he be contumacious, if it seem to be for the good of the man
for whom the excommunication was intended as a medicine.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[24] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether a man can be absolved from one excommunication without being
absolved from all?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[24] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that a man cannot be absolved from one
excommunication without being absolved from all. For an effect should be
proportionate to its cause. Now the cause of excommunication is a sin.
Since then a man cannot be absolved from one sin without being absolved
from all, neither can this happen as regards excommunication.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[24] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, absolution from excommunication is pronounced in the
Church. But a man who is under the ban of one excommunication is outside
the Church. Therefore so long as one remains, a man cannot be loosed from
another.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[24] A[3] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, Excommunication is a punishment. Now a man can be
loosed from one punishment, while another remains. Therefore a man can be
loosed from one excommunication and yet remain under another.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[24] A[3] Body Para. 1/2
I answer that, Excommunications are not connected together in any way,
and so it is possible for a man to be absolved from one, and yet remain
under another.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[24] A[3] Body Para. 2/2
It must be observed however that sometimes a man lies under several
excommunications pronounced by one judge; and then, when he is absolved
from one, he is understood to be absolved from all, unless the contrary
be expressed, or unless he ask to be absolved from excommunication on one
count only, whereas he was excommunicated under several. On the other
hand sometimes a man lies under several sentences of excommunication
pronounced by several judges; and then, when absolved from one
excommunication, he is not therefore absolved from the others, unless at
his prayer they all confirm his absolution, or unless they all depute one
to absolve him.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[24] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: All sins are connected together in aversion from God, which
is incompatible with the forgiveness of sin: wherefore one sin cannot be
forgiven without another. But excommunications have no such connection.
Nor again is absolution from excommunication hindered by contrariety of
the will, as stated above (A[2]). Hence the argument does not prove.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[24] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Just as such a man was for several reasons outside the
Church so is it possible for his separation to be removed on one count
and to remain on another.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[25] Out. Para. 1/2
OF INDULGENCES (THREE ARTICLES)
We must now consider indulgence: (1) in itself; (2) those who grant
indulgence; (3) those who receive it.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[25] Out. Para. 2/2
Under the first head there are three points of inquiry:
(1) Whether an indulgence remits any part of the punishment due for the
satisfaction of sins?
(2) Whether indulgences are as effective as they claim to be?
(3) Whether an indulgence should be granted for temporal assistance?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[25] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether an indulgence can remit any part of the punishment due for the
satisfaction of sins?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[25] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that an indulgence cannot remit any part of the
punishment due for the satisfaction of sins. Because a gloss on 2 Tim.
2:13, "He cannot deny Himself," says: "He would do this if He did not
keep His word." Now He said (Dt. 25:2): "According to the measure of the
sin shall the measure also of the stripes be." Therefore nothing can be
remitted from the satisfactory punishment which is appointed according to
the measure of sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[25] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, an inferior cannot absolve from an obligation imposed by
his superior. But when God absolves us from sin He binds us to temporal
punishment, as Hugh of St. Victor declares (Tract. vi Sum. Sent. [*Of
doubtful authenticity]). Therefore no man can absolve from that
punishment, by remitting any part of it.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[25] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, the granting of the sacramental effect without the
sacraments belongs to the power of excellence. Now none but Christ has
the power of excellence in the sacraments. Since then satisfaction is a
part of the sacrament of Penance, conducing to the remission of the
punishment due, it seems that no mere man can remit the debt of
punishment without satisfaction.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[25] A[1] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, the power of the ministers of the Church was given them,
not "unto destruction," but "unto edification" (2 Cor. 10:8). But it
would be conducive to destruction, if satisfaction, which was intended
for our good, inasmuch as it serves for a remedy, were done away with.
Therefore the power of the ministers of the Church does not extend to
this.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[25] A[1] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, It is written (2 Cor. 2:10): "For, what I have
pardoned, if I have pardoned anything, for your sakes have I done it in
the person of Christ," and a gloss adds: i.e. "as though Christ Himself
had pardoned." But Christ could remit the punishment of a sin without any
satisfaction, as evidenced in the case of the adulterous woman (Jn. 8).
Therefore Paul could do so likewise. Therefore the Pope can too, since
his power in the Church is not less than Paul's.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[25] A[1] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, the universal Church cannot err; since He Who "was heard for
His reverence" (Heb. 5:7) said to Peter, on whose profession of faith the
Church was founded (Lk. 22:32): "I have prayed for thee that thy faith
fail not." Now the universal Church approves and grants indulgences.
Therefore indulgences have some value.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[25] A[1] Body Para. 1/3
I answer that, All admit that indulgences have some value, for it would
be blasphemy to say that the Church does anything in vain. But some say
that they do not avail to free a man from the debt of punishment which he
has deserved in Purgatory according to God's judgment, and that they
merely serve to free him from the obligation imposed on him by the priest
as a punishment for his sins, or from the canonical penalties he has
incurred. But this opinion does not seem to be true. First, because it is
expressly opposed to the privilege granted to Peter, to whom it was said
(Mt. 16:19) that whatsoever he should loose on earth should be loosed
also in heaven. Wherefore whatever remission is granted in the court of
the Church holds good in the court of God. Moreover the Church by
granting such indulgences would do more harm than good, since, by
remitting the punishment she had enjoined on a man, she would deliver him
to be punished more severely in Purgatory.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[25] A[1] Body Para. 2/3
Hence we must say on the contrary that indulgences hold good both in the
Church's court and in the judgment of God, for the remission of the
punishment which remains after contrition, absolution, and confession,
whether this punishment be enjoined or not. The reason why they so avail
is the oneness of the mystical body in which many have performed works of
satisfaction exceeding the requirements of their debts; in which, too,
many have patiently borne unjust tribulations whereby a multitude of
punishments would have been paid, had they been incurred. So great is the
quantity of such merits that it exceeds the entire debt of punishment due
to those who are living at this moment: and this is especially due to the
merits of Christ: for though He acts through the sacraments, yet His
efficacy is nowise restricted to them, but infinitely surpasses their
efficacy.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[25] A[1] Body Para. 3/3
Now one man can satisfy for another, as we have explained above (Q[13],
A[2]). And the saints in whom this super-abundance of satisfactions is
found, did not perform their good works for this or that particular
person, who needs the remission of his punishment (else he would have
received this remission without any indulgence at all), but they
performed them for the whole Church in general, even as the Apostle
declares that he fills up "those things that are wanting of the
sufferings of Christ . . . for His body, which is the Church" to whom he
wrote (Col. 1:24). These merits, then, are the common property of the
whole Church. Now those things which are the common property of a number
are distributed to the various individuals according to the judgment of
him who rules them all. Hence, just as one man would obtain the remission
of his punishment if another were to satisfy for him, so would he too if
another's satisfactions be applied to him by one who has the power to do
so.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[25] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The remission which is granted by means of indulgences does
not destroy the proportion between punishment and sin, since someone has
spontaneously taken upon himself the punishment due for another's guilt,
as explained above.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[25] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: He who gains an indulgence is not, strictly speaking,
absolved from the debt of punishment, but is given the means whereby he
may pay it.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[25] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: The effect of sacramental absolution is the removal of a
man's guilt, an effect which is not produced by indulgences. But he who
grants indulgences pays the debt of punishment which a man owes, out of
the common stock of the Church's goods, as explained above.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[25] A[1] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: Grace affords a better remedy for the avoidance of sin than
does habituation to (good) works. And since he who gains an indulgence is
disposed to grace through the love which he conceives for the cause for
which the indulgence is granted, it follows that indulgences provide a
remedy against sin. Consequently it is not harmful to grant indulgences
unless this be done without discretion. Nevertheless those who gain
indulgences should be advised, not, on this account, to omit the
penitential works imposed on them, so that they may derive a remedy from
these also, even though they may be quit of the debt of punishment; and
all the more, seeing that they are often more in debt than they think.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[25] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether indulgences are as effective as they claim to be?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[25] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that indulgences are not as effective as they claim
to be. For indulgences have no effect save from the power of the keys.
Now by the power of the keys, he who has that power can only remit some
fixed part of the punishment due for sin, after taking into account the
measure of the sin and of the penitent's sorrow. Since then indulgences
depend on the mere will of the grantor, it seems that they are not as
effective as they claim to be.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[25] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the debt of punishment keeps man back from the
attainment of glory, which he ought to desire above all things. Now, if
indulgences are as effective as they claim to be, a man by setting
himself to gain indulgences might become immune from all debt of temporal
punishment. Therefore it would seem that a man ought to put aside all
other kinds of works, and devote himself to gain indulgences.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[25] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, sometimes an indulgence whereby a man is remitted a
third part of the punishment due for his sins is granted if he contribute
towards the erection of a certain building. If, therefore, indulgences
produce the effect which is claimed for them, he who gives a penny, and
then another, and then again another, would obtain a plenary absolution
from all punishment due for his sins, which seems absurd.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[25] A[2] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, sometimes an indulgence is granted, so that for visiting
a church a man obtains a seven years' remission. If, then, an indulgence
avails as much as is claimed for it a man who lives near that church, or
the clergy attached thereto who go there every day, obtain as much
indulgence as one who comes from a distance (which would appear unjust);
moreover, seemingly, they would gain the indulgence several times a day,
since they go there repeatedly.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[25] A[2] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, to remit a man's punishment beyond a just estimate seems
to amount to the same as to remit it without reason; because in so far as
he exceeds that estimate, he limits the compensation. Now he who grants
an indulgence cannot without cause remit a man's punishment either wholly
or partly, even though the Pope were to say to anyone: "I remit to all
the punishment you owe for your sins." Therefore it seems that he cannot
remit anything beyond the just estimate. Now indulgences are often
published which exceed that just estimate. Therefore they do not avail as
much as is claimed for them.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[25] A[2] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, It is written (Job 13:7): "Hath God any need of your
lie, that you should speak deceitfully for Him?" Therefore the Church, in
publishing indulgences, does not lie; and so they avail as much as is
claimed for them.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[25] A[2] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, the Apostle says (1 Cor. 15:14): "If . . . our preaching is
vain, your faith is also vain." Therefore whoever utters a falsehood in
preaching, so far as he is concerned, makes faith void. and so sins
mortally. If therefore indulgences are not as effective as they claim to
be, all who publish indulgences would commit a mortal sin: which is
absurd.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[25] A[2] Body Para. 1/5
I answer that, on this point there are many opinions. For some maintain
that indulgences have not the efficacy claimed for them, but that they
simply avail each individual in proportion to his faith and devotion. And
consequently those who maintain this, say that the Church publishes her
indulgences in such a way as, by a kind of pious fraud, to induce men to
do well, just as a mother entices her child to walk by holding out an
apple. But this seems a very dangerous assertion to make. For as
Augustine states (Ep. ad Hieron. lxxviii), "if any error were discovered
in Holy Writ, the authority of Holy Writ would perish." In like manner,
if any error were to be found in the Church's preaching, her doctrine
would have no authority in settling questions of faith.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[25] A[2] Body Para. 2/5
Hence others have maintained that indulgences avail as much as is
claimed for them, according to a just estimate, not of him who grants
it---who perhaps puts too high a value on it---nor of the recipient---for
he may prize too highly the gift he receives, but a just estimate
according to the estimate of good men who consider the condition of the
person affected, and the utility and needs of the Church, for the
Church's needs are greater at one time than at another. Yet, neither,
seemingly, can this opinion stand. First, because in that case
indulgences would no longer be a remission, but rather a mere
commutation. Moreover the preaching of the Church would not be excused
from untruth, since, at times, indulgences are granted far in excess of
the requirements of this just estimate, taking into consideration all the
aforesaid conditions, as, for example, when the Pope granted to anyone
who visited a certain church, an indulgence of seven years, which
indulgence was granted by Blessed Gregory for the Roman Stations.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[25] A[2] Body Para. 3/5
Hence others say that the quantity of remission accorded in an
indulgence is not to be measured by the devotion of the recipient, as the
first opinion suggested, nor according to the quantity of what is given,
as the second opinion held; but according to the cause for which the
indulgence is granted, and according to which a person is held deserving
of obtaining such an indulgence. Thus according as a man approached near
to that cause, so would he obtain remission in whole or in part. But
neither will this explain the custom of the Church, who assigns, now a
greater, now a lesser indulgence, for the same cause: thus, under the
same circumstances, now a year's indulgence, now one of only forty days,
according to the graciousness of the Pope, who grants the indulgence, is
granted to those who visit a church. Wherefore the amount of the
remission granted by the indulgence is not to be measured by the cause
for which a person is worthy of an indulgence.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[25] A[2] Body Para. 4/5
We must therefore say otherwise that the quantity of an effect is
proportionate to the quantity of the cause. Now the cause of the
remission of punishment effected by indulgences is no other than the
abundance of the Church's merits, and this abundance suffices for the
remission of all punishment. The effective cause of the remission is not
the devotion, or toil, or gift of the recipient; nor, again, is it the
cause for which the indulgence was granted. We cannot, then, estimate the
quantity of the remission by any of the foregoing, but solely by the
merits of the Church---and these are always superabundant. Consequently,
according as these merits are applied to a person so does he obtain
remission. That they should be so applied demands, firstly, authority to
dispense this treasure. secondly, union between the recipient and Him Who
merited it---and this is brought about by charity; thirdly, there is
required a reason for so dispensing this treasury, so that the intention,
namely, of those who wrought these meritorious works is safeguarded,
since they did them for the honor of God and for the good of the Church
in general. Hence whenever the cause assigned tends to the good of the
Church and the honor of God, there is sufficient reason for granting an
indulgence.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[25] A[2] Body Para. 5/5
Hence, according to others, indulgences have precisely the efficacy
claimed for them, provided that he who grants them have the authority,
that the recipient have charity, and that, as regards the cause, there be
piety which includes the honor of God and the profit of our neighbor. Nor
in this view have we "too great a market of the Divine mercy" [*St.
Bonaventure, Sent. iv, D, 20], as some maintain, nor again does it
derogate from Divine justice, for no punishment is remitted, but the
punishment of one is imputed to another.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[25] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: As stated above (Q[19], A[3]) there are two keys, the key
of orders and the key of jurisdiction. The key of orders is a
sacramental: and as the effects of the sacraments are fixed, not by men
but by God, the priest cannot decide in the tribunal of confession how
much shall be remitted by means of the key of orders from the punishment
due; it is God Who appoints the amount to be remitted. On the other hand
the key of jurisdiction is not something sacramental, and its effect
depends on a man's decision. The remission granted through indulgences is
the effect of this key, since it does not belong to the dispensation of
the sacraments, but to the distribution of the common property of the
Church: hence it is that legates, even though they be not priests, can
grant indulgences. Consequently the decision of how much punishment is to
be remitted by an indulgence depends on the will of the one who grants
that indulgence. If, however, he remits punishment without sufficient
reason, so that men are enticed to substitute mere nothings, as it were,
for works of penance, he sins by granting such indulgences, although the
indulgence is gained fully.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[25] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Although indulgences avail much for the remission of
punishment, yet works of satisfaction are more meritorious in respect of
the essential reward, which infinitely transcends the remission of
temporal punishment.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[25] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: When an indulgence is granted in a general way to anyone
that helps towards the building of a church, we must understand this to
mean a help proportionate to the giver: and in so far as he approaches to
this, he will gain the indulgence more or less fully. Consequently a poor
man by giving one penny would gain the full indulgence, not so a rich
man, whom it would not become to give so little to so holy and profitable
a work; Just as a king would not be said to help a man if he gave him an
"obol."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[25] A[2] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: A person who lives near the church, and the priest and
clergy of the church, gain the indulgence as much as those who come
perhaps a distance of a thousand days' journey: because the remission, as
stated above, is proportionate, not to the toil, but to the merits which
are applied. Yet he who toils most gains most merit. This, however, is to
be understood of those cases in which an indulgence is given in an
undeterminate manner. For sometimes a distinction is expressed: thus the
Pope at the time of general absolution grants an indulgence of five years
to those who come from across the seas, and one of three years to those
who come from across the mountains, to others an indulgence of one year.
Nor does a person gain the indulgence each time he visits the church
during the term of indulgence, because sometimes it is granted for a
fixed time; thus when it is said, "Whoever visits such and such a church
until such and such a day, shall gain so much indulgence," we must
understand that it can be gained only once. on the other hand if there be
a continual indulgence in a certain church, as the indulgence of forty
days to be gained in the church of the Blessed Peter, then a person
gains the indulgence as often as he visits the church.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[25] A[2] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: An indulgence requires a cause, not as a measure of the
remission of punishment, but in order that the intention of those whose
merits are applied, may reach to this particular individual. Now one
person's good is applied to another in two ways: first, by charity; and
in this way, even without indulgences, a person shares in all the good
deeds done, provided he have charity: secondly, by the intention of the
person who does the good action; and in this way, provided there be a
lawful cause, the intention of a person who has done something for the
profit of the Church, may reach to some individual through indulgences.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[25] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether an indulgence ought to be granted for temporal help?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[25] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that an indulgence ought not to be granted for
temporal help. Because the remission of sins is something spiritual. Now
to exchange a spiritual for a temporal thing is simony. Therefore this
ought not to be done.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[25] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, spiritual assistance is more necessary than temporal.
But indulgences do not appear to be granted for spiritual assistance.
Much less therefore ought they to be granted for temporal help.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[25] A[3] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, stands the common custom of the Church in granting
indulgences for pilgrimages and almsgiving.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[25] A[3] Body Para. 1/2
I answer that, Temporal things are subordinate to spiritual matters,
since we must make use of temporal things on account of spiritual things.
Consequently an indulgence must not be granted for the sake of temporal
matters as such, but in so far as they are subordinate to spiritual
things: such as the quelling of the Church's enemies, who disturb her
peace; or such as the building of a church, of a bridge, and other forms
of almsgiving. It is therefore evident that there is no simony in these
transactions, since a spiritual thing is exchanged, not for a temporal
but for a spiritual commodity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[25] A[3] Body Para. 2/2
Hence the Reply to the First Objection is clear.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[25] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Indulgences can be, and sometimes are, granted even for
purely spiritual matters. Thus Pope Innocent IV granted an indulgence of
ten days to all who prayed for the king of France; and in like manner
sometimes the same indulgence is granted to those who preach a crusade as
to those who take part in it.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[26] Out. Para. 1/1
OF THOSE WHO CAN GRANT INDULGENCES (FOUR ARTICLES)
We must now consider those who can grant indulgences: under which head
there are four points of inquiry:
(1) Whether every parish priest can grant indulgences?
(2) Whether a deacon or another, who is not a priest, can grant
indulgences?
(3) Whether a bishop can grant them?
(4) Whether they can be granted by one who is in mortal sin?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[26] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether every parish priest can grant indulgences?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[26] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that every parish priest can grant indulgences. For
an indulgence derives its efficacy from the superabundance of the
Church's merits. Now there is no congregation without some superabundance
of merits. Therefore every priest, who has charge of a congregation, can
grant indulgences, and, in like manner, so can every prelate.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[26] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, every prelate stands for a multitude, just as an
individual stands for himself. But any individual can assign his own
goods to another and thus offer satisfaction for a third person.
Therefore a prelate can assign the property of the multitude subject to
him, and so it seems that he can grant indulgences.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[26] A[1] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, To excommunicate is less than to grant indulgences. But
a parish priest cannot do the former. Therefore he cannot do the latter.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[26] A[1] Body Para. 1/2
I answer that, Indulgences are effective, in as much as the works of
satisfaction done by one person are applied to another, not only by
virtue of charity, but also by the intention of the person who did them
being directed in some way to the person to whom they are applied. Now a
person's intention may be directed to another in three ways,
specifically, generically and individually. Individually, as when one
person offers satisfaction for another particular person; and thus anyone
can apply his works to another. Specifically, as when a person prays for
the congregation to which he belongs, for the members of his household,
or for his benefactors, and directs his works of satisfaction to the same
intention: in this way the superior of a congregation can apply those
works to some other person, by applying the intention of those who belong
to his congregation to some fixed individual. Generically, as when a
person directs his works for the good of the Church in general; and thus
he who presides over the whole Church can communicate those works, by
applying his intention to this or that individual. And since a man is a
member of a congregation, and a congregation is a part of the Church,
hence the intention of private good includes the intention of the good of
the congregation, and of the good of the whole Church. Therefore he who
presides over the Church can communicate what belongs to an individual
congregation or to an individual man: and he who presides over a
congregation can communicate what belongs to an individual man, but not
conversely. Yet neither the first nor the second communication is called
an indulgence, but only the third; and this for two reasons. First,
because, although those communications loose man from the debt of
punishment in the sight of God, yet he is not freed from the obligation
of fulfilling the satisfaction enjoined, to which he is bound by a
commandment of the Church; whereas the third communication frees man even
from this obligation. Secondly, because in one person or even in one
congregation there is not such an unfailing supply of merits as to be
sufficient both for the one person or congregation and for all others;
and consequently the individual is not freed from the entire debt of
punishment unless satisfaction is offered for him individually, to the
very amount that he owes. On the other hand, in the whole Church there is
an unfailing supply of merits, chiefly on account of the merit of Christ.
Consequently he alone who is at the head of the Church can grant
indulgences. Since, however, the Church is the congregation of the
faithful, and since a congregation of men is of two kinds, the domestic,
composed of members of the same family, and the civil, composed of
members of the same nationality, the Church is like to a civil
congregation, for the people themselves are called the Church; while the
various assemblies, or parishes of one diocese are likened to a
congregation in the various families and services. Hence a bishop alone
is properly called a prelate of the Church, wherefore he alone, like a
bridegroom, receives the ring of the Church. Consequently full power in
the dispensation of the sacraments, and jurisdiction in the public
tribunal, belong to him alone as the public person, but to others by
delegation from him. Those priests who have charge of the people are not
prelates strictly speaking, but assistants, hence, in consecrating
priests the bishop says: "The more fragile we are, the more we need these
assistants": and for this reason they do not dispense all the sacraments.
Hence parish priests, or abbots or other like prelates cannot grant
indulgences.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[26] A[1] Body Para. 2/2
This suffices for the Replies to the Objections.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[26] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether a deacon or another who is not a priest can grant an indulgence?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[26] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that a deacon, or one that is not a priest cannot
grant an indulgence. Because remission of sins is an effect of the keys.
Now none but a priest has the keys. Therefore a priest alone can grant
indulgences.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[26] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, a fuller remission of punishment is granted by
indulgences than by the tribunal of Penance. But a priest alone has power
in the latter, and, therefore, he alone has power in the former.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[26] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, The distribution of the Church's treasury is entrusted
to the same person as the government of the Church. Now this is entrusted
sometimes to one who is not a priest. Therefore he can grant indulgences,
since they derive their efficacy from the distribution of the Church's
treasury.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[26] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, The power of granting indulgences follows jurisdiction,
as stated above (Q[25], A[2]). And since deacons and others, who are not
priests, can have jurisdiction either delegated, as legates, or ordinary,
as bishops-elect, it follows that even those who are not priests can
grant indulgences, although they cannot absolve in the tribunal of
Penance, since this follows the reception of orders. This suffices for
the Replies to the Objections, because the granting of indulgences
belongs to the key of jurisdiction and not to the key of orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[26] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether a bishop can grant indulgences?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[26] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that even a bishop cannot grant indulgences.
Because the treasury of the Church is the common property of the whole
Church. Now the common property of the whole Church cannot be distributed
save by him who presides over the whole Church. Therefore the Pope alone
can grant indulgences.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[26] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, none can remit punishments fixed by law, save the one
who has the power to make the law. Now punishments in satisfaction for
sins are fixed by law. Therefore the Pope alone can remit these
punishments, since he is the maker of the law.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[26] A[3] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, stands the custom of the Church in accordance with
which bishops grant indulgences.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[26] A[3] Body Para. 1/2
I answer that, The Pope has the plenitude of pontifical power, being
like a king in his kingdom: whereas the bishops are appointed to a share
in his solicitude, like judges over each city. Hence them alone the Pope,
in his letters, addresses as "brethren," whereas he calls all others his
"sons." Therefore the plenitude of the power of granting indulgences
resides in the Pope, because he can grant them, as he lists, provided the
cause be a lawful one: while, in bishops, this power resides subject to
the Pope's ordination, so that they can grant them within fixed limits
and not beyond.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[26] A[3] Body Para. 2/2
This suffices for the Replies to the Objections.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[26] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether indulgences can be granted by one who is in mortal sin?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[26] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that indulgences cannot be granted by one who is in
mortal sin. For a stream can no longer flow if cut off from its source.
Now the source of grace which is the Holy Ghost is cut off from one who
is in mortal sin. Therefore such a one can convey nothing to others by
granting indulgences.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[26] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, it is a greater thing to grant an indulgence than to
receive one. But one who is in mortal sin cannot receive an indulgence,
as we shall show presently (Q[27], A[1]). Neither, therefore, can he
grant one.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[26] A[4] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, Indulgences are granted in virtue of the power
conferred on the prelates of the Church. Now mortal sin takes away, not
power but goodness. Therefore one who is in mortal sin can grant
indulgences.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[26] A[4] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, The granting of indulgences belongs to jurisdiction. But
a man does not, through sin, lose jurisdiction. Consequently indulgences
are equally valid, whether they be granted by one who is in mortal sin,
or by a most holy person; since he remits punishment, not by virtue of
his own merits, but by virtue of the merits laid up in the Church's
treasury.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[26] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The prelate who, while in a state of mortal sin, grants an
indulgence, does not pour forth anything of his own, and so it is not
necessary that he should receive an inflow from the source, in order that
he may grant a valid indulgence.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[26] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Further, to grant an indulgence is more than to receive
one, if we consider the power, but it is less, if we consider the
personal profit.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[27] Out. Para. 1/1
OF THOSE WHOM INDULGENCES AVAIL (FOUR ARTICLES)
We must now consider those whom indulgences avail: under which head
there are four points of inquiry:
(1) Whether indulgences avail those who are in mortal sin?
(2) Whether they avail religious?
(3) Whether they avail a person who does not fulfill the conditions for
which the indulgence is given?
(4) Whether they avail him who grants them?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[27] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether an indulgence avails those who are in mortal sin?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[27] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that an indulgence avails those who are in mortal
sin. For one person can merit grace and many other good things for
another, even though he be in mortal sin. Now indulgences derive their
efficacy from the application of the saints' merits to an individual.
Therefore they are effective in one who is in mortal sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[27] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the greater the need, the more room there is for pity.
Now a man who is in mortal sin is in very great need. Therefore all the
more should pity be extended to him by indulgence.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[27] A[1] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, A dead member receives no inflow from the other members
that are living. But one who is in mortal sin, is like a dead member.
Therefore he receives no inflow, through indulgences, from the merits of
living members.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[27] A[1] Body Para. 1/3
I answer that, Some hold that indulgences avail those even who are in
mortal sin, for the acquiring of grace, but not for the remission of
their punishment, since none can be freed from punishment who is not yet
freed from guilt. For he who has not yet been reached by God's operation
unto the remission of guilt, cannot receive the remission of his
punishment from the minister of the Church neither by indulgences nor in
the tribunal of Penance.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[27] A[1] Body Para. 2/3
But this opinion seems to be untrue. Because, although those merits
which are applied by means of an indulgence, might possibly avail a
person so that he could merit grace (by way of congruity and
impetration), yet it is not for this reason that they are applied, but
for the remission of punishment. Hence they do not avail those who are in
mortal sin, and consequently, true contrition and confession are demanded
as conditions for gaining all indulgences. If however the merits were
applied by such a form as this: "I grant you a share in the merits of the
whole Church---or of one congregation, or of one specified person," then
they might avail a person in mortal sin so that he could merit something,
as the foregoing opinion holds.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[27] A[1] Body Para. 3/3
This suffices for the Reply to the First Objection.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[27] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Although he who is in mortal sin is in greater need of
help, yet he is less capable of receiving it.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[27] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether indulgences avail religious?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[27] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that indulgences do not avail religious. For there
is no reason to bring supplies to those who supply others out of their
own abundance. Now indulgences are derived from the abundance of works of
satisfaction to be found in religious. Therefore it is unreasonable for
them to profit by indulgences.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[27] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, nothing detrimental to religious life should be done in
the Church. But, if indulgences were to avail religious, this would be
detrimental to regular discipline, because religious would become lax on
account of indulgences, and would neglect the penances imposed in
chapter. Therefore indulgences do not avail religious.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[27] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, Good brings harm to no man. But the religious life is a
good thing. Therefore it does not take away from religious the profit to
be derived from indulgences.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[27] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Indulgences avail both seculars and religious, provided
they have charity and satisfy the conditions for gaining the indulgences:
for religious can be helped by indulgences no less than persons living in
the world.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[27] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Although religious are in the state of perfection, yet they
cannot live without sin: and so if at times they are liable to punishment
on account of some sin, they can expiate this debt by means of
indulgences. For it is not unreasonable that one who is well off
absolutely speaking, should be in want at times and in some respect, and
thus need to be supplied with what he lacks. Hence it is written (Gal.
6:2): "Bear ye one another's burdens."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[27] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: There is no reason why indulgences should be detrimental to
religious observance, because, as to the reward of eternal life,
religious merit more by observing their rule than by gaining indulgences;
although, as to the remission of punishment, which is a lesser good, they
merit less. Nor again do indulgences remit the punishment enjoined in
chapter, because the chapter is a judicial rather than a penitential
tribunal. hence even those who are not priests hold chapter. Absolution
from punishment enjoined or due for sin is given in the tribunal of
Penance.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[27] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether an indulgence can ever be granted to one who does not fulfill the
conditions required?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[27] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that an indulgence can sometimes be granted to one
who does not fulfill the required conditions. Because when a person is
unable to perform a certain action his will is taken for the deed. Now
sometimes an indulgence is to be gained by giving an alms, which a poor
man is unable to do, though he would do so willingly. Therefore he can
gain the indulgence.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[27] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, one man can make satisfaction for another. Now an
indulgence is directed to the remission of punishment, just as
satisfaction is. Therefore one man can gain an indulgence for another;
and so a man can gain an indulgence without doing that for which the
indulgence is given.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[27] A[3] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, If the cause is removed, the effect is removed. If
therefore a person fails to do that for which an indulgence is granted,
and which is the cause of the indulgence, he does not gain the indulgence.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[27] A[3] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Failing the condition of a grant, no grant ensues. Hence,
as an indulgence is granted on the condition that a person does or gives
a certain thing, if he fails in this, he does not gain the indulgence.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[27] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: This is true of the essential reward, but not of certain
accidental rewards, such as the remission of punishment and the like.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[27] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: A person can by his intention apply his own action to
whomever he lists, and so he can make satisfaction for whomever he
chooses. On the other hand, an indulgence cannot be applied to someone,
except in accordance with the intention of the grantor. Hence, since he
applies it to the doer or giver of a particular action or thing, the doer
cannot transfer this intention to another. If, however, the indulgence
were expressed thus: "Whosoever does this, or for whomsoever this is
done, shall gain so much indulgence," it would avail the person for whom
it is done. Nor would the person who does this action, give the
indulgence to another, but he who grants the indulgence in this form.
�Aquin.: SMT XP Q[27] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether an indulgence avails the person who grants it?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[27] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that an indulgence does not avail him who grants
it. For the granting of an indulgence belongs to jurisdiction. Now no one
can exercise jurisdiction on himself. thus no one can excommunicate
himself. Therefore no one can participate in an indulgence granted by
himself.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[27] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, if this were possible, he who grants an indulgence might
gain the remission of the punishment of all his sins for some small deed,
so that he would sin with impunity, which seems senseless.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[27] A[4] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, to grant indulgences and to excommunicate belong to the
same power. Now a man cannot excommunicate himself. Therefore he cannot
share in the indulgence of which he is the grantor.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[27] A[4] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, He would be worse off than others if he could not make
use of the Church's treasury which he dispenses to others.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[27] A[4] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, An indulgence should be given for some reason, in order
for anyone to be enticed by the indulgence to perform some action that
conduces to the good of the Church and to the honor of God. Now the
prelate to whom is committed the care of the Church's good and of the
furthering of God's honor, does not need to entice himself thereto.
Therefore he cannot grant an indulgence to himself alone; but he can
avail himself of an indulgence that he grants for others, since it is
based on a cause for granting it to them.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[27] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/2
Reply OBJ 1: A man cannot exercise an act of jurisdiction on himself,
but a prelate can avail himself of those things which are granted to
others by the authority of his jurisdiction, both in temporal and in
spiritual matters: thus also a priest gives himself the Eucharist which
he gives to others. And so a bishop too can apply to himself the
suffrages of the Church which he dispenses to others, the immediate
effect of which suffrages, and not of his jurisdiction, is the remission
of punishment by means of indulgences.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[27] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 2/2
The Reply to the Second Objection is clear from what had been said.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[27] A[4] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Excommunication is pronounced by way of sentence, which no
man can pronounce on himself, for the reason that in the tribunal of
justice the same man cannot be both judge and accused. On the other hand
an indulgence is not given under the form of a sentence, but by way of
dispensation, which a man can apply to himself.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[28] Out. Para. 1/1
OF THE SOLEMN RITE OF PENANCE (THREE ARTICLES)
We must now consider the solemn rite of Penance: under which head there
are three points of inquiry:
(1) Whether a penance can be published or solemnized?
(2) Whether a solemn penance can be repeated?
(3) Whether public penance should be imposed on women?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[28] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether a penance should be published or solemnized?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[28] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that a penance should not be published or
solemnized. Because it is not lawful for a priest, even through fear, to
divulge anyone's sin, however notorious it may be. Now a sin is published
by a solemn penance. Therefore a penance should not be solemnized.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[28] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the judgment should follow the nature of the tribunal.
Now penance is a judgment pronounced in a secret tribunal. Therefore it
should not be published or solemnized.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[28] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, "Every deficiency is made good by penance" as Ambrose
[*Cf. Hypognost. iii, among the spurious works ascribed to St. Augustine]
states. Now solemnization has a contrary effect, since it involves the
penitent in many deficiencies: for a layman cannot be promoted to the
ranks of the clergy nor can a cleric be promoted to higher orders, after
doing solemn penance. Therefore Penance should not be solemnized.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[28] A[1] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, Penance is a sacrament. Now some kind of solemnity is
observed in every sacrament. Therefore there should be some solemnity in
Penance.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[28] A[1] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, the medicine should suit the disease. Now a sin is sometimes
public, and by its example draws many to sin. Therefore the penance which
is its medicine should also be public and solemn so as to give
edification to many.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[28] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Some penances should be public and solemn for four
reasons. First, so that a public sin may have a public remedy; secondly,
because he who has committed a very grave crime deserves the greatest
confusion even in this life; thirdly, in order that it may deter others;
fourthly, that he may be an example of repentance, lest those should
despair, who have committed grievous sins.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[28] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The priest does not divulge the confession by imposing such
a penance, though people may suspect the penitent of having committed
some great sin. For a man is not certainly taken to be guilty, because he
is punished, since sometimes one does penance for another: thus we read
in the Lives of the Fathers of a certain man who, in order to incite his
companion to do penance, did penance together with him. And if the sin be
public, the penitent, by fulfilling his penance, shows that he has been
to confession.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[28] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: A solemn penance, as to its imposition, does not go beyond
the limits of a secret tribunal, since, just as the confession is made
secretly, so the penance is imposed secretly. It is the execution of the
penance, that goes beyond the limits of the secret tribunal: and there is
nothing objectionable in this.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[28] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Although Penance cancels all deficiencies, by restoring man
to his former state of grace, yet it does not always restore him to his
former dignity. Hence women after doing penance for fornication are not
given the veil, because they do not recover the honor of virginity. In
like manner, after doing public penance, a sinner does not recover his
former dignity so as to be eligible for the clerical state and a bishop
who would ordain such a one ought to be deprived of the power of
ordaining, unless perhaps the needs of the Church or custom require it.
In that case such a one would be admitted to minor orders by way of
exception, but not to the sacred orders. First, on account of the dignity
of the latter; secondly, for fear of relapse; thirdly, in order to avoid
the scandal which the people might take through recollection of his
former sins; fourthly, because he would not have the face to correct
others, by reason of the publicity of his own sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[28] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether a solemn penance can be repeated?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[28] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that a solemn penance can be repeated. For those
sacraments which do not imprint a character, can be solemnized a second
time, such as the Eucharist, Extreme Unction and the like. But Penance
does not imprint a character, therefore it can be solemnized over again.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[28] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, penance is solemnized on account of the gravity and
publicity of the sin. Now, after doing penance, a person may commit the
same sins over again, or even more grievous sins. Therefore the solemn
penance should be imposed again.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[28] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, Solemn penance signifies the expulsion of the first man
from paradise. Now this was done but once. Therefore solemn penance
should be imposed once only.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[28] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Solemn penance ought not to be repeated, for three
reasons. First, lest frequency bring it into contempt. Secondly, on
account of its signification; for it signifies the expulsion of the first
man from paradise, which happened only once; thirdly, because the
solemnization indicates, in a way, that one makes profession of continual
repentance. Wherefore repetition is inconsistent with solemnization. And
if the sinner fall again, he is not precluded from doing penance, but a
solemn penance should not be imposed on him again.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[28] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: In those sacraments which are solemnized again and again,
repetition is not inconsistent with solemnity, as it is in the present
case. Hence the comparison fails.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[28] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Although, if we consider his crime, he ought to do the same
penance again, yet the repeated solemnization is not becoming, for the
reasons stated above.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[28] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether solemn penance should be imposed on women and clerics, and
whether any priest can impose it?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[28] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that solemn penance should not be imposed on women.
Because, when this penance is imposed on a man, he has to cut his hair
off. But this becomes not a woman, according to 1 Cor. 11:15. Therefore
she should not do solemn penance.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[28] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: It also seems that it ought to be imposed on clerics. For it is
enjoined on account of a grievous crime. Now the same sin is more
grievous in a cleric than in a layman. Therefore it ought to be imposed
on a cleric more than on a layman.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[28] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: It also seems that it can be imposed by any priest. Because to
absolve in the tribunal of Penance belongs to one who has the keys. Now
an ordinary priest has the keys. Therefore he can administer this penance.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[28] A[3] Body Para. 1/3
I answer that, Every solemn penance is public, but not vice versa. For
solemn penance is done as follows: "On the first day of Lent, these
penitents clothed in sackcloth, with bare feet, their faces to the
ground, and their hair shorn away, accompanied by their priests, present
themselves to the bishop of the city at the door of the church. Having
brought them into the church the bishop with all his clergy recites the
seven penitential psalms, and then imposes his hand on them, sprinkles
them with holy water, puts ashes on their heads, covers their shoulders
with a hairshirt, and sorrowfully announces to them that as Adam was
expelled from paradise, so are they expelled from the church. He then
orders the ministers to put them out of the church, and the clergy follow
reciting the responsory: 'In the sweat of thy brow,' etc. Every year on
the day of our Lord's Supper they are brought back into the church by
their priests, and there shall they be until the octave day of Easter,
without however being admitted to Communion or to the kiss of peace. This
shall be done every year as long as entrance into the church is forbidden
them. The final reconciliation is reserved to the bishop, who alone can
impose solemn penance" [*Cap. lxiv, dist. 50].
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[28] A[3] Body Para. 2/3
This penance can be imposed on men and women; but not on clerics, for
fear of scandal. Nor ought such a penance to be imposed except for a
crime which has disturbed the whole of the city.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[28] A[3] Body Para. 3/3
On the other hand public but not solemn penance is that which is done in
the presence of the Church, but without the foregoing solemnity, such as
a pilgrimage throughout the world with a staff. A penance of this kind
can be repeated, and can be imposed by a mere priest, even on a cleric.
Sometimes however a solemn penance is taken to signify a public one: so
that authorities speak of solemn penance in different senses.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[28] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The woman's hair is a sign of her subjection, a man's is
not. Hence it is not proper for a woman to put aside her hair when doing
penance, as it is for a man.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[28] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Although in the same kind of sin, a cleric offends more
grievously than a layman, yet a solemn penance is not imposed on him,
lest his orders should be an object of contempt. Thus deference is given
not to the person but to his orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[28] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Grave sins need great care in their cure. Hence the
imposition of a solemn penance, which is only applied for the most
grievous sins, is reserved to the bishop.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] Out. Para. 1/2
EXTREME UNCTION (QQ[29]-33)
OF EXTREME UNCTION, AS REGARDS ITS ESSENCE AND INSTITUTION (NINE ARTICLES)
We must now consider the sacrament of Extreme Unction: in respect of
which five points have to be considered: (1) Its essentials and
institution; (2) Its effect; (3) Its minister; (4) on whom should it be
conferred and in what parts; (5) Its repetition.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] Out. Para. 2/2
Under the first head there are nine points of inquiry:
(1) Whether Extreme Unction is a sacrament?
(2) Whether it is one sacrament?
(3) Whether this sacrament was instituted by Christ?
(4) Whether olive oil is a suitable matter for this sacrament?
(5) Whether the oil ought to be consecrated?
(6) Whether the matter of this sacrament should be consecrated by a
bishop?
(7) Whether this sacrament has any form?
(8) Whether the form of this sacrament should take the shape of a
deprecatory phrase?
(9) Whether this is a suitable form for this sacrament?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether Extreme Unction is a sacrament?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that Extreme Unction is not a sacrament. For just
as oil is used on sick people, so is it on catechumens. But anointing of
catechumens with oil is not a sacrament. Therefore neither is the Extreme
Unction of the sick with oil.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the sacraments of the Old Law were figures of the
sacraments of the New Law. But there was no figure of Extreme Unction in
the Old Law. Therefore it is not a sacrament of the New Law.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, according to Dionysius (Eccl. Hier. iii, v) every
sacrament aims at either cleansing, or enlightening, or perfecting. Now
Extreme Unction does not aim at either cleansing, or enlightening, for
this is ascribed to Baptism alone, or perfecting, for according to
Dionysius (Eccl. Hier. ii), this belongs to Confirmation and the
Eucharist. Therefore Extreme Unction is not a sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[1] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, The sacraments of the Church supply man's defects
sufficiently with respect to every state of life. Now no other than
Extreme Unction does this for those who are departing from this life.
Therefore it is a sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[1] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, the sacraments are neither more nor less than spiritual
remedies. Now Extreme Unction is a spiritual remedy, since it avails for
the remission of sins, according to James 5:15. Therefore it is a
sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Among the visible operations of the Church, some are
sacraments, as Baptism, some are sacramentals, as Exorcism. The
difference between these is that a sacrament is an action of the Church
that reaches to the principal effect intended in the administration of
the sacraments, whereas a sacramental is an action which, though it does
not reach to that effect, is nevertheless directed towards that principal
action. Now the effect intended in the administration of the sacraments
is the healing of the disease of sin: wherefore it is written (Is. 27:9):
"This is all the fruit, that the sin . . . should be taken away." Since
then Extreme Unction reaches to this effect, as is clear from the words
of James, and is not ordained to any other sacrament as an accessory
thereto, it is evident that Extreme Unction is not a sacramental but a
sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The oil with which catechumens are anointed does not convey
the remission of sins to them by its unction, for that belongs to
Baptism. It does, however, dispose them to receive Baptism, as stated
above (TP, Q[71], A[3]). Hence that unction is not a sacrament as Extreme
Unction is.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: This sacrament prepares man for glory immediately, since it
is given to those who are departing from this life. And as, under the Old
Law, it was not yet time to enter into glory, because "the Law brought
nobody [Vulg.: 'nothing'] to perfection" (Heb. 7:19), so this sacrament
had not to be foreshadowed therein by some corresponding sacrament, as by
a figure of the same kind. Nevertheless it was somewhat foreshadowed
remotely by all the healings related in the Old Testament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Dionysius makes no mention of Extreme Unction, as neither
of Penance, nor of Matrimony, because he had no intention to decide any
question about the sacraments, save in so far as they serve to illustrate
the orderly disposition of the ecclesiastical hierarchy, as regards the
ministers, their actions, and the recipients. Nevertheless since Extreme
Unction confers grace and remission of sins, there is no doubt that it
possesses an enlightening and cleansing power, even as Baptism, though
not so copious.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether Extreme Unction is one sacrament?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that Extreme Unction is not one sacrament. Because
the oneness of a thing depends on its matter and form, since being and
oneness are derived from the same source. Now the form of this sacrament
is said several times during the one administration, and the matter is
applied to the person anointed in respect of various parts of his body.
Therefore it is not one sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the unction itself is a sacrament, for it would be
absurd to say that the oil is a sacrament. But there are several
unctions. Therefore there are several sacraments.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, one sacrament should be performed by one minister. But
the case might occur that Extreme Unction could not be conferred by one
minister: thus if the priest die after the first unction, another priest
would have to proceed with the others. Therefore Extreme Unction is not
one sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[2] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, As immersion is in relation to Baptism, so is unction
to this sacrament. But several immersions are but one sacrament of
Baptism. Therefore the several unctions in Extreme Unction are also one
sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[2] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, if it were not one sacrament, then after the first unction, it
would not be essential for the perfection of the sacrament that the
second unction should be performed, since each sacrament has perfect
being of itself. But that is not true. Therefore it is one sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Strictly speaking, a thing is one numerically in three
ways. First, as something indivisible, which is neither actually nor
potentially several---as a point, and unity. Secondly, as something
continuous, which is actually one, but potentially several---as a line.
Thirdly, as something complete, that is composed of several parts---as a
house, which is, in a way, several things, even actually, although those
several things go together towards making one. In this way each sacrament
is said to be one thing, in as much as the many things which are
contained in one sacrament, are united together for the purpose of
signifying or causing one thing, because a sacrament is a sign of the
effect it produces. Hence when one action suffices for a perfect
signification, the unity of the sacrament consists in that action only,
as may be seen in Confirmation. When, however, the signification of the
sacrament can be both in one and in several actions, then the sacrament
can be complete both in one and in several actions, even as Baptism in
one immersion and in three, since washing which is signified in Baptism,
can be completed by one immersion and by several. But when the perfect
signification cannot be expressed except by means of several actions,
then these several actions are essential for the perfection of the
sacrament, as is exemplified in the Eucharist, for the refreshment of the
body which signifies that of the soul, can only be attained by means of
meat and drink. It is the same in this sacrament, because the healing of
the internal wounds cannot be perfectly signified save by the application
of the remedy to the various sources of the wounds. Hence several actions
are essential to the perfection of this sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The unity of a complete whole is not destroyed by reason of
a diversity of matter or form in the parts of that whole. Thus it is
evident that there is neither the same matter nor the same form in the
flesh and in the bones of which one man is composed. In like manner too,
in the sacrament of the Eucharist, and in this sacrament, the diversity
of matter and form does not destroy the unity of the sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Although those actions are several simply, yet they are
united together in one complete action, viz. the anointing of all the
external senses, whence arises the infernal malady.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Although, in the Eucharist, if the priest die after the
consecration of the bread, another priest can go on with the consecration
of the wine, beginning where the other left off, or can begin over again
with fresh matter, in Extreme Unction he cannot begin over again, but
should always go on, because to anoint the same part a second time would
produce as much effect as if one were to consecrate a host a second time,
which ought by no means to be done. Nor does the plurality of ministers
destroy the unity of this sacrament, because they only act as
instruments, and the unity of a smith's work is not destroyed by his
using several hammers.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether this sacrament was instituted by Christ?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that this sacrament was not instituted by Christ.
For mention is made in the Gospel of the institution of those sacraments
which Christ instituted, for instance the Eucharist and Baptism. But no
mention is made of Extreme Unction. Therefore it was not instituted by
Christ.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the Master says explicitly (Sent. iv, D, 23) that it was
instituted by the apostles. Therefore Christ did not institute it Himself.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, Christ showed forth the sacraments which He instituted,
as in the case of the Eucharist and Baptism. But He did not bestow this
sacrament on anyone. Therefore He did not institute it Himself.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[3] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, The sacraments of the New Law are more excellent than
those of the Old Law. But all the sacraments of the Old Law were
instituted by God. Therefore much more do all the sacraments of the New
Law owe their institution to Christ Himself.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[3] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, to make an institution and to remove it belongs to the same
authority. Now the Church, who enjoys the same authority in the
successors of the apostles, as the apostles themselves possessed, cannot
do away with the sacrament of Extreme Unction. Therefore the apostles did
not institute it, but Christ Himself.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[3] Body Para. 1/2
I answer that, There are two opinions on this point. For some hold that
this sacrament and Confirmation were not instituted by Christ Himself,
but were left by Him to be instituted by the apostles; for the reason
that these two sacraments, on account of the plenitude of grace conferred
in them, could not be instituted before the mission of the Holy Ghost in
perfect plenitude. Hence they are sacraments of the New Law in such a way
as not to be foreshadowed in the Old Law. But this argument is not very
cogent, since, just as Christ, before His Passion, promised the mission
of the Holy Ghost in His plenitude, so could He institute these
sacraments.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[3] Body Para. 2/2
Wherefore others hold that Christ Himself instituted all the sacraments,
but that He Himself published some, which present greater difficulty to
our belief, while he reserved some to be published by the apostles, such
as Extreme Unction and Confirmation. This opinion seems so much the more
probable, as the sacraments belong to the foundation of the Law,
wherefore their institution pertains to the lawgiver; besides, they
derive their efficacy from their institution, which efficacy is given
them by God alone.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Our Lord did and said many things which are not related in
the Gospel. For the evangelists were intent on handing down chiefly those
things that were necessary for salvation or concerned the building of the
ecclesiastical edifice. Hence they related the institution by Christ of
Baptism, Penance, the Eucharist and orders, rather than of Extreme
Unction and Confirmation, which are not necessary for salvation, nor do
they concern the building or division of the Church. As a matter of fact
however an anointing done by the apostles is mentioned in the Gospel (Mk.
6:13) where it is said that they "anointed the sick with oil."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The Master says it was instituted by the apostles because
its institution was made known to us by the teaching of the apostles.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Christ did not show forth any sacrament except such as He
received by way of example: but He could not be a recipient of Penance
and Extreme Unction, since there was no sin in Him: hence He did not show
them forth.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether olive oil is a suitable matter for this sacrament?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that olive oil is not a suitable matter for this
sacrament. For this sacrament is ordained immediately to the state of
incorruption. Now incorruption is signified by balsam which is contained
in chrism. Therefore chrism would be a more suitable matter for this
sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, this sacrament is a spiritual healing. Now spiritual
healing is signified by the use of wine, as may be gathered from the
parable of the wounded man (Lk. 10:34). Therefore wine also would be more
suitable a matter for this sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[4] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, where there is the greater danger, the remedy should be
a common one. But olive oil is not a common remedy, since the olive is
not found in every country. Therefore, since this sacrament is given to
the dying, who are in the greatest danger, it seems that olive oil is not
a suitable matter.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[4] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, oil is appointed (James 5:14) as the matter of this
sacrament. Now, properly speaking, oil is none but olive oil. Therefore
this is the matter of this sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[4] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, spiritual healing is signified by anointing with oil, as is
evident from Is. 1:6 where we read: " . . . swelling sores: they are not
. . dressed nor fomented with oil." Therefore the suitable matter for
this sacrament is oil.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[4] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, The spiritual healing, which is given at the end of life,
ought to be complete, since there is no other to follow; it ought also to
be gentle, lest hope, of which the dying stand in utmost need, be
shattered rather than fostered. Now oil has a softening effect, it
penetrates to the very heart of a thing, and spreads over it. Hence, in
both the foregoing respects, it is a suitable matter for this sacrament.
And since oil is, above all, the name of the liquid extract of olives,
for other liquids are only called oil from their likeness to it, it
follows that olive oil is the matter which should be employed in this
sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The incorruption of glory is something not contained in
this sacrament: and there is no need for the matter to signify such a
thing. Hence it is not necessary for balsam to be included in the matter
of this sacrament, because on account of its fragrance it is indicative
of a good name, which is no longer necessary, for its own sake, to those
who are dying; they need only a clear conscience which is signified by
oil.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Wine heals by its roughness, oil by its softness, wherefore
healing with wine pertains to Penance rather than to this sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[4] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Though olive oil is not produced everywhere, yet it can
easily be transported from one place to another. Moreover this sacrament
is not so necessary that the dying cannot obtain salvation without it.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[5] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the oil ought to be consecrated?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[5] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the oil need not be consecrated. Because there
is a sanctification in the use of this sacrament, through the form of
words. Therefore another sanctification is superfluous if it be applied
to the matter.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[5] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the efficacy and signification of the sacraments are in
their very matter. But the signification of the effect of this sacrament,
is suitable to oil on account of its natural properties, and the efficacy
thereof is due to the Divine institution. Therefore its matter does not
need to be sanctified.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[5] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, Baptism is a more perfect sacrament than Extreme
Unction. But, so far as the essentials of the sacrament are concerned,
the baptismal matter needs no sanctification. Neither therefore does the
matter of Extreme Unction need to be sanctified.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[5] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, In all other anointings the matter is previously
consecrated. Therefore since this sacrament is an anointing, it requires
consecrated matter.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[5] Body Para. 1/2
I answer that, Some hold that mere oil is the matter of this sacrament,
and that the sacrament itself is perfected in the consecration of the oil
by the bishop. But this is clearly false since we proved when treating of
the Eucharist that that sacrament alone consists in the consecration of
the matter (Q[2], A[1], ad 2).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[5] Body Para. 2/2
We must therefore say that this sacrament consists in the anointing
itself, just as Baptism consists in the washing, and that the matter of
this sacrament is consecrated oil. Three reasons may be assigned why
consecrated matter is needed in this sacrament and in certain others. The
first is that all sacramental efficacy is derived from Christ: wherefore
those sacraments which He Himself used, derived their efficacy from His
use of them, even as, by the contact of His flesh, He bestowed the force
of regeneration on the waters. But He did not use this sacrament, nor any
bodily anointing, wherefore in all anointings a consecrated matter is
required. The second reason is that this sacrament confers a plenitude of
grace, so as to take away not only sin but also the remnants of sin, and
bodily sickness. The third reason is that its effect on the body, viz.
bodily health, is not caused by a natural property of the matter.
wherefore it has to derive this efficacy from being consecrated.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[5] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The first consecration sanctifies the matter in itself, but
the second regards rather the use of the matter considered as actually
producing its effect. Hence neither is superfluous, because instruments
also receive their efficacy from the craftsman, both when they are made,
and when they are used for action.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[5] R.O. 2 Para. 1/2
Reply OBJ 2: The efficacy which the sacrament derives from its
institution, is applied to this particular matter when it is consecrated.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[5] R.O. 2 Para. 2/2
The Reply to the Third Objection is gathered from what has been said.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[6] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the matter of this sacrament need be consecrated by a bishop?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[6] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the matter of this sacrament need not be
consecrated by a bishop. Because the consecration of the Eucharistic
elements surpasses that of the matter in this sacrament. But a priest can
consecrate the matter in the Eucharist. Therefore he can do so in this
sacrament also.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[6] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, in material works the higher art never prepares the
matter for the lower, because the art which applies the matter is more
excellent than that which prepares it, as stated in Phys. ii, text. 25.
Now a bishop is above a priest. Therefore he does not prepare the matter
of a sacrament which is applied by a priest. But a priest dispenses this
sacrament, as we shall state further on (Q[31]). Therefore the
consecration of the matter does not belong to a bishop.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[6] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, In other anointings also the matter is consecrated by a
bishop. Therefore the same applies to this.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[6] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, The minister of a sacrament produces the effect, not by
his own power, as though he were the principal agent, but by the efficacy
of the sacrament which he dispenses. This efficacy comes, in the first
place, from Christ, and from Him flows down to others in due order, viz.
to the people through the medium of the ministers who dispense the
sacraments, and to the lower ministers through the medium of the higher
ministers who sanctify the matter. Wherefore, in all the sacraments which
require a sanctified matter, the first consecration of the matter is
performed by a bishop, and the application thereof sometimes by a priest,
in order to show that the priest's power is derived from the bishop's,
according to Ps. 132:2: "Like the precious ointment on the head," i.e.
Christ, "that ran down upon the beard of Aaron" first, and then "to the
skirt of his garment."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[6] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The sacrament of the Eucharist consists in the consecration
of the matter and not in its use. Consequently, strictly speaking, that
which is the matter of the sacrament is not a consecrated thing. Hence no
consecration of the matter by a bishop is required beforehand: but the
altar and such like things, even the priest himself, need to be
consecrated, all of which can be done by none but a bishop: so that in
this sacrament also, the priest's power is shown to be derived from the
bishop's, as Dionysius observes (Eccl. Hier. iii). The reason why a
priest can perform that consecration of matter which is a sacrament by
itself, and not that which, as a sacramental, is directed to a sacrament
consisting in something used by the faithful, is that in respect of
Christ's true body no order is above the priesthood, whereas, in respect
of Christ's mystic body the episcopate is above the priesthood, as we
shall state further on (Q[40], A[4]).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[6] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The sacramental matter is not one that is made into
something else by him that uses it, as occurs in the mechanical arts: it
is one, in virtue of which something is done, so that it partakes
somewhat of the nature of an efficient cause, in so far as it is the
instrument of a Divine operation. Hence the matter needs to acquire this
virtue from a higher art or power, since among efficient causes, the more
prior the cause the more perfect it is, whereas in material causes, the
more prior the matter, the more imperfect it is.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[7] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether this sacrament has a form?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[7] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that this sacrament has no form. Because, since the
efficacy of the sacraments is derived from their institution, as also
from their form, the latter must needs be appointed by the institutor of
the sacrament. But there is no account of the form of this sacrament
being instituted either by Christ or by the apostles. Therefore this
sacrament has no form.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[7] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, whatever is essential to a sacrament is observed
everywhere in the same way. Now nothing is so essential to a sacrament
that has a form, as that very form. Therefore, as in this sacrament there
is no form commonly used by all, since various words are in use, it seems
that this sacrament has no form.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[7] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, in Baptism no form is needed except for the
sanctification of the matter, because the water is "sanctified by the
word of life so as to wash sin away," as Hugh states (De Sacram. ii). Now
the matter of this sacrament is already consecrated. Therefore it needs
no form of words.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[7] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, The Master says (Sent. iv, D, 1) that every sacrament
of the New Law consists in things and words. Now the words are the
sacramental form. Therefore, since this is a sacrament of the New Law, it
seems that it has a form.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[7] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, this is confirmed by the rite of the Universal Church, who uses
certain words in the bestowal of this sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[7] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Some have held that no farm is essential to this
sacrament. This, however, seems derogatory to the effect of this
sacrament, since every sacrament signifies its effect. Now the matter is
indifferent as regards its effect, and consequently cannot be determined
to any particular effect save by the form of words. Hence in all the
sacraments of the New Law, since they effect what they signify, there
must needs be things and words. Moreover James (5:14,15) seems to ascribe
the whole force of this sacrament to prayer, which is the form thereof,
as we shall state further on (ad 2: AA[8],9). Wherefore the foregoing
opinion seems presumptuous and erroneous; and for that reason we should
hold with the common opinion that this, like all the other sacraments,
has a fixed form.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[7] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Holy Writ is proposed to all alike: and so, the form of
Baptism, which can be conferred by all, should be expressed in Holy Writ,
as also the form of the Eucharist, which in regard to that sacrament,
expresses faith which is necessary for salvation. Now the forms of the
other sacraments are not contained in Holy Writ, but were handed down to
the Church by the apostles, who received them from our Lord, as the
Apostle declares (1 Cor. 11:23): "For I have received of the Lord that
which also I delivered to you," etc.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[7] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The words which are essential to the form, viz. the prayer
of deprecation, are said by all; but other words which pertain to the
well-being thereof, are not said by all.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[7] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: The matter of Baptism has a certain sanctification of its
own from the very contact of our Saviour's flesh; but the form of words
sanctifies it so that it has a sanctifying force. In like manner when the
matter of this sacrament has been sanctified in itself, it requires
sanctification in its use, so that it may sanctify actually.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[8] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the form of this sacrament should be expressed by way of
assertion or of petition?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[8] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the form of this sacrament should be expressed
by way of assertion rather than of petition. Because all the sacraments
of the New Law have a sure effect. But sureness of effect is not
expressed in the sacramental forms except by way of assertion, as when we
say: "This is My body" or "I baptize thee." Therefore the form of this
sacrament should be expressed as an assertion.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[8] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the intention of the minister should be expressed in the
sacramental forms because it is essential to the sacrament. But the
intention of conferring a sacrament is not expressed except by an
assertion. Therefore, etc.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[8] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, in some churches the following words are said in the
conferring of this sacrament: "I anoint these eyes with consecrated oil
in the name of the Father," etc., which is in keeping with the forms of
the other sacraments. Therefore it seems that such is the form of this
sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[8] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, The form of a sacrament must needs be one that is
observed everywhere. Now the words employed according to the custom of
all the churches are not those quoted above, but take the form of a
petition viz.: "Through this holy unction, and His most tender mercy, may
the Lord pardon thee whatever sins thou hast committed, by sight," etc.
Therefore the form of this sacrament is expressed as a petition.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[8] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, this seems to follow from the words of James, who ascribes the
effect of this sacrament to prayer: "The prayer of faith," says he
(5:15), "shall save the sick man." Since then a sacrament takes its
efficacy from its form, it seems that the form of this sacrament is
expressed as a petition.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[8] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, The form of this sacrament is expressed by way of a
petition, as appears from the words of James, and from the custom of the
Roman Church, who uses no other than words of supplication in conferring
this sacrament. Several reasons are assigned for this: first, because the
recipient of this sacrament is deprived of his strength, so that he needs
to be helped by prayers; secondly, because it is given to the dying, who
are on the point of quitting the courts of the Church, and rest in the
hands of God alone, for which reason they are committed to Him by prayer;
thirdly, because the effect of this sacrament is not such that it always
results from the minister's prayer, even when all essentials have been
duly observed, as is the case with the character in Baptism and
Confirmation, transubstantiation in the Eucharist, remission of sin in
Penance (given contrition) which remission is essential to the sacrament
of Penance but not to this sacrament. Consequently the form of this
sacrament cannot be expressed in the indicative mood, as in the
sacraments just mentioned.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[8] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: This sacrament, like the others mentioned, considered in
itself, is sure of its effect. yet this effect can be hindered through
the insincerity of the recipient (though by his intention he submit to
the sacrament), so that he receives no effect at all. Hence there is no
parity between this sacrament, and the others wherein some effect always
ensues.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[8] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The intention is sufficiently expressed by the act which is
mentioned in the form, viz.: "By this holy unction."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[8] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: These words in the indicative mood, which some are wont to
say before the prayer, are not the sacramental form, but are a
preparation for the form, in so far as they determine the intention of
the minister.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[9] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the foregoing prayer is a suitable form for this sacrament?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[9] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the foregoing prayer is not a suitable form
for this sacrament. For in the forms of the other sacraments mention is
made of the matter, for instance in Confirmation, whereas this is not
done in the aforesaid words. Therefore it is not a suitable form.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[9] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, just as the effect of this sacrament is bestowed on us
by the mercy of God, so are the effects of the other sacraments. But
mention is made in the forms of the other sacraments, not of the Divine
mercy, but rather of the Trinity and of the Passion. Therefore the same
should be done here.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[9] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, this sacrament is stated in the text (Sent. iv, D, 23)
to have a twofold effect. But in the foregoing words mention is made of
only one effect, viz. the remission of sins, and not of the healing of
the body to which end James directs the prayer of faith to be made (James
5:15): "The prayer of faith shall save the sick man." Therefore the above
form is unsuitable.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[9] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, The prayer given above (A[8]) is a suitable form for this
sacrament, for it includes the sacrament by the words: "By this holy
unction," and that which works in the sacrament, viz. "the mercy of God,"
and the effect, viz. "remission of sins."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[9] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The matter of this sacrament may be understood in the act
of anointing, whereas the matter of Confirmation cannot be implied by the
act expressed in the form. Hence there is no parity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[9] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The object of mercy is misery: and because this sacrament
is given when we are in a state of misery, i.e. of sickness, mention of
mercy is made in this rather than in other sacraments.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[29] A[9] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: The form should contain mention of the principal effect,
and of that which always ensues in virtue of the sacrament, unless there
be something lacking on the part of the recipient. Now bodily health is
not an effect of this kind, as we shall state further on (Q[30], AA[1]
,2), though it does ensue at times, for which reason James ascribes this
effect to the prayer which is the form of this sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[30] Out. Para. 1/1
OF THE EFFECT OF THIS SACRAMENT (THREE ARTICLES)
We must now consider the effect of this sacrament: under which head
there are three points of inquiry:
(1) Whether Extreme Unction avails for the remission of sins?
(2) Whether bodily health is an effect of this sacrament?
(3) Whether this sacrament imprints a character?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[30] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether Extreme Unction avails for the remission of sins?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[30] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that Extreme Unction does not avail for the
remission of sins. For when a thing can be attained by one means, no
other is needed. Now repentance is required in the recipient of Extreme
Unction for the remission of his sins. Therefore sins are not remitted by
Extreme Unction.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[30] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, there are no more than three things in sin, the stain,
the debt of punishment, and the remnants of sin. Now Extreme Unction does
not remit the stain without contrition, and this remits sin even without
Unction; nor does it remit the punishment, for if the recipient recover,
he is still bound to fulfill the satisfaction enjoined; nor does it take
away the remnants of sin, since the dispositions remaining from preceding
acts still remain, as may easily be seen after recovery. Therefore
remission of sins is by no means the effect of Extreme Unction.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[30] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, remission of sins takes place, not successively, but
instantaneously. On the other hand, Extreme Unction is not done all at
once, since several anointings are required. Therefore the remission of
sins is not its effect.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[30] A[1] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, It is written (James 5:15): "If he be in sins, they
shall be forgiven him."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[30] A[1] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, every sacrament of the New Law confers grace. Now grace effects
the forgiveness of sins. Therefore since Extreme Unction is a sacrament
of the New Law, its effect is the remission of sins.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[30] A[1] Body Para. 1/2
I answer that, Each sacrament was instituted for the purpose of one
principal effect, though it may, in consequence, produce other effects
besides. And since a sacrament causes what it signifies, the principal
effect of a sacrament must be gathered from its signification. Now this
sacrament is conferred by way of a kind of medicament, even as Baptism is
conferred by way of washing, and the purpose of a medicament is to expel
sickness. Hence the chief object of the institution of this sacrament is
to cure the sickness of sin. Therefore, just as Baptism is a spiritual
regeneration, and Penance, a spiritual resurrection, so Extreme Unction
is a spiritual healing or cure. Now just as a bodily cure presupposes
bodily life in the one who is cured, so does a spiritual cure presuppose
spiritual life. Hence this sacrament is not an antidote to those defects
which deprive man of spiritual life, namely. original and mortal sin, but
is a remedy for such defects as weaken man spiritually, so as to deprive
him of perfect vigor for acts of the life of grace or of glory; which
defects consist in nothing else but a certain weakness and unfitness, the
result in us of actual or original sin. against which weakness man is
strengthened by this sacrament. Since, however, this strength is given by
grace, which is incompatible with sin, it follows that. in consequence,
if it finds any sin, either mortal or venial, it removes it as far as the
guilt is concerned, provided there be no obstacle on the part of the
recipient; just as we have stated to be the case with regard to the
Eucharist and Confirmation (TP, Q[73], A[7]; TP, Q[79], A[3]). Hence,
too, James speaks of the remission of sin as being conditional, for he
says: "If he be in sins, they shall be forgiven him," viz. as to the
guilt. Because it does not always blot out sin, since it does not always
find any: but it always remits in respect of the aforesaid weakness which
some call the remnants of sin. Some, however, maintain that it is
instituted chiefly as a remedy for venial sin which cannot be cured
perfectly in this lifetime: for which reason the sacrament of the dying
is ordained specially against venial sin. But this does not seem to be
true, since Penance also blots out venial sins sufficiently during this
life as to their guilt, and that we cannot avoid them after doing
penance, does not cancel the effect of the previous penance; moreover
this is part of the weakness mentioned above.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[30] A[1] Body Para. 2/2
Consequently we must say that the principal effect of this sacrament is
the remission of sin, as to its remnants, and, consequently, even as to
its guilt, if it find it.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[30] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Although the principal effect of a sacrament can be
obtained without actually receiving that sacrament (either without any
sacrament at all, or indirectly by means of some other sacrament), yet it
never can be obtained without the purpose of receiving that sacrament.
And so, since Penance was instituted chiefly against actual sin,
whichever other sacrament may blot out sin indirectly, it does not
exclude the necessity of Penance.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[30] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Extreme Unction remits sin in some way as to those three
things. For, although the stain of sin is not washed out without
contrition, yet this sacrament, by the grace which it bestows, makes the
movement of the free will towards sin to be one of contrition, just as
may occur in the Eucharist and Confirmation. Again it diminishes the debt
of temporal punishment; and this indirectly, in as much as it takes away
weakness, for a strong man bears the same punishment more easily than a
weak man. Hence it does not follow that the measure of satisfaction is
diminished. As to the remnants of sin, they do not mean here those
dispositions which result from acts, and are inchoate habits so to speak,
but a certain spiritual debility in the mind, which debility being
removed, though such like habits or dispositions remain, the mind is not
so easily prone to sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[30] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: When many actions are ordained to one effect, the last is
formal with respect to all the others that precede, and acts by virtue of
them: wherefore by the last anointing is infused grace which gives the
sacrament its effect.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[30] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether bodily health is an effect of this sacrament?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[30] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that bodily health is not an effect of this
sacrament. For every sacrament is a spiritual remedy. Now a spiritual
remedy is ordained to spiritual health, just as a bodily remedy is
ordained to health of the body. Therefore bodily health is not an effect
of this sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[30] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the sacraments always produce their effect in those who
approach them in the proper dispositions. Now sometimes the recipient of
this sacrament does not receive bodily health, no matter how devoutly he
receives it. Therefore bodily health is not its effect.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[30] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, the efficacy of this sacrament is notified to us in the
fifth chapter of James. Now healing is ascribed there as the effect, not
of the anointing, but of the prayer, for he says: "The prayer of faith
shall save the sick man." Therefore bodily healing is not an effect of
this sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[30] A[2] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, The operation of the Church is more efficacious since
Christ's Passion than before. Now, before the Passion, those whom the
apostles anointed with oil were healed (Mk. 6:13). Therefore unction has
its effect now in healing bodies.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[30] A[2] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, the sacraments produce their effect by signifying it. Now
Baptism signifies and effects a spiritual washing, through the bodily
washing in which it consists outwardly. Therefore Extreme Unction
signifies and causes a spiritual healing through the bodily healing which
it effects externally.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[30] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Just as Baptism causes a spiritual cleansing from
spiritual stains by means of a bodily washing, so this sacrament causes
an inward healing by means of an outward sacramental healing: and even as
the baptismal washing has the effect of a bodily washing, since it
effects even a bodily cleansing, so too, Extreme Unction has the effect
of a bodily remedy, namely a healing of the body. But there is a
difference, for as much as the bodily washing causes a bodily cleansing
by a natural property of the bodily element, and consequently always
causes it, whereas Extreme Unction causes a bodily healing, not by a
natural property of the matter, but by the Divine power which works
reasonably. And since reasonable working never produces a secondary
effect, except in so far as it is required for the principal effect, it
follows that a bodily healing does not always ensue from this sacrament,
but only when it is requisite for the spiritual healing: and then it
produces it always, provided there be no obstacle on the part of the
recipient.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[30] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/2
Reply OBJ 1: This objection proves that bodily health is not the
principal effect of this sacrament: and this is true.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[30] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 2/2
The Reply to the Second Objection is clear from what has been said above
(cf. Q[29], A[8]).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[30] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: This prayer is the form of this sacrament as stated above
(Q[29], AA[8],9). Hence, so far as its form is concerned, this sacrament
derives from it its efficacy in healing the body.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[30] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether this sacrament imprints a character?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[30] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that this sacrament imprints a character. For a
character is a distinctive sign. Now just as one who is baptized is
distinguished from one who is not so is one who is anointed, from one who
is not. Therefore, just as Baptism imprints a character so does Extreme
Unction.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[30] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, there is an anointing in the sacraments or order and
Confirmation, as there is in this sacrament. But a character is imprinted
in those sacraments. Therefore a character is imprinted in this one also.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[30] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, every sacrament contains something that is a reality
only, something that is a sacrament only, and something that is both
reality and sacrament. Now nothing in this sacrament can be assigned as
both reality and sacrament except a character. Therefore in this
sacrament also, a character is imprinted.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[30] A[3] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, No sacrament that imprints a character is repeated. But
this sacrament is repeated as we shall state further on (Q[33]).
Therefore it does not imprint a character.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[30] A[3] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, a sacramental character causes a distinction among those who
are in the present Church. But Extreme Unction is given to one who is
departing from the present Church. Therefore it does not imprint a
character.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[30] A[3] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, A character is not imprinted except in those sacraments
whereby man is deputed to some sacred duty. Now this sacrament is for no
other purpose than a remedy, and man is not deputed thereby to do or
receive anything holy. Therefore it does not imprint a character.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[30] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: A character marks a distinction of . states with regard to
duties which have to be performed in the Church, a distinction which a
man does not receive by being anointed.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[30] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The unction of orders and Confirmation, is the unction of
consecration whereby a man is deputed to some sacred duty, whereas this
unction is remedial. Hence the comparison fails.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[30] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: In this sacrament, that which is both reality and sacrament
is not a character, but a certain inward devotion which is a kind of
spiritual anointing.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[31] Out. Para. 1/1
OF THE MINISTER OF THIS SACRAMENT (THREE ARTICLES)
We must now consider the minister of this sacrament: under which head
there are three points of inquiry:
(1) Whether a layman can confer this sacrament?
(2) Whether a deacon can?
(3) Whether none but a bishop can confer it?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[31] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether a layman can confer this sacrament?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[31] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that even a layman can confer this sacrament. For
this sacrament derives its efficacy from prayer, as James declares (James
5:15). But a layman's prayer is sometimes as acceptable to God as a
priest's. Therefore he can confer this sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[31] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, we read of certain fathers in Egypt that they sent the
oil to the sick, and that these were healed. It is also related of the
Blessed Genevieve that she anointed the sick with oil. Therefore this
sacrament can be conferred even by lay people.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[31] A[1] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, Remission of sins is given in this sacrament. But
laymen have not the power to forgive sins. Therefore, etc.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[31] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, According to Dionysius (Eccl. Hier. v) there are some who
exercise hierarchical actions, and some who are recipients only. Hence
laymen are officially incompetent to dispense any sacrament: and that
they can baptize in cases of necessity, is due to the Divine
dispensation, in order that no one may be deprived of spiritual
regeneration.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[31] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: This prayer is not said by the priest in his own person,
for since sometimes he is in sin, he would not in that case be heard. But
it is said in the person of the whole Church, in whose person he can pray
as a public official, whereas a layman cannot, for he is a private
individual.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[31] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: These unctions were not sacramental. It was due to the
devotion of the recipients of the unction, and to the merits of those who
anointed them that they procured the effects of bodily health, through
the "grace of healing" (1 Cor. 12:9) but not through sacramental grace.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[31] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether deacons can confer this sacrament?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[31] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that deacons can confer this sacrament. For,
according to Dionysius (Eccl. Hier. v) "deacons have the power to
cleanse." Now this sacrament was instituted precisely to cleanse from
sickness of the mind and body. Therefore deacons also can confer it.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[31] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, Baptism is a more excellent sacrament than the one of
which we are speaking. But deacons can baptize, as instanced by the
Blessed Laurence. Therefore they can confer this sacrament also.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[31] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, It is written (James 5:14): "Let him bring in the
priests of the Church."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[31] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, A deacon has the power to cleanse but not to enlighten.
Hence, since enlightenment is an effect of grace, no sacrament whereby
grace is conferred can be given by a deacon in virtue of his office: and
so he cannot confer this sacrament, since grace is bestowed therein.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[31] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: This sacrament cleanses by enlightening through the
bestowal of grace: wherefore a deacon is not competent to confer it.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[31] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: This is not a necessary sacrament, as Baptism is. Hence its
bestowal is not committed to all in cases of necessity, but only to those
who are competent to do so in virtue of their office. Nor are deacons
competent to baptize in virtue of their office.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[31] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether none but a bishop can confer this sacrament?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[31] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that none but a bishop can confer this sacrament.
For this sacrament consists in an anointing, just as Confirmation does.
Now none but a bishop can confirm. Therefore only a bishop can confer
this sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[31] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, he who cannot do what is less cannot do what is greater.
Now the use of consecrated matter surpasses the act of consecrating the
matter, since the former is the end of the latter. Therefore since a
priest cannot consecrate the matter, neither can he use the matter after
it has been consecrated.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[31] A[3] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, The minister of this sacrament has to be brought in to
the recipient, as is clear from James 5:14. Now a bishop cannot go to all
the sick people of his diocese. Therefore the bishop is not the only one
who can confer this sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[31] A[3] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, According to Dionysius (Eccl. Hier. v), the office of
perfecting belongs to a bishop, just as it belongs to a priest to
enlighten. Wherefore those sacraments are reserved to a bishop's
dispensation, which place the recipient in a state of perfection above
others. But this is not the case with this sacrament, for it is given to
all. Consequently it can be given by ordinary priests.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[31] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Confirmation imprints a character, whereby man is placed in
a state of perfection, as stated above (TP, Q[63], AA[1], 2,6). But this
does not take place in this sacrament; hence there is no comparison.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[31] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Although the use of consecrated matter is of more
importance than the consecration of the matter, from the point of view of
the final cause; nevertheless, from the point of view of efficient cause,
the consecration of the matter is the more important, since the use of
the matter is dependent thereon, as on its active cause: hence the
consecration of the matter demands a higher power than the use of the
matter does.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] Out. Para. 1/1
ON WHOM SHOULD THIS SACRAMENT BE CONFERRED AND ON WHAT PART OF THE BODY?
(SEVEN ARTICLES)
We must now consider on whom this sacrament should be conferred and on
what part of the body: under which head there are seven points of inquiry:
(1) Whether this sacrament should be conferred on those who are in good
health?
(2) Whether it should be conferred in any kind of sickness?
(3) Whether it should be conferred on madmen and imbeciles?
(4) Whether it should be given to children?
(5) Whether, in this sacrament, the whole body should be anointed?
(6) Whether certain parts are suitably assigned to be anointed?
(7) Whether those who are deformed in the above parts ought to be
anointed thereon?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether this sacrament ought to be conferred on those who are in good
health?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that this sacrament should be conferred even on
those who are in good health. For the healing of the mind is a more
important effect of this sacrament than the healing of the body, as
stated above (Q[30], A[2]). Now even those who are healthy in body need
to be healed in mind. Therefore this sacrament should be conferred on
them also.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, this is the sacrament of those who are departing this
life, just as Baptism is the sacrament of those who are entering this
life. Now Baptism is given to all who enter. Therefore this sacrament
should be given to all who are departing. But sometimes those who are
near departure are in good health, for instance those who are to be
beheaded. Therefore this sacrament should be conferred on them.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[1] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, It is written (James 5:14): "Is any man sick among
you," etc. Therefore none but the sick are competent to receive this
sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, This sacrament is a spiritual healing, as stated above
(Q[30], AA[1],2), and is signified by way of a healing of the body. Hence
this sacrament should not be conferred on those who are not subjects for
bodily healing, those namely, who are in good health.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Although spiritual health is the principal effect of this
sacrament, yet this same spiritual healing needs to be signified by a
healing of the body, although bodily health may not actually ensue.
Consequently spiritual health can be conferred by this sacrament on those
alone who are competent to receive bodily healing, viz. the sick; even as
he alone can receive Baptism who is capable of a bodily washing, and not
a child yet in its mother's womb.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Even those who are entering into life cannot receive
Baptism unless they are capable of a bodily washing. And so those who are
departing this life cannot receive this sacrament, unless they be
subjects for a bodily healing.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether this sacrament ought to be given in any kind of sickness?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that this sacrament should be given in any kind of
sickness. For no kind of sickness is determined in the fifth chapter of
James where this sacrament is delivered to us. Therefore this sacrament
should be given in all kinds of sickness.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the more excellent a remedy is, the more generally
should it be available. Now this sacrament is more excellent than bodily
medicine. Since then bodily medicine is given to all manner of sick
persons, it seems that this sacrament should be given in like manner to
all.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, This sacrament is called by all Extreme Unction. Now it
is not every sickness that brings man to the extremity of his life, since
some ailments prolong life, according to the Philosopher (De Long. et
Brev. Vitae i). Therefore this sacrament should not be given in every
case of sickness.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, This sacrament is the last remedy that the Church can
give, since it is an immediate preparation for glory. Therefore it ought
to be given to those only, who are so sick as to be in a state of
departure from this life, through their sickness being of such a nature
as to cause death, the danger of which is to be feared.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Any sickness can cause death, if it be aggravated. Hence if
we consider the different kinds of disease, there is none in which this
sacrament cannot be given; and for this reason the apostle does not
determine any particular one. But if we consider the degree and the stage
of the complaint, this sacrament should not be given to every sick person.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The principal effect of bodily medicine is bodily health,
which all sick people lack, whatever be the stage of their sickness. But
the principal effect of this sacrament is that immunity from disorder
which is needed by those who are taking their departure from this life
and setting out for the life of glory. Hence the comparison fails.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether this sacrament ought to be given to madmen and imbeciles?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that this sacrament should be given to madmen and
imbeciles. For these diseases are full of danger and cause death quickly.
Now when there is danger it is the time to apply the remedy. Therefore
this sacrament, which was intended as a remedy to human weakness, should
be given to such people.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, Baptism is a greater sacrament than this. Now Baptism is
conferred on mad people as stated above (TP, Q[68], A[12]). Therefore
this sacrament also should be given to them.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[3] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, This sacrament should be given to none but such as
acknowledge it. Now this does not apply to madmen and imbeciles.
Therefore it should not be given to them.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[3] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, The devotion of the recipient, the personal merit of the
minister, and the general merits of the whole Church, are of great
account towards the reception of the effect of this sacrament. This is
evident from the fact that the form of this sacrament is pronounced by
way of a prayer. Hence it should not be given those who cannot
acknowledge it, and especially to madmen and imbeciles, who might
dishonor the sacrament by their offensive conduct, unless they have lucid
intervals, when they would be capable of acknowledging the sacrament, for
then the sacrament should be given to children the same in that state.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Although such people are sometimes in danger of death; yet
the remedy cannot be applied to them, on account of their lack of
devotion. Hence it should not be given to them.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Baptism does not require a movement of the free-will,
because it is given chiefly as a remedy for original sin, which, in us,
is not taken away by a movement of the free-will. On the other hand this
sacrament requires a movement of the free-will; wherefore the comparison
fails. Moreover Baptism is a necessary sacrament, while Extreme Unction
is not.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether this sacrament should be given to children?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that this sacrament ought to be given to children.
Because children suffer from the same ailments sometimes as adults. Now
the same disease requires the same remedy. Therefore this sacrament
should be given to children the same as to adults.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, this sacrament is given in order to remove the remnants
of sin, whether original or actual, as stated above (Q[30], A[1]). Now
the remnants of original sin are in children. Therefore this sacrament
should be given to them.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[4] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, This sacrament should be given to none but those to
whom the form applies. But the form of this sacrament does not apply to
children, since they have not sinned by sight and hearing; as expressed
in the form. Therefore this sacrament should not be given to them.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[4] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, This sacrament, like the Eucharist, requires actual
devotion in the recipient. Therefore, just as the Eucharist ought not to
be given to children, so neither ought this sacrament to be given to them.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Children's infirmities are not caused by actual sin, as in
adults, and this sacrament is given chiefly as a remedy for infirmities
that result from sins, being the remnants of sin, as it were.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: This sacrament is not given as a remedy for the remnants of
original sin, except in so far as they gather strength, so to speak, from
actual sins. Hence from the very form it appears that it is given chiefly
as a remedy for actual sins, which are not in children.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[5] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the whole body should be anointed in this sacrament?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[5] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the whole body should be anointed in this
sacrament. For, according to Augustine (De Trin. vi, 6), "the whole soul
is in every part of the body." Now this sacrament is given chiefly in
order to heal the soul. Therefore the whole body ought to be anointed.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[5] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the remedy should be applied to the part affected by the
disease. But sometimes the disease is general, and affects the whole
body, as a fever does. Therefore the whole body should be anointed.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[5] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, in Baptism the whole body is dipped under the water.
Therefore in this sacrament the whole body should be anointed.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[5] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, stands the rite observed throughout the Church,
according to which in this sacrament the sick man is anointed, only in
certain fixed parts of the body.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[5] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, This sacrament is shown to us under the form of a
healing. Now bodily healing has to be effected, by applying the remedy,
not to the whole body, but to those parts where the root of the disease
is seated. Consequently the sacramental unction also ought to be applied
to those parts only in which the spiritual sickness is rooted.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[5] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Although the whole soul is, as to its essence, in each part
of the body, it is not as to its powers which are the roots of sinful
acts. Hence certain fixed parts have to be anointed, those, namely, in
which powers have their being.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[5] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The remedy is not always applied to the part affected by
the disease, but, with greater reason, to the part where the root of the
disease is seated.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[5] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Baptism is given under the form of washing: and a bodily
washing cleanses only the part to which it is applied; for this reason
Baptism is applied to the whole body. It is different with Extreme
Unction for the reason given above.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[6] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the parts to be anointed are suitably assigned?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[6] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that these parts are unsuitably assigned, namely,
that the eyes, nose, ears, lips, hands, and feet should be anointed. For
a wise physician heals the disease in its root. Now "from the heart come
forth thoughts . . . that defile a man" (Mt. 15:19,20). Therefore the
breast ought to be anointed.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[6] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, purity of mind is not less necessary to those who are
departing this life than to those who are entering therein. Now those
who are entering are anointed with chrism on the head by the priest, to
signify purity of mind. Therefore in this sacrament those who are
departing should be anointed on the head.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[6] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, the remedy should be applied where the disease is most
virulent. Now spiritual sickness is most virulent in the loins in men,
and in the navel in women, according to Job 40:11: "His strength is in
his loins, and his force in the navel of his belly," as Gregory expounds
the passage (Moral. xxxii, 11). Therefore these parts should be anointed.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[6] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, sins are committed with other parts of the body, no less
than with the feet. Therefore, as the feet are anointed, so ought other
members of the body to be anointed.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[6] Body Para. 1/2
I answer that, The principles of sinning are the same in us as the
principles of action, for a sin is an act. Now there are in us three
principles of action; the first is the directing principle, namely, the
cognitive power; the second is the commanding principle, namely, the
appetitive power; the third is the executive principle, namely, the
motive power.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[6] Body Para. 2/2
Now all our knowledge has its origin in the senses. And, since the
remedy for sin should be applied where sin originates in us first, for
that reason the places of the five senses are anointed. the eyes, to wit,
on account of the sight, the ears on account of hearing, the nostrils on
account of the smell, the mouth on account of the taste, the hands on
account of the touch which is keenest in the finger tips, (in some places
too the loins are anointed on account of the appetite), and the feet are
anointed on account of the motive power of which they are the chief
instrument. And since the cognitive power is the first principle of human
activity, the anointing of the five senses is observed by all, as being
essential to the sacrament. But some do not observe the other
unctions---some also anoint the feet but not the loins---because the
appetitive and motive powers are secondary principles.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[6] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: No thought arises in the heart without an act of the
imagination which is a movement proceeding from sensation (De Anima ii).
Hence the primary root of thought is not the heart, but the sensory
organs, except in so far as the heart is a principle of the whole body,
albeit a remote principle.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[6] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Those who enter have to receive purity of the mind, whereas
those who are departing have to cleanse the mind. Hence the latter need
to be anointed in those parts in respect of which the mind's purity may
be sullied.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[6] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Some are wont to anoint the loins, because they are the
chief seat of the concupiscible appetite: however, as stated above, the
appetitive power is not the primary root.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[6] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: The bodily organs which are the instruments of sin, are the
feet, hands, and tongue, all of which are anointed, and the organs of
generation which it would be unbecoming to anoint, on account of their
uncleanliness, and out of respect for the sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[7] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether those who are deformed in those parts should be anointed?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[7] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that those who are deformed should not be anointed
in those parts. For just as this sacrament demands a certain disposition
on the part of the recipient, viz. that he should be sick, so it demands
that he should be anointed in a certain part of the body. Now he that is
not sick cannot be anointed. Therefore neither can he be anointed who
lacks the part to be anointed.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[7] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, a man born blind does not sin by his sight. Yet in the
anointing of the eyes mention is made of sins by sight. Therefore this
anointing ought not to be applied to one born blind, and in like manner
as regards the other senses.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[7] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, Bodily deformity is not an impediment to any other
sacrament. Therefore it should not be an impediment to this one. Now each
of the anointings is essential to the sacrament. Therefore all should be
applied to those who are deformed.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[7] Body Para. 1/2
I answer that, Even those who are deformed should be anointed, and that
as near as possible to the part which ought to have been anointed. For
though they have not the members, nevertheless, they have, at least
radically, the powers of the soul, corresponding to those members, and
they may commit inwardly the sins that pertain to those members, though
they cannot outwardly.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[32] A[7] Body Para. 2/2
This suffices for the Replies to the Objections.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[33] Out. Para. 1/1
OF THE REPETITION OF THIS SACRAMENT (TWO ARTICLES)
We must now consider the repetition of this sacrament: under which head
there are two points of inquiry:
(1) Whether this sacrament ought to be repeated?
(2) Whether it ought to be repeated during the same sickness?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[33] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether this sacrament ought to be repeated?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[33] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that this sacrament ought not to be repeated. For
the anointing of a man is of greater import than the anointing of a
stone. But the anointing of an altar is not repeated, unless the altar be
shattered. Neither, therefore, should Extreme Unction, whereby a man is
anointed, be repeated.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[33] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, nothing comes after what is extreme. But this unction is
called extreme. Therefore it should not be repeated.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[33] A[1] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, This sacrament is a spiritual healing applied under
the form of a bodily cure. But a bodily cure is repeated. Therefore this
sacrament also can be repeated.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[33] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, No sacramental or sacrament, having an effect that lasts
for ever, can be repeated, because this would imply that the sacrament
had failed to produce that effect; and this would be derogatory to the
sacrament. On the other hand a sacrament whose effect does not last for
ever, can be repeated without disparaging that sacrament, in order that
the lost effect may be recovered. And since health of body and soul,
which is the effect of this sacrament, can be lost after it has been
effected, it follows that this sacrament can, without disparagement
thereto, be repeated.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[33] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The stone is anointed in order that the altar may be
consecrated, and the stone remains consecrated, as long as the altar
remains, hence it cannot be anointed again. But a man is not consecrated
by being anointed, since it does not imprint a character on him. Hence
there is no comparison.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[33] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: What men think to be extreme is not always extreme in
reality. It is thus that this sacrament is called Extreme Unction,
because it ought not to be given save to those whose death men think to
be nigh.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[33] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether this sacrament ought to be repeated during the same sickness?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[33] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that this sacrament ought not to be repeated during
the same sickness. For one disease demands one remedy. Now this sacrament
is a spiritual remedy. Therefore it ought not to be repeated for one
sickness.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[33] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, if a sick man could be anointed more than once during
one disease, this might be done for a whole day: which is absurd.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[33] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, Sometimes a disease lasts long after the sacrament has
been received, so that the remnants of sin, against which chiefly this
sacrament is given, would be contracted. Therefore it ought to be given
again.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[33] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, This sacrament regards not only the sickness, but also
the state of the sick man, because it ought not to be given except to
those sick people who seem, in man's estimation, to be nigh to death. Now
some diseases do not last long; so that if this sacrament is given at the
time that the sick man is in a state of danger of death, he does not
leave that state except the disease be cured, and thus he needs not to be
anointed again. But if he has a relapse, it will be a second sickness,
and he can be anointed again. on the other hand some diseases are of long
duration, as hectic fever, dropsy and the like, and those who lie sick of
them should not be anointed until they seem to be in danger of death. And
if the sick man escape that danger while the disease continues, and be
brought again thereby to the same state of danger, he can be anointed
again, because it is, as it were, another state of sickness, although
strictly speaking, it is not another sickness. This suffices for the
Replies to the Objections.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] Out. Para. 1/3
HOLY ORDERS (QQ[34]-40)
OF THE SACRAMENT OF ORDER AS TO ITS ESSENCE AND ITS PARTS (FIVE ARTICLES)
In the next place we must consider the sacrament of Order: (1) Order in
general; (2) the difference of Orders; (3) those who confer Orders; (4)
the impediments to receiving Orders; (5) things connected with Orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] Out. Para. 2/3
Concerning Order in general three points have to be considered: (1) Its
essence, quiddity, and parts; (2) Its effect; (3) The recipients of
Orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] Out. Para. 3/3
Under the first head there are five points of inquiry:
(1) Whether there should be Order in the Church?
(2) Whether it is fittingly defined?
(3) Whether it is a sacrament?
(4) Whether its form is expressed properly?
(5) Whether this sacrament has any matter?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether there should be Order in the Church?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that there should not be Order in the Church. For
Order requires subjection and preeminence. But subjection seemingly is
incompatible with the liberty whereunto we are called by Christ.
Therefore there should not be Order in the Church.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, he who has received an Order becomes another's superior.
But in the Church everyone should deem himself lower than another (Phil.
2:3): "Let each esteem others better than themselves." Therefore Order
should not be in the Church.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, we find order among the angels on account of their
differing in natural and gratuitous gifts. But all men are one in nature,
and it is not known who has the higher gifts of grace. Therefore Order
should not be in the Church.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[1] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, "Those things that are of God, are in order [*Vulg:
'Those (powers) that are, are ordained of God.']." Now the Church is of
God, for He Himself built it with His blood. Therefore there ought to be
Order in the Church.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[1] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, the state of the Church is between the state of nature and the
state of glory. Now we find order in nature, in that some things are
above others, and likewise in glory, as in the angels. Therefore there
should be Order in the Church.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, God wished to produce His works in likeness to Himself,
as far as possible, in order that they might be perfect, and that He
might be known through them. Hence, that He might be portrayed in His
works, not only according to what He is in Himself, but also according as
He acts on others, He laid this natural law on all things, that last
things should be reduced and perfected by middle things, and middle
things by the first, as Dionysius says (Eccl. Hier. v). Wherefore that
this beauty might not be lacking to the Church, He established Order in
her so that some should deliver the sacraments to others, being thus made
like to God in their own way, as co-operating with God; even as in the
natural body, some members act on others.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The subjection of slavery is incompatible with liberty; for
slavery consists in lording over others and employing them for one's own
profit. Such subjection is not required in Order, whereby those who
preside have to seek the salvation of their subjects and not their own
profit.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Each one should esteem himself lower in merit, not in
office; and orders are a kind of office.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Order among the angels does not arise from difference of
nature, unless accidentally, in so far as difference of grace results in
them from difference of nature. But in them it results directly from
their difference in grace; because their orders regard their
participation of divine things, and their communicating them in the state
of glory, which is according to the measure of grace, as being the end
and effect, so to speak, of grace. on the other hand, the Orders of the
Church militant regard the participation in the sacraments and the
communication thereof, which are the cause of grace and, in a way,
precede grace; and consequently our Orders do not require sanctifying
grace, but only the power to dispense the sacraments; for which reason
order does not correspond to the difference of sanctifying grace, but to
the difference of power.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether Order is properly defined?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that order is improperly defined by the Master
(Sent. iv, D, 53), where it is said "Order is a seal of the Church,
whereby spiritual power is conferred on the person ordained." For a part
should not be described as the genus of the whole. Now the character
which is denoted by the seal in a subsequent definition is a part of
order, since it is placed in contradistinction with that which is either
reality only, or sacrament only, since it is both reality and sacrament.
Therefore seal should not be mentioned as the genus of Order.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, just as a character is imprinted in the sacrament of
order, so is it in the sacrament of Baptism. Now character was not
mentioned in the definition of Baptism. Therefore neither should it be
mentioned in the definition of Order.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, in Baptism there is also given a certain spiritual power
to approach the sacraments; and again it is a seal, since it is a
sacrament. Therefore this definition is applicable to Baptism; and
consequently it is improperly applied to Order.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[2] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, Order is a kind of relation, and relation is realized in
both its terms. Now the terms of the relation of order are the superior
and the inferior. Therefore inferiors have order as well as superiors.
Yet there is no power of preeminence in them, such as is mentioned here
in the definition of Order, as appears from the subsequent explanation
(Sent. iv, D, 53), where promotion to power is mentioned. Therefore Order
is improperly defined there.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, The Master's definition of Order applies to Order as a
sacrament of the Church. Hence he mentions two things, namely the outward
sign, a "kind of seal," i.e. a kind of sign, and the inward effect,
"whereby spiritual power," etc.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Seal stands here, not for the inward character, but for the
outward action, which is the sign and cause of inward power; and this is
also the sense of character in the other definition. If, however, it be
taken for the inward character, the definition would not be unsuitable;
because the division of a sacrament into those three things is not a
division into integral parts, properly speaking; since what is reality
only is not essential to the sacrament, and that which is the sacrament
is transitory; while that which is sacrament and reality is said to
remain. Wherefore it follows that inward character itself is essentially
and principally the sacrament of Order.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Although in Baptism there is conferred a spiritual power to
receive the other sacraments, for which reason it imprints a character,
nevertheless this is not its principal effect, but the inward cleansing;
wherefore Baptism would be given even though the former motive did not
exist. On the other hand, order denotes power principally. Wherefore the
character which is a spiritual power is included in the definition of
Order, but not in that of Baptism.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: In Baptism there is given a certain spiritual potentiality
to receive, and consequently a somewhat passive potentiality. But power
properly denotes active potentiality, together with some kind of
preeminence. Hence this definition is not applicable to Baptism.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[2] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: The word "order" is used in two ways. For sometimes it
denotes the relation itself, and thus it is both in the inferior and in
the superior, as the objection states; but it is not thus that we use the
word here. On the other hand, it denotes the degree which results in the
order taken in the first sense. And since the notion of order as relation
is observed where we first meet with something higher than another, it
follows that this degree of pre-eminence by spiritual power is called
Order.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether Order is a sacrament?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that Order is not a sacrament. For a sacrament,
according to Hugh of St. Victor (De Sacram. i) "is a material element."
Now Order denotes nothing of the kind, but rather relation or power;
since Order is a part of power according to Isidore. Therefore it is not
a sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the sacraments do not concern the Church triumphant. Yet
Order is there, as in the angels. Therefore it is not a sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, just as spiritual authority, which is Order, is given by
means of consecration, so is secular authority, since kings also are
anointed, as stated above (Q[19], A[3], ad 2). But the kingly power is
not a sacrament. Therefore neither is order of which we speak now.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[3] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, It is mentioned by all among the seven sacraments of
the Church.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[3] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, "the cause of a thing being such, is still more so." Now Order
is the cause of man being the dispenser of the other sacraments.
Therefore Order has more reason for being a sacrament than the others.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[3] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, As stated above (Q[29], A[1]; TP, Q[60]), a sacrament is
nothing else than a sanctification conferred on man with some outward
sign. Wherefore, since by receiving orders a consecration is conferred on
man by visible signs, it is clear that Order is a sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Although Order does not by its name express a material
element, it is not conferred without some material element.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Power must needs be proportionate to the purpose for which
it is intended. Now the communication of divine things, which is the
purpose for which spiritual power is given, is not effected among the
angels by means of sensible signs, as is the case among men. Hence the
spiritual power that is Order is not bestowed on the angels by visible
signs, as on men. Wherefore Order is a sacrament among men, but not among
angels.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Not every blessing or consecration given to men is a
sacrament, for both monks and abbots are blessed, and yet such blessings
are not sacraments, and in like manner neither is the anointing of a
king; because by such blessings men are not ordained to the dispensing of
the divine sacraments, as by the blessing of Order. Hence the comparison
fails.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the form of this sacrament is suitably expressed?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the form of this sacrament is unsuitably set
forth in the text (Sent. iv, D, 24). Because the sacraments take their
efficacy from their form. Now the efficacy of the sacraments is from the
divine power, which works our salvation in them in a most hidden manner.
Therefore the form of this sacrament should include a mention of the
divine power by the invocation of the Trinity, as in the other sacraments.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, to command pertains to one who has authority. Now the
dispenser of the sacrament exercises no authority, but only ministry.
Therefore he should not use the imperative mood by saying: "Do" or
"Receive" this or that, or some similar expression.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[4] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, mention should not be made in the sacramental form,
except of such things as are essential to the sacrament. But the use of
the power received is not essential to this sacrament, but is consequent
upon it. Therefore it should not be mentioned in the form of this
sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[4] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, all the sacraments direct us to an eternal reward. But
the forms of the other sacraments make no mention of a reward. Therefore
neither should any mention be made thereof in the form of this sacrament,
as in the words: "Since thou wilt have a share, if faithfully," etc.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[4] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, This sacrament consists chiefly in the power conferred.
Now power is conferred by power, as like proceeds from like; and again
power is made known by its use, since powers are manifested by their
acts. Wherefore in the form of order the use of order is expressed by the
act which is commanded; and the conferring of power is expressed by
employing the imperative mood.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The other sacraments are not ordained chiefly to effects
similar to the power whereby the sacraments are dispensed, as this
sacrament is. Hence in this sacrament there is a kind of universal
communication. Wherefore in the other sacraments something is expressed
on the part of the divine power to which the effect of the sacrament is
likened, but not in this sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: [There is a special reason why this sacrament, rather than
the others, is conferred by employing the imperative mood. For]* although
the bishop who is the minister of this sacrament has no authority in
respect of the conferring of this sacrament, nevertheless he has some
power with regard to the power of Order, which power he confers, in so
far as it is derived, from his. [*The sentence in brackets is not in the
Leonine edition.]
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[4] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: The use of power is the effect of power in the genus of
efficient cause, and from this point of view it has no reason to be
mentioned in the definition of Order. But it is somewhat a cause in the
genus of final cause, and from this point of view it can be placed in
the definition of order.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[4] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: There is here a difference between this and the other
sacraments. Because by this sacrament an office or the power to do
something is conferred; and so it is fitting that mention be made of the
reward to be obtained if it be administered faithfully. But in the other
sacraments no such office or power to act is conferred, and so no mention
of reward is made in them. Accordingly the recipient is somewhat passive
in relation to the other sacraments, because he receives them for the
perfecting of his own state only, whereas in relation to this sacrament
he holds himself somewhat actively, since he receives it for the sake of
exercising hierarchical duties in the Church. Wherefore although the
other sacraments, from the very fact that they give grace, direct the
recipient to salvation, properly speaking they do not direct him to a
reward, in the same way as this sacrament does.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[5] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether this sacrament has any matter?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[5] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that this sacrament has no matter. Because in every
sacrament that has a matter the power that works in the sacrament is in
the matter. But in the material objects which are used here, such as
keys, candlesticks, and so forth, there is not apparently any power of
sanctification. Therefore it has no matter.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[5] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, in this sacrament the fulness of sevenfold grace is
conferred, as stated in the text (Sent. iv, D, 24), just as in
Confirmation. But the matter of Confirmation requires to be consecrated
beforehand. Since then the things which appear to be material in this
sacrament are not consecrated beforehand, it would seem that they are not
the matter of the sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[5] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, in any sacrament that has matter there needs to be
contact of matter with the recipient of the sacrament. Now, as some say,
it is not essential to this sacrament that there be contact between the
aforesaid material objects and the recipient of the sacrament, but only
that they be presented to him. Therefore the aforesaid material objects
are not the matter of this sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[5] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, Every sacrament consists of things and words. Now in
any sacrament the thing is the matter. Therefore the things employed in
this sacrament are its matter.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[5] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, more is requisite to dispense the sacraments than to receive
them. Yet Baptism, wherein the power is given to receive the sacraments,
needs a matter. Therefore order also does, wherein the power is given to
dispense them.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[5] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, The matter employed outwardly in the sacraments signifies
that the power which works in the sacraments comes entirely from without.
Wherefore, since the effect proper to this sacrament, namely the
character, is not received through any operation of the one who
approaches the sacrament, as was the case in Penance, but comes wholly
from without, it is fitting that it should have a matter, yet otherwise
than the other sacraments that have matter; because that which is
bestowed in the other sacraments comes from God alone, and not from the
minister who dispenses the sacrament; whereas that which is conferred in
this sacrament, namely the spiritual power, comes also from him who gives
the sacrament, as imperfect from perfect power. Hence the efficacy of the
other sacraments resides chiefly in the matter which both signifies and
contains the divine power through the sanctification applied by the
minister; whereas the efficacy of this sacrament resides chiefly with him
who dispenses the sacrament. And the matter is employed to show the
powers conferred in particular by one who has it completely, rather than
to cause power; and this is clear from the fact that the matter is in
keeping with the use of power. This suffices for the Reply to the First
Objection.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[5] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: It is necessary for the matter to be consecrated in the
other sacraments, on account of the power it contains; but it is not so
in the case in point.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[34] A[5] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: If we admit this assertion, the reason for it is clear from
what we have said; for since the power of order is received from the
minister and not from the matter, the presenting of the matter is more
essential to the sacrament than contact therewith. However, the words
themselves of the form would seem to indicate that contact with the
matter is essential to the sacrament, for it is said: "Receive" this or
that.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[35] Out. Para. 1/2
OF THE EFFECT OF THIS SACRAMENT (FIVE ARTICLES)
We must next consider me effect of this sacrament. Under this head there
are five points of inquiry:
(1) Whether sanctifying grace is conferred in the sacrament of Order?
(2) Whether a character is imprinted in connection with all the Orders?
(3) Whether the character of Order presupposes of necessity the
character of Baptism?
(4) Whether it presupposes of necessity the character of Confirmation?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[35] Out. Para. 2/2
(5) Whether the character of one Order presupposes of necessity the
character of another Order?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[35] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether sanctifying grace is conferred in the sacrament of Order?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[35] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that sanctifying grace is not conferred in the
sacrament of Order. For it is commonly agreed that the sacrament of Order
is directed to counteract the defect of ignorance. Now not sanctifying
grace but gratuitous grace is given to counteract ignorance, for
sanctifying grace has more to do with the will. Therefore sanctifying
grace is not given in the sacrament of Order.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[35] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, Order implies distinction. Now the members of the Church
are distinguished, not by sanctifying but by gratuitous grace, of which
it is said (1 Cor. 12:4): "There are diversities of graces." Therefore
sanctifying grace is not given in order.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[35] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, no cause presupposes its effect. But grace is
presupposed in one who receives orders, so that he may be worthy to
receive them. Therefore this same grace is not given in the conferring of
Orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[35] A[1] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, The sacraments of the New Law cause what they signify.
Now Order by its sevenfold number signifies the seven gifts of the Holy
Ghost, as stated in the text (Sent. iv, D, 24). Therefore the gifts of
the Holy Ghost, which are not apart from sanctifying grace, are given in
Orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[35] A[1] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, Order is a sacrament of the New Law. Now the definition of a
sacrament of that kind includes the words, "that it may be a cause of
grace." Therefore it causes grace in the recipient.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[35] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that The works of God are perfect (Dt. 32:4); and consequently
whoever receives power from above receives also those things that render
him competent to exercise that power. This is also the case in natural
things, since animals are provided with members, by which their soul's
powers are enabled to proceed to their respective actions unless there be
some defect on the part of matter. Now just as sanctifying grace is
necessary in order that man receive the sacraments worthily, so is it
that he may dispense them worthily. Wherefore as in Baptism, whereby a
man is adapted to receive the other sacraments, sanctifying grace is
given, so is it in the sacrament of Order whereby man is ordained to the
dispensation of the other sacraments.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[35] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Order is given as a remedy, not to one person but to the
whole Church. Hence, although it is said to be given in order to
counteract ignorance, it does not mean that by receiving Orders a man has
his ignorance driven out of him, but that the recipient of Orders is set
in authority to expel ignorance from among the people.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[35] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Although the gifts of sanctifying grace are common to all
the members of the Church, nevertheless a man cannot be the worthy
recipient of those gifts, in respect of which the members of the Church
are distinguished from one another, unless he have charity, and this
cannot be apart from sanctifying grace.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[35] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: The worthy exercise of Orders requires not any kind of
goodness but excellent goodness, in order that as they who receive orders
are set above the people in the degree of Order, so may they be above
them by the merit of holiness. Hence they are required to have the grace
that suffices to make them worthy members of Christ's people, but when
they receive Orders they are given a yet greater gift of grace, whereby
they are rendered apt for greater things.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[35] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether in the sacrament of Order a character is imprinted in connection
with all the Orders?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[35] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that in the sacrament of Order a character is not
imprinted in connection with all the Orders. For the character of Order
is a spiritual power. Now some Orders are directed only to certain bodily
acts, for instance those of the doorkeeper or of the acolyte. Therefore a
character is not imprinted in these Orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[35] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, every character is indelible. Therefore a character
places a man in a state whence he cannot withdraw. Now those who have
certain Orders can lawfully return to the laity. Therefore a character is
not imprinted in all the Orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[35] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, by means of a character a man is appointed to give or to
receive some sacred thing. Now a man is sufficiently adapted to the
reception of the sacraments by the character of Baptism, and a man is not
appointed to dispense the sacraments except in the Order of priesthood.
Therefore a character is not imprinted in the other Orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[35] A[2] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, Every sacrament in which a character is not imprinted
can be repeated. But no Order can be repeated. Therefore a character is
imprinted in each Order.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[35] A[2] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, a character is a distinctive sign. Now there is something
distinct in every Order. Therefore every Order imprints a character.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[35] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, There have been three opinions on this point. For some
have said that a character is imprinted only in the Order of priesthood;
but this is not true, since none but a deacon can exercise the act of the
diaconate, and so it is clear that in the dispensation of the sacraments,
he has a spiritual power which others have not. For this reason others
have said that a character is impressed in the sacred, but not in the
minor, Orders. But this again comes to nothing, since each Order sets a
man above the people in some degree of authority directed to the
dispensation of the sacraments. Wherefore since a character is a sign
whereby one thing is distinguished from another, it follows that a
character is imprinted in each Order. And this is confirmed by the fact
that they remain for ever and are never repeated. This is the third and
more common opinion.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[35] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Each Order either has an act connected with the sacrament
itself, or adapts a man to the dispensation of the sacraments; thus
doorkeepers exercise the act of admitting men to witness the Divine
sacraments, and so forth; and consequently a spiritual power is required
in each.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[35] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/2
Reply OBJ 2: For all that a man may return to the laity, the character
always remains in him. This is evident from the fact that if he return to
the clerical state, he does not receive again the order which he had
already.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[35] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 2/2
The Reply to the Third Objection is the same as to the First.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[35] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the character of Order presupposes the baptismal character?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[35] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the character of Order does not presuppose the
character of Baptism. For the character of Order makes a man a dispenser
of the sacraments; while the character of Baptism makes him a recipient
of them. Now active power does not necessarily presuppose passive power,
for it can be without it, as in God. Therefore the character of Order
does not necessarily presuppose the character of Baptism.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[35] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, it may happen that a man is not baptized, and yet think
with probability that he has been baptized. If therefore such a person
present himself for Orders, he will not receive the character of Order,
supposing the character of Order to presuppose the character of Baptism;
and consequently whatever he does by way of consecration or absolution
will be invalid, and the Church will be deceived therein, which is
inadmissible.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[35] A[3] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, Baptism is the door of the sacraments. Therefore since
Order is a sacrament, it presupposes Baptism.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[35] A[3] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, No one can receive what he has not the power to receive.
Now the character of Baptism gives a man the power to receive the other
sacraments. Wherefore he that has not the baptismal character, can
receive no other sacrament; and consequently the character of Order
presupposes the character of Baptism.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[35] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: In one who has active power of himself, the active does not
presuppose the passive power; but in one who has active power from
another, passive power, whereby he is enabled to receive the active
power, is prerequisite to active power.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[35] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Such a man if he be ordained to the priesthood is not a
priest, and he can neither consecrate, nor absolve in the tribunal of
Penance. Wherefore according to the canons he must be baptized, and
reordained (Extra De Presbyt. non Bapt., cap. Si quis; cap. Veniens). And
even though he be raised to the episcopate, those whom he ordains receive
not the Order. Yet it may piously be believed that as regards the
ultimate effects of the sacraments, the High Priest will supply the
defect, and that He would not allow this to be so hidden as to endanger
the Church.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[35] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the character of Order necessarily presupposes the character of
Confirmation?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[35] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the character of Order necessarily presupposes
the character of Confirmation. For in things subordinate to one another,
as the middle presupposes the first, so does the last presuppose the
middle. Now the character of Confirmation presupposes that of Baptism as
being the first. Therefore the character of Order presupposes that of
Confirmation as being in the middle.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[35] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, those who are appointed to confirm should themselves be
most firm. Now those who receive the sacrament of Order are appointed to
confirm others. Therefore they especially should have received the
sacrament of Confirmation.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[35] A[4] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, The apostles received the power of order before the
Ascension (Jn. 20:22), where it is said: "Receive the Holy Ghost." But
they were confirmed after the Ascension by the coming of the Holy Ghost.
Therefore order does not presuppose Confirmation.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[35] A[4] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, For the reception of Orders something is prerequisite for
the validity of the sacrament, and something as congruous to the
sacrament. For the validity of the sacrament it is required that one who
presents himself for Orders should be capable of receiving them, and this
is competent to him through Baptism; wherefore the baptismal character is
prerequisite for the validity of the sacrament, so that the sacrament of
Order cannot be conferred without it. On the other hand, as congruous to
the sacrament a man is required to have every perfection whereby he
becomes adapted to the exercise of Orders, and one of these is that he be
confirmed. Wherefore the character of Order presupposes the character of
Confirmation as congruous but not as necessary.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[35] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: In this case the middle does not stand in the same relation
to the last as the first to the middle, because the character of Baptism
enables a man to receive the sacrament of Confirmation, whereas the
character of Confirmation does not enable a man to receive the sacrament
of Order. Hence the comparison fails.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[35] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: This argument considers aptness by way of congruity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[35] A[5] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the character of one Order necessarily presupposes the character
of another Order?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[35] A[5] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the character of one Order necessarily
presupposes the character of another Order. For there is more in common
between one Order and another, than between Order and another sacrament.
But the character of Order presupposes the character of another
sacrament, namely Baptism. Much more therefore does the character of one
Order presuppose the character of another.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[35] A[5] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the Orders are degrees of a kind. Now no one can reach a
further degree, unless he first mount the previous degree. Therefore no
one can receive the character of a subsequent Order unless he has first
received the preceding Order.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[35] A[5] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, If anything necessary for a sacrament be omitted in
that sacrament, the sacrament must be repeated. But if one receive a
subsequent Order, without receiving a preceding Order, he is not
reordained, but he receives what was lacking, according to the canonical
statutes (cap. Tuae literae, De clerico per salt. prom.). Therefore the
preceding Order is not necessary for the following.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[35] A[5] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, It is not necessary for the higher Orders that one should
have received the minor Orders, because their respective powers are
distinct, and one, considered in its essentials, does not require another
in the same subject. Hence even in the early Church some were ordained
priests without having previously received the lower Orders and yet they
could do all that the lower Orders could, because the lower power is
comprised in the higher, even as sense in understanding, and dukedom in
kingdom. Afterwards, however, it was decided by the legislation of the
Church that no one should present himself to the higher orders who had
not previously humbled himself in the lower offices. And hence it is that
according to the Canons (cap. Tuae literae, De clerico per salt. prom.)
those who are ordained without receiving a preceding Order are not
reordained, but receive what was lacking to them of the preceding Order.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[35] A[5] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Orders have more in common with one another as regards
specific likeness, than order has with Baptism. But as regards proportion
of power to action, Baptism has more in common with Order, than one Order
with another, because Baptism confers on man the passive power to receive
Orders, whereas a lower Order does not give him the passive power to
receive higher Orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[35] A[5] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Orders are not degrees combining in one action or in one
movement, so that it be necessary to reach the last through the first;
but they are like degrees consisting in things of different kinds, such
as the degrees between man and angel, and it is not necessary that one
who is an angel be first of all a man. Such also are the degrees between
the head and all members of the body; nor is it necessary that that which
is the head should be previously a foot; and thus it is in the case in
point.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] Out. Para. 1/1
OF THE QUALITIES REQUIRED OF THOSE WHO RECEIVE THIS SACRAMENT (FIVE
ARTICLES)
We must next consider the qualities required of those who receive the
sacrament of Order. Under this head there are five points of inquiry:
(1) Whether goodness of life is required of those who receive this
sacrament?
(2) Whether the knowledge of the whole of Sacred Writ is required?
(3) Whether the degree of Orders is obtained by mere merit of life?
(4) Whether he who raises the unworthy to Orders sins?
(5) Whether one who is in sin can without committing a sin exercise the
Order he has received?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether goodness of life is required of those who receive Orders?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that goodness of life is not required of those who
receive Orders. For by Orders a man is ordained to the dispensation of
the sacraments. But the sacraments can be administered by good and
wicked. Therefore goodness of life is not requisite.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the service of God in the sacraments is no greater than
service offered to Him in the body. Now our Lord did not cast aside the
sinful and notorious woman from rendering Him a bodily service (Lk. 7).
Therefore neither should the like be debarred from His service in the
sacraments.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, by every grace a remedy is given against sin. Now those
who are in sin should not be refused a remedy that may avail them. Since
then grace is given in the sacrament of order, it would seem that this
sacrament ought also to be conferred on sinners.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[1] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, "Whosoever of the seed of Aaron throughout their
families hath a blemish, he shall not offer bread to his God neither
shall he approach to minister to him [*Vulg.: 'Say to Aaron: Whosoever of
thy seed,'etc.]" (Lev. 21:17,18). Now "blemish signifies all kinds of
vice" according to a gloss. Therefore he who is shackled by any vice
should not be admitted to the ministry of Orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[1] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, Jerome commenting on the words of Titus 2:15, "Let no man
despise thee," says that "not only should bishops, priests, and deacons
take very great care to be examples of speech and conduct to those over
whom they are placed, but also the lower grades, and without exception
all who serve the household of God, since it is most disastrous to the
Church if the laity be better than the clergy." Therefore holiness of
life is requisite in all the Orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, As Dionysius says (Eccl. Hier. iii), "even as the more
subtle and clear essences, being filled by the outpouring of the solar
radiance, like the sun enlighten other bodies with their brilliant light,
so in all things pertaining to God a man must not dare to become a leader
of others, unless in all his habits he be most deiform and godlike."
Wherefore, since in every order a man is appointed to lead others in
Divine things, he who being conscious of mortal sin presents himself for
Orders is guilty of presumption and sins mortally. Consequently holiness
of life is requisite for Orders, as a matter of precept, but not as
essential to the sacrament; and if a wicked man be ordained, he receives
the Order none the less, and yet with sin withal.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Just as the sinner dispenses sacraments validly, so does he
receive validly the sacrament of Orders, and as he dispenses unworthily,
even so he receives unworthily.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The service in point consisted only in the exercise of
bodily homage, which even sinners can offer lawfully. It is different
with the spiritual service to which the ordained are appointed, because
thereby they are made to stand between God and the people. Wherefore they
should shine with a good conscience before God, and with a good name
before men.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Certain medicines require a robust constitution, else it is
mortally dangerous to take them; others can be given to the weakly. So
too in spiritual things certain sacraments are ordained as remedies for
sin, and the like are to be given to sinners, as Baptism and Penance,
while others, which confer the perfection of grace, require a man made
strong by grace.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether knowledge of all Holy Writ is required?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that knowledge of all Holy Writ is required. For
one from whose lips we seek the law, should have knowledge of the law.
Now the laity seek the law at the mouth of the priest (Malachi 2:7).
Therefore he should have knowledge of the whole law.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, "being always ready to satisfy everyone that asketh you
a reason of that faith and hope in you [*Vulg.: 'Of that hope which is in
you; St. Thomas apparently took his reading from Bede]." Now to give a
reason for things pertaining to faith and hope belongs to those who have
perfect knowledge of Holy Writ. Therefore the like knowledge should be
possessed by those who are placed in Orders, and to whom the aforesaid
words are addressed.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, no one is competent to read what he understands not,
since to read without intelligence is "negligence,"* as Cato declares
(Rudiment.). [*"Legere et non intelligere est negligere." The play on the
words is more evident in Latin.] Now it belongs to the reader (which is
the lower Order) to read the Old Testament, as stated in the text (Sent.
iv, D, 24). Therefore he should understand the whole of the Old
Testament; and much more those in the higher Orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[2] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, Many are raised to the priesthood even who know nothing
at all of these things, even in many religious Orders. Therefore
apparently this knowledge is not required.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[2] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, we read in the Lives of the Fathers that some who were monks
were raised to the priesthood, being of a most holy life. Therefore the
aforesaid knowledge is not required in those to be ordained.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, For any human act to be rightly ordered there must needs
be the direction of reason. Wherefore in order that a man exercise the
office of an Order, it is necessary for him to have as much knowledge as
suffices for his direction in the act of that Order. And consequently one
who is to be raised to Orders is required to have that knowledge, and to
be instructed in Sacred Scripture, not the whole, but more or less,
according as his office is of a greater or lesser extent---to wit, that
those who are placed over others, and receive the care of souls, know
things pertaining to the doctrine of faith and morals, and that others
know whatever concerns the exercise of their Order.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: A priest exercises a twofold action: the one, which is
principal, over the true body of Christ; the other, which is secondary,
over the mystical body of Christ. The second act depends on the first,
but not conversely. Wherefore some are raised to the priesthood, to whom
the first act alone is deputed, for instance those religious who are not
empowered with the care of souls. The law is not sought at the mouth of
these, they are required only for the celebration of the sacraments; and
consequently it is enough for them to have such knowledge as enables them
to observe rightly those things that regard the celebration of the
sacrament. Others are raised to exercise the other act which is over the
mystical body of Christ, and it is at the mouth of these that the people
seek the law; wherefore they ought to possess knowledge of the law, not
indeed to know all the difficult points of the law (for in these they
should have recourse to their superiors), but to know what the people
have to believe and fulfill in the law. To the higher priests, namely the
bishops, it belongs to know even those points of the law which may offer
some difficulty, and to know them the more perfectly according as they
are in a higher position.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The reason that we have to give for our faith and hope does
not denote one that suffices to prove matters of faith and hope, since
they are both of things invisible; it means that we should be able to
give general proofs of the probability of both, and for this there is not
much need of great knowledge.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: The reader has not to explain Holy Writ to the people (for
this belongs to the higher orders), but merely to voice the words.
Therefore he is not required to have so much knowledge as to understand
Holy Writ, but only to know how to pronounce it correctly. And since such
knowledge is obtained easily and from many persons, it may be supposed
with probability that the ordained will acquire that knowledge even if he
have it not already, especially if it appear that he is on the road to
acquire it.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether a man obtains the degrees of Order by the merit of one's life?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that a man obtains the degrees of order by the mere
merit of his life. For, according to Chrysostom [*Hom. xliii in the Opus
Imperfectum, wrongly ascribed to St. John Chrysostom], "not every priest
is a saint, but every saint is a priest." Now a man becomes a saint by
the merit of his life. Consequently he thereby also becomes a priest, and
"a fortiori" has he the other Orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, in natural things, men obtain a higher degree from the
very fact that they are near God, and have a greater share of His favors,
as Dionysius says (Eccl. Hier. iv). Now it is by merit of holiness and
knowledge that a man approaches nearer to God and receives more of His
favors. Therefore by this alone he is raised to the degree of Orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[3] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, Holiness once possessed can be lost. But when once a
man is ordained he never loses his order. Therefore order does not
consist in the mere merit of holiness.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[3] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, A cause should be proportionate to its effect. And
consequently as in Christ, from Whom grace comes down on all men, there
must needs be fulness of grace; so in the ministers of the Church, to
whom it belongs, not to give grace, but to give the sacraments of grace,
the degree of order does not result from their having grace, but from
their participating in a sacrament of grace.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Chrysostom is speaking of the priest in reference to the
reason for which he is so called, the word "sacerdos" signifying
dispenser of holy things [sacra dans]: for in this sense every righteous
man, in so far as he assists others by the sacraments, may be called a
priest. But he is not speaking according to the actual meaning of the
words; for this word "sacerdos" [priest] is employed to signify one who
gives sacred things by dispensing the sacraments.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Natural things acquire a degree of superiority over others,
from the fact that they are able to act on them by virtue of their form;
wherefore from the very fact that they have a higher form, they obtain a
higher degree. But the ministers of the Church are placed over others,
not to confer anything on them by virtue of their own holiness (for this
belongs to God alone), but as ministers, and as instruments, so to say,
of the outpouring from the Head to the members. Hence the comparison
fails as regards the dignity of Order, although it applies as to
congruity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether he who raises the unworthy to Orders commits a sin?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that he who raises the unworthy to orders commits
no sin. For a bishop needs assistants appointed to the lesser offices.
But he would be unable to find them in sufficient number, if he were to
require of them such qualifications as the saints enumerate. Therefore if
he raise some who are not qualified, he would seem to be excusable.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the Church needs not only ministers for the dispensation
of things spiritual, but also for the supervision of temporalities. But
sometimes men without knowledge or holiness of life may be useful for the
conduct of temporal affairs, either because of their worldly power, or on
account of their natural industry. Therefore seemingly the like can be
promoted without sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[4] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, everyone is bound to avoid sin, as far as he can. If
therefore a bishop sins in promoting the unworthy, he is bound to take
the utmost pains to know whether those who present themselves for Orders
be worthy, by making a careful inquiry about their morals and knowledge,
and yet seemingly this is not done anywhere.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[4] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, It is worse to raise the wicked to the sacred ministry,
than not to correct those who are raised already. But Heli sinned
mortally by not correcting his sons for their wickedness; wherefore "he
fell backwards . . . and died" (1 Kgs. 4:18). Therefore he who promotes
the unworthy does not escape sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[4] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, spiritual things must be set before temporal things in the
Church. Now a man would commit a mortal sin were he knowingly to endanger
the temporalities of the Church. Much more therefore is it a mortal sin
to endanger spiritual things. But whoever promotes the unworthy endangers
spiritual things, since according to Gregory (Hom. xii in Evang.) "if a
man's life is contemptible, his preaching is liable to be despised"; and
for the same reason all the spiritual things that he dispenses. Therefore
he who promotes the unworthy sins mortally.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[4] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Our Lord describes the faithful servant whom He has set
"over His household to give them their measure of wheat." Hence he is
guilty of unfaithfulness who gives any man Divine things above his
measure: and whoso promotes the unworthy does this. Wherefore he commits
a mortal crime, as being unfaithful to his sovereign Lord, especially
since this is detrimental to the Church and to the Divine honor which is
promoted by good ministers. For a man would be unfaithful to his earthly
lord were he to place unworthy subjects in his offices.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: God never so abandons His Church that apt ministers are not
to be found sufficient for the needs of the people, if the worthy be
promoted and the unworthy set aside. And though it were impossible to
find as many ministers as there are now, it were better to have few good
ministers than many bad ones, as the blessed Clement declares in his
second epistle to James the brother of the Lord.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Temporal things are not to be sought but for the sake of
spiritual things. Wherefore all temporal advantage should count for
nothing, and all gain be despised for the advancement of spiritual good.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[4] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: It is at least required that the ordainer know that nothing
contrary to holiness is in the candidate for ordination. But besides this
he is required to take the greatest care, in proportion to the Order or
office to be enjoined, so as to be certain of the qualifications of those
to be promoted, at least from the testification of others. This is the
meaning of the Apostle when he says (1 Tim. 5:22): "Impose not hands
lightly on any man."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[5] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether a man who is in sin can without sin exercise the Order he has
received? [*Cf. TP, Q[64], A[6]]
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[5] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that one who is in sin can without sin exercise the
order he has received. For since, by virtue of his office, he is bound to
exercise his order, he sins if he fails to do so. If therefore he sins by
exercising it, he cannot avoid sin: which is inadmissible.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[5] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, a dispensation is a relaxation of the law. Therefore
although by rights it would be unlawful for him to exercise the order he
has received, it would be lawful for him to do so by dispensation.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[5] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, whoever co-operates with another in a mortal sin, sins
mortally. If therefore a sinner sins mortally by exercising his order, he
who receives or demands any Divine thing from him also sins mortally: and
this seems absurd.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[5] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, if he sins by exercising his order, it follows that
every act of his order that he performs is a mortal sin; and consequently
since many acts concur in the one exercise of his order, it would seem
that he commits many mortal sins: which seems very hard.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[5] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, Dionysius says (Ep. ad Demophil.): "It seems
presumptuous for such a man, one to wit who is not enlightened, to lay
hands on priestly things; he is not afraid nor ashamed, all unworthy that
he is to take part in Divine things, with the thought that God does not
see what he sees in himself; he thinks, by false pretense, to cheat Him
Whom he falsely calls his Father; he dares to utter in the person of
Christ, words polluted by his infamy, I will not call them prayers, over
the Divine symbols." Therefore a priest is a blasphemer and a cheat if he
exercises his order unworthily, and thus he sins mortally: and in like
manner any other person in orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[5] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, holiness of life is required in one who receives an order, that
he may be qualified to exercise it. Now a man sins mortally if he present
himself for orders in mortal sin. Much more therefore does he sin
mortally whenever he exercises his order.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[5] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, The law prescribes (Dt. 16:20) that "man should follow
justly after that which is just." Wherefore whoever fulfills unworthily
the duties of his order follows unjustly after that which is just, and
acts contrary to a precept of the law, and thereby sins mortally. Now
anyone who exercises a sacred office in mortal sin, without doubt does so
unworthily. Hence it is clear that he sins mortally.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[5] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: He is not perplexed as though he were in the necessity of
sinning; for he can renounce his sin, or resign his office whereby he was
bound to the exercise of his order.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[5] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The natural law allows of no dispensation; and it is of
natural law that man handle holy things holily. Therefore no one can
dispense from this.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[5] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: So long as a minister of the Church who is in mortal sin is
recognized by the Church, his subject must receive the sacraments from
him, since this is the purpose for which he is bound to him.
Nevertheless, outside the case of necessity, it would not be safe to
induce him to an execution of his Order, as long as he is conscious of
being in mortal sin, which conscience, however, he can lay aside since a
man is repaired in an instant by Divine grace.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[36] A[5] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: When any man performs an action as a minister of the Church
while in a state of mortal sin, he sins mortally, and as often as he
performs that action, since, as Dionysius says (Eccl. Hier. i), "it is
wrong for the unclean even to touch the symbols," i.e. the sacramental
signs. Hence when they touch sacred things in the exercise of their
office they sin mortally. It would be otherwise if they were to touch
some sacred thing or perform some sacred duty in a case of necessity,
when it would be allowable even to a layman, for instance if they were to
baptize in a case of urgency, or gather up the Lord's body should it be
cast to the ground.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] Out. Para. 1/1
OF THE DISTINCTION OF ORDERS, OF THEIR ACTS, AND THE IMPRINTING OF THE
CHARACTER (FIVE ARTICLES)
In the next place we must consider the distinction of the orders and
their acts, and the imprinting of the character. Under this head there
are five points of inquiry:
(1) Whether Order should be divided into several kinds?
(2) How many are there?
(3) Whether they ought to be divided into those that are sacred and
those that are not?
(4) Whether the acts of the Orders are rightly assigned in the text?
(5) When are the characters of the Orders imprinted?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether we ought to distinguish several Orders?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that we ought not to distinguish several Orders.
For the greater a power is, the less is it multiplied. Now this sacrament
ranks above the others in so far as it places its recipients in a degree
above other persons. Since then the other sacraments are not divided into
several of which the whole is predicated, neither ought this sacrament to
be divided into several Orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, if it be divided, the parts of the division are either
integral or subjective. But they are not integral, for then the whole
would not be predicated of them. Therefore it is a division into
subjective parts. Now subjective parts can have the remote genus
predicated of them in the plural in the same way as the proximate genus;
thus man and ass are several animals, and are several animated bodies.
Therefore also priesthood and diaconate, as they are several Orders, even
so are several sacraments, since sacrament is the genus, so to speak, in
respect of Orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, according to the Philosopher (Ethic. viii, 10) the form
of authority in which one alone governs is a better government of the
common weal than aristocracy, where different persons occupy different
offices. But the government of the Church should be the best of all.
Therefore in the Church there should be no distinction of Orders for
different acts, but the whole power should reside in one person; and
consequently there ought to be only one Order.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[1] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, The Church is Christ's mystical body, like to our
natural body, according to the Apostle (Rm. 12:5; 1 Cor. 12:12,27; Eph.
1:22,23; Col. 1:24). Now in the natural body there are various offices of
the members. Therefore in the Church also there should be various Orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[1] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, the ministry of the New Testament is superior to that of the
Old Testament (2 Cor. 3). Now in the Old Testament not only the priests,
but also their ministers, the Levites, were consecrated. Therefore
likewise in the New Testament not only the priests but also their
ministers should be consecrated by the sacrament of Order; and
consequently there ought to be several Orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Multiplicity of Orders was introduced into the Church for
three reasons. First to show forth the wisdom of God, which is reflected
in the orderly distinction of things both natural and spiritual. This is
signified in the statement of 3 Kgs. 10:4,[5] that "when the queen of
Saba saw . . . the order of" Solomon's "servants . . . she had no longer
any spirit in her," for she was breathless from admiration of his wisdom.
Secondly, in order to succor human weakness, because it would be
impossible for one man, without his being heavily burdened, to fulfill
all things pertaining to the Divine mysteries; and so various orders are
severally appointed to the various offices; and this is shown by the Lord
giving Moses seventy ancients to assist him. Thirdly, that men may be
given a broader way for advancing (to perfection), seeing that the
various duties are divided among many men, so that all become the
co-operators of God; than which nothing is more God-like, as Dionysius
says (Eccl. Hier. iii).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The other sacraments are given that certain effects may be
received; but this sacrament is given chiefly that certain acts may be
performed. Hence it behooves the sacrament of Order to be differentiated
according to the diversity of acts, even as powers are differentiated by
their acts.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The division of Order is not that of an integral whole into
its parts, nor of a universal whole, but of a potential whole, the nature
of which is that the notion of the whole is found to be complete in one
part, but in the others by some participation thereof. Thus it is here:
for the entire fulness of the sacrament is in one Order, namely the
priesthood, while in the other sacraments there is a participation of
Order. And this is signified by the Lord saying (Num. 11:17): "I will
take of thy spirit and give to them, that they may bear with thee the
burden of the people." Therefore all the Orders are one sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: In a kingdom, although the entire fulness of power resides
in the king, this does not exclude the ministers having a power which is
a participation of the kingly power. It is the same in Order. In the
aristocratic form of government, on the contrary, the fulness of power
resides in no one, but in all.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether there are seven Orders?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that there are not seven Orders. For the Orders of
the Church are directed to the hierarchical acts. But there are only
three hierarchical acts, namely "to cleanse, to enlighten, and to
perfect," for which reason Dionysius distinguishes three Orders (Eccl.
Hier. v). Therefore there are not seven.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, all the sacraments derive their efficacy and
authenticity from their institution by Christ, or at least by His
apostles. But no mention except of priests and deacons is made in the
teaching of Christ and His apostles. Therefore seemingly there are no
other Orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, by the sacrament of Order a man is appointed to dispense
the other sacraments. But there are only six other sacraments. Therefore
there should be only six Orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[2] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: On the other hand, It would seem that there ought to be more. For
the higher a power is, the less is it subject to multiplication. Now the
hierarchical power is in the angels in a higher way than in us, as
Dionysius says (Eccl. Hier. i). Since then there are nine Orders in the
angelic hierarchy, there should be as many, or more, in the Church.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[2] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, the prophecy of the Psalms is the most noble of all the
prophecies. Now there is one Order, namely of readers, for reading the
other prophecies in the Church. Therefore there ought to be another Order
for reading the Psalms, especially since (Decretals, Dist. xxi, cap.
Cleros) the "psalmist" is reckoned as the second Order after the
doorkeeper.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Some show the sufficiency of the orders from their
correspondence with the gratuitous graces which are indicated 1 Cor. 12.
For they say that the "word of wisdom" belongs to the bishop, because he
is the ordainer of others, which pertains to wisdom; the "word of
knowledge" to the priest, for he ought to have the key of knowledge;
"faith" to the deacon, for he preaches the Gospel; the "working of
miracles" to the subdeacon, who sets himself to do deeds of perfection by
the vow of continency; "interpretation of speeches" to the acolyte, this
being signified by the light which he bears; the "grace of healing" to
the exorcist; "diverse kinds of tongues" to the psalmist; "prophecy" to
the reader; and the "discerning of spirits" to the doorkeeper, for he
excludes some and admits others. But this is of no account, for the
gratuitous graces are not given, as the Orders are, to one same man. For
it is written (1 Cor. 12:4): "There are distributions [Douay:
'diversities'] of graces." Moreover the episcopate [*Cf. Q[40], A[5]] and
the office of psalmist are included, which are not Orders. Wherefore
others account for the Orders by likening them to the heavenly hierarchy,
where the Orders are distinguished in reference to cleansing,
enlightening, and perfecting. Thus they say that the doorkeeper cleanses
outwardly, by separating even in the body the good from the wicked; that
the acolyte cleanses inwardly, because by the light which he bears, he
signifies that he dispels inward darkness; and that the exorcist cleanses
both ways, for he casts out the devil who disturbs a man both ways. But
enlightening, which is effected by teaching, is done by readers as
regards prophetic doctrine; by subdeacons as to apostolic doctrine; and
by deacons as to the gospel doctrine; while ordinary perfection, such as
the perfection of Penance, Baptism, and so forth is the work of the
priest; excellent perfection, such as the consecration of priests and
virgins, is the work of the bishop; while the most excellent perfection
is the work of the Sovereign Pontiff in whom resides the fulness of
authority. But this again is of no account; both because the orders of
the heavenly hierarchy are not distinguished by the aforesaid
hierarchical actions, since each of them is applicable to every Order;
and because, according to Dionysius (Eccl. Hier. v), perfecting belongs
to the bishops alone, enlightening to the priests, and cleansing to all
the ministers. Wherefore others suit the orders to the seven gifts, so
that the priesthood corresponds to the gift of wisdom, which feeds us
with the bread of life and understanding, even as the priest refreshes us
with the heavenly bread; fear to the doorkeeper, for he separates us from
the wicked; and thus the intermediate Orders to the intermediate gifts.
But this again is of no account, since the sevenfold grace is given in
each one of the Orders. Consequently we must answer differently by saying
that the sacrament of Order is directed to the sacrament of the
Eucharist, which is the sacrament of sacraments, as Dionysius says (Eccl.
Hier. iii). For just as temple, altar, vessels, and vestments need to be
consecrated, so do the ministers who are ordained for the Eucharist; and
this consecration is the sacrament of Order. Hence the distinction of
Orders is derived from their relation to the Eucharist. For the power of
Order is directed either to the consecration of the Eucharist itself, or
to some ministry in connection with this sacrament of the Eucharist. If
in the former way, then it is the Order of priests; hence when they are
ordained, they receive the chalice with wine, and the paten with the
bread, because they are receiving the power to consecrate the body and
blood of Christ. The co-operation of the ministers is directed either to
the sacrament itself, or to the recipients. If the former, this happens
in three ways. For in the first place, there is the ministry whereby the
minister co-operates with the priest in the sacrament itself, by
dispensing, but not by consecrating, for this is done by the priest
alone; and this belongs to the deacon. Hence in the text (Sent. iv, D,
24) it is said that it belongs to the deacon to minister to the priests
in whatever is done in Christ's sacraments, wherefore he dispenses
Christ's blood. Secondly, there is the ministry directed to the disposal
of the sacramental matter in the sacred vessels of the sacrament. and
this belongs to subdeacons. Wherefore it is stated in the text (Sent. iv,
D, 24) that they carry the vessels of our Lord's body and blood, and
place the oblation on the altar; hence, when they are ordained, they
receive the chalice, empty however, from the bishop's hands. Thirdly,
there is the ministry directed to the proffering of the sacramental
matter, and this belongs to the acolyte. For he, as stated in the text
(Sent. iv, D, 24), prepares the cruet with wine and water; wherefore he
receives an empty cruet. The ministry directed to the preparation of the
recipients can be exercised only over the unclean, since those who are
clean are already apt for receiving the sacraments. Now the unclean are
of three kinds, according to Dionysius (Eccl. Hier. iii). For some are
absolute unbelievers and unwilling to believe; and these must be
altogether debarred from beholding Divine things and from the assembly of
the faithful; this belongs to the doorkeepers. Some, however, are willing
to believe, but are not as yet instructed, namely catechumens, and to the
instruction of such persons the Order of readers is directed, who are
therefore entrusted with the reading of the first rudiments of the
doctrine of faith, namely the Old Testament. But some are believers and
instructed, yet lie under an impediment through the power of the devil,
namely those who are possessed: and to this ministry the order of
exorcists is directed. Thus the reason and number of the degrees of
Orders is made clear.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Dionysius is speaking of the orders not as sacraments, but
as directed to hierarchical actions. Wherefore he distinguishes three
Orders corresponding to those actions. The first of these Orders, namely
the bishop, has all three actions; the second, namely the priest, has
two; while the third has one, namely to cleanse; this is the deacon who
is called a minister: and under this last all the lower Orders are
comprised. But the Orders derive their sacramental nature from their
relation to the greatest of the sacraments, and consequently the number
of Orders depends on this.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: In the early Church, on account of the fewness of
ministers, all the lower ministries were entrusted to the deacons, as
Dionysius says (Eccl. Hier. iii), where he says: "Some of the ministers
stand at the closed door of the Church, others are otherwise occupied in
the exercise of their own order; others place the sacred bread and the
chalice of benediction on the altar and offer them to the priests."
Nevertheless all the power to do all these things was included in the one
power of the deacon, though implicitly. But afterwards the Divine worship
developed, and the Church committed expressly to several persons that
which had hitherto been committed implicitly in one Order. This is what
the Master means, when He says in the text (Sent. iv, D, 24) that the
Church instituted other Orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: The orders are directed to the sacrament of the Eucharist
chiefly, and to the other sacraments consequently, for even the other
sacraments flow from that which is contained in that sacrament. Hence it
does not follow that the orders ought to be distinguished according to
the sacraments.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[2] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: The angels differ specifically [*Cf. FP, Q[50], A[4]]: for
this reason it is possible for them to have various modes of receiving
Divine things, and hence also they are divided into various hierarchies.
But in men there is only one hierarchy, because they have only one mode
of receiving Divine things, which results from the human species, namely
through the images of sensible objects. Consequently the distinction of
orders in the angels cannot bear any relation to a sacrament as it is
with us, but only a relation to the hierarchical actions which among them
each Order exercises on the Orders below. In this respect our Orders
correspond to theirs; since in our hierarchy there are three Orders,
distinguished according to the three hierarchical actions, even as in
each angelic hierarchy.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[2] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: The office of psalmist is not an Order, but an office
annexed to an Order. For the psalmist is also styled precentor because
the psalms are recited with chant. Now precentor is not the name of a
special Order, both because it belongs to the whole choir to sing, and
because he has no special relation to the sacrament of the Eucharist.
Since, however, it is a particular office, it is sometimes reckoned among
the Orders, taking these in a broad sense.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the Order should be divided into those that are sacred and those
that are not?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the Orders ought not to be divided into those
that are sacred and those that are not. For all the Orders are
sacraments, and all the sacraments are sacred. Therefore all the Orders
are sacred.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, by the Orders of the Church a man is not appointed to
any other than Divine offices. Now all these are sacred. Therefore all
the Orders also are sacred.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[3] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, The sacred Orders are an impediment to the contracting
of marriage and annul the marriage that is already contracted. But the
four lower orders neither impede the contracting nor annul the contract.
Therefore these are not sacred Orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[3] Body Para. 1/2
I answer that, An Order is said to be sacred in two ways. First, in
itself, and thus every order is sacred, since it is a sacrament.
Secondly, by reason of the matter about which it exercises an act, and
thus an Order is called sacred, if it exercises an act about some
consecrated thing. In this sense there are only three sacred Orders,
namely the priesthood and diaconate, which exercise an act about the
consecrated body and blood of Christ, and the subdiaconate, which
exercises an act about the consecrated vessels. Wherefore continency is
enjoined them, that they who handle holy things may themselves be holy
and clean.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[3] Body Para. 2/2
This suffices for the Replies to the Objections.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the acts of the Orders are rightly assigned in the text?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the acts of the Orders are not rightly
assigned in the text (Sent. iv, D, 24). Because a person is prepared by
absolution to receive Christ's body. Now the preparation of the
recipients of a sacrament belongs to the lower Orders. Therefore
absolution from sins is unfittingly reckoned among the acts of a priest.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, man is made like to God immediately in Baptism, by
receiving the character which causes this likeness. But prayer and the
offering of oblations are acts directed immediately to God. Therefore
every baptized person can perform these acts, and not priests alone.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[4] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, different Orders have different acts. But it belongs to
the subdeacon to place the oblations on the altar, and to read the
epistle; and subdeacons carry the cross before the Pope. Therefore these
acts should not be assigned to the deacon.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[4] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, the same truth is contained in the Old and in the New
Testament. But it belongs to the readers to read the Old Testament.
Therefore it should belong to them likewise, and not to deacons, to read
the New Testament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[4] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, the apostles preached naught else but the gospel of
Christ (Rm. 1:15). But the teaching of the apostles is entrusted to
subdeacons to be read by them. Therefore the Gospel teaching should be
also.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[4] Obj. 6 Para. 1/1
OBJ 6: Further, according to Dionysius (Eccl. Hier. v) that which
belongs to a higher Order should not be applicable to a lower Order. But
it is an act of subdeacons to minister with the cruets. Therefore it
should not be assigned to acolytes.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[4] Obj. 7 Para. 1/1
OBJ 7: Further, spiritual actions should rank above bodily actions. But
the acolyte's act is merely corporeal. Therefore the exorcist has not the
spiritual act of casting out devils, since he is of inferior rank.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[4] Obj. 8 Para. 1/1
OBJ 8: Further, things that have most in common should be placed beside
one another. Now the reading of the Old Testament must needs have most in
common with the reading of the New Testament, which latter belongs to the
higher ministers. Therefore the reading of the Old Testament should be
reckoned the act, not of the reader, but rather of the acolyte;
especially since the bodily light which the acolytes carry signifies the
light of spiritual doctrine.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[4] Obj. 9 Para. 1/1
OBJ 9: Further, in every act of a special Order, there should be some
special power, which the person ordained has to the exclusion of other
persons. But in opening and shutting doors the doorkeeper has no special
power that other men have not. Therefore this should not be reckoned
their act.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[4] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Since the consecration conferred in the sacrament of
orders is directed to the sacrament of the Eucharist, as stated above
(A[2]), the principal act of each order is that whereby it is most nearly
directed to the sacrament of the Eucharist. In this respect, too, one
order ranks above another, in so far as one act is more nearly directed
to that same sacrament. But because many things are directed to the
Eucharist, as being the most exalted of the sacraments, it follows not
unfittingly that one Order has many acts besides its principal act, and
all the more, as it ranks higher, since a power extends to the more
things, the higher it is.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The preparation of the recipients of a sacrament is
twofold. One is remote and is effected by the ministers: another is
proximate, whereby they are rendered apt at once for receiving the
sacraments. This latter belongs to priests, since even in natural things
matter receives from one and the same agent both the ultimate disposition
to the form, and the form itself. And since a person acquires the
proximate disposition to the Eucharist by being cleansed from sin, it
follows that the priest is the proper minister of all those sacraments
which are chiefly instituted for the cleansing of sins, namely Baptism,
Penance, and Extreme Unction.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Acts are directed immediately to God in two ways; in one
way on the part of one person only, for instance the prayers of
individuals, vows, and so forth: such acts befit any baptized person. In
another way on the part of the whole Church, and thus the priest alone
exercises acts immediately directed to God; because to impersonate the
whole Church belongs to him alone who consecrates the Eucharist, which is
the sacrament of the universal Church.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[4] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: The offerings made by the people are offered through the
priest. Hence a twofold ministry is necessary with regard to offerings.
One on the part of the people: and this belongs to the subdeacon who
receives the offerings from the people and places them on the altar or
offers them to the deacon. the other is on the part of the priest, and
belongs to the deacon, who hands the offerings to the priest. This is the
principal act of both Orders, and for this reason the deacon's Order is
the higher. But to read the epistle does not belong to a deacon, except
as the acts of lower Orders are ascribed to the higher; and in like
manner to carry the cross. Moreover, this depends on the customs of
Churches, because in secondary acts it is not unfitting for customs to
vary.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[4] R.O. 4 Para. 1/2
Reply OBJ 4: Doctrine is a remote preparation for the reception of a
sacrament; wherefore the announcement of doctrine is entrusted to the
ministers. But the doctrine of the Old Testament is more remote than that
of the New Testament, since it contains no instruction about this
sacrament except in figures. Hence announcing of the New Testament is
entrusted to the higher ministers, and that of the Old Testament to the
lower ministers. Moreover the doctrine of the New Testament is more
perfect as delivered by our Lord Himself, than as made known by His
apostles. Wherefore the Gospel is committed to deacons and the Epistle to
subdeacons.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[4] R.O. 4 Para. 2/2
This suffices for the Reply to the Fifth Objection.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[4] R.O. 6 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 6: Acolytes exercise an act over the cruet alone, and not over
the contents of the cruet; whereas the subdeacon exercises an act over
the contents of the cruet, because he handles the water and wine to the
end that they be put into the chalice,* and again he pours the water over
the hands of the priest; and the deacon, like the subdeacon, exercises an
act over the chalice only, not over its contents, whereas the priest
exercises an act over the contents. [*The wording of St. Thomas is
sufficiently vague to refer either to the Roman rite, where the priest
pours the wine and water into the chalice, or to the Dominican rite,
where this is done by the subdeacon.] Wherefore as the subdeacon at his
ordination receives an empty chalice, while the priest receives a full
chalice, so the acolyte receives an empty cruet, but the subdeacon a full
one. Thus there is a certain connection among the Orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[4] R.O. 7 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 7: The bodily acts of the acolyte are more intimately
connected with the act of Holy orders than the act of the exorcist,
although the latter is, in a fashion, spiritual. For the acolytes
exercise a ministry over the vessels in which the sacramental matter is
contained, as regards the wine, which needs a vessel to hold it on
account of its humidity. Hence of all the minor orders the Order of
acolytes is the highest.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[4] R.O. 8 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 8: The act of the acolyte is more closely connected with the
principal acts of the higher ministers, than the acts of the other minor
Orders, as is self-evident; and again as regards the secondary acts
whereby they prepare the people by doctrine. For the acolyte by bearing a
light represents the doctrine of the New Testament in a visible manner,
while the reader by his recital represents it differently, wherefore the
acolyte is of higher rank. It is the same with the exorcist, for as the
act of the reader is compared with the secondary act of the deacon and
subdeacon, so is the act of the exorcist compared with the secondary act
of the priest, namely to bind and to loose, by which man is wholly freed
from the slavery of the devil. This, too, shows the degrees of Order to
be most orderly. since only the three higher Orders co-operate with the
priest in his principal act which is to consecrate the body of Christ,
while both the higher and lower Orders co-operate with him in his
secondary act, which is to loose and bind.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[4] R.O. 9 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 9: Some say that in receiving the Order the doorkeeper is
given a Divine power to debar others from entering the Church, even as
Christ had, when He cast out the sellers from the Temple. But this
belongs to a gratuitous grace rather than to a sacramental grace.
Wherefore we should reply that he receives the power to do this by virtue
of his office, although others may do so, but not officially. It is the
case in all the acts of the minor Orders, that they can be lawfully
exercised by others, even though these have no office to that effect:
just as Mass may be said in an unconsecrated building, although the
consecration of a church is directed to the purpose that Mass be said
there.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[5] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the character is imprinted on a priest when the chalice is handed
to him?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[5] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the character is not imprinted on the priest
at the moment when the chalice is handed to him. For the consecration of
a priest is done by anointing as in Confirmation. Now in Confirmation the
character is imprinted at the moment of anointing; and therefore in the
priesthood also and not at the handing of the chalice.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[5] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, our Lord gave His disciples the priestly power when He
said (Jn. 20:22,23): "Receive ye the Holy Ghost: whose sins you shall
forgive," etc. Now the Holy Ghost is given by the imposition of hands.
Therefore the character of order is given at the moment of the imposition
of hands.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[5] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, as the ministers are consecrated, even so are the
ministers' vestments. Now the blessing alone consecrates the vestments.
Therefore the consecration of the priest also is effected by the mere
blessing of the bishop.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[5] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, as a chalice is handed to the priest, even so is the
priestly vestment. Therefore if a character is imprinted at the giving of
the chalice, so likewise is there at the giving of the chasuble, and thus
a priest would have two characters: but this is false.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[5] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, the deacon's order is more closely allied to the
priest's Order than is the subdeacon's. But if a character is imprinted
on the priest at the moment of the handing of the chalice, the subdeacon
would be more closely allied to the priest than the deacon; because the
subdeacon receives the character at the handing of the chalice and not
the deacon. Therefore the priestly character is not imprinted at the
handing of the chalice.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[5] Obj. 6 Para. 1/1
OBJ 6: Further, the Order of acolytes approaches nearer to the priestly
act by exercising an act over the cruet than by exercising an act over
the torch. Yet the character is imprinted on the acolytes when they
receive the torch rather than when they receive the cruet, because the
name of acolyte signifies candle-bearer. Therefore the character is not
imprinted on the priest when he receives the chalice.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[5] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, The principal act of the priest's Order is to
consecrate Christ's body. Now he receives the power to this effect at the
handing of the chalice. Therefore the character is imprinted on him then.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[5] Body Para. 1/2
I answer that, As stated above (A[4], ad 1), to cause the form and to
give the matter its proximate preparation for the form belong to the same
agent. Wherefore the bishop in conferring orders does two things; for he
prepares the candidates for the reception of orders, and delivers to them
the power of order. He prepares them, both by instructing them in their
respective offices and by doing something to them, so that they may be
adapted to receive the power. This preparation consists of three things,
namely blessing, imposition of hands, and anointing. By the blessing they
are enlisted in the Divine service, wherefore the blessing is given to
all. By the imposition of hands the fulness of grace is given, whereby
they are qualified for exalted duties, wherefore only deacons and priests
receive the imposition of hands, because they are competent to dispense
the sacraments, although the latter as principal dispensers, the former
as ministers. But by the anointing they are consecrated for the purpose
of handling the sacrament, wherefore the anointing is done to the priests
alone who touch the body of Christ with their own hands; even as a
chalice is anointed because it holds the blood, and the paten because it
holds the body.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[5] Body Para. 2/2
The conferring of power is effected by giving them something pertaining
to their proper act. And since the principal act of a priest is to
consecrate the body and blood of Christ, the priestly character is
imprinted at the very giving of the chalice under the prescribed form of
words.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[5] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: In Confirmation there is not given the office of exercising
an act on an exterior matter, wherefore the character is not imprinted in
that sacrament at the handing of some particular thing, but at the mere
imposition of hands and anointing. But it is otherwise in the priestly
Order, and consequently the comparison fails.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[5] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Our Lord gave His disciples the priestly power, as regards
the principal act, before His passion at the supper when He said: "Take
ye and eat" (Mt. 26:26), wherefore He added: "Do this for a commemoration
of Me" (Lk. 22:19). After the resurrection, however, He gave them the
priestly power, as to its secondary act, which is to bind and loose.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[5] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Vestments require no other consecration except to be set
aside for the Divine worship, wherefore the blessing suffices for their
consecration. But it is different with those who are ordained, as
explained above.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[5] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: The priestly vestment signifies, not the power given to the
priest, but the aptitude required of him for exercising the act of that
power. Wherefore a character is imprinted neither on the priest nor on
anyone else at the giving of a vestment.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[5] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: The deacon's power is midway between the subdeacon's and
the priest's. For the priest exercises a power directly on Christ's body,
the subdeacon on the vessels only, and the deacon on Christ's body
contained in a vessel. Hence it is not for him to touch Christ's body,
but to carry the body on the paten, and to dispense the blood with the
chalice. Consequently his power, as to the principal act, could not be
expressed, either by the giving of the vessel only, or by the giving of
the matter; and his power is expressed as to the secondary act alone, by
his receiving the book of the Gospels, and this power is understood to
contain the other; wherefore the character is impressed at the handing of
the book.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[37] A[5] R.O. 6 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 6: The act of the acolyte whereby he serves with the cruet
ranks before his act of carrying the torch; although he takes his name
from the secondary act, because it is better known and more proper to
him. Hence the acolyte receives the character when he is given the cruet,
by virtue of the words uttered by the bishop.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[38] Out. Para. 1/1
OF THOSE WHO CONFER THIS SACRAMENT (TWO ARTICLES)
We must now consider those who confer this sacrament. Under this head
there are two points of inquiry:
(1) Whether a bishop alone can confer this sacrament?
(2) Whether a heretic or any other person cut off from the Church can
confer this sacrament?
�Aquin.: SMT XP Q[38] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether a bishop alone confers the sacrament of Order?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[38] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that not only a bishop confers the sacrament of
Order. For the imposition of hands has something to do with the
consecration. Now not only the bishop but also the assisting priests lay
hands on the priests who are being ordained. Therefore not only a bishop
confers the sacrament of Order.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[38] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, a man receives the power of Order, when that which
pertains to the act of his Order is handed to him. Now the cruet with
water, bowl* and towel, are given to the subdeacon by the archdeacon; as
also the candlestick with candle, and the empty cruet to the acolyte.
[*"Bacili." The rubric has "aquamanili." Some texts of the Summa have
"mantili" ("maniple"), but the archdeacon does not give the maniple to
the subdeacon.] Therefore not only the bishop confers the sacrament of
Order.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[38] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, that which belongs to an Order cannot be entrusted to
one who has not the Order. Now the conferring of minor Orders is
entrusted to certain persons who are not bishops, for instance to
Cardinal priests. Therefore the conferring of Orders does not belong to
the episcopal Order.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[38] A[1] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, whoever is entrusted with the principal is entrusted
with the accessory also. Now the sacrament of Order is directed to the
Eucharist, as accessory to principal. Since then a priest consecrates the
Eucharist, he can also confer Orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[38] A[1] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, there is a greater distinction between a priest and a
deacon than between bishop and bishop. But a bishop can consecrate a
bishop. Therefore a priest can ordain a deacon.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[38] A[1] OTC Para. 1/3
On the contrary, Ministers are applied by their Orders to the Divine
worship in a more noble way than the sacred vessels. But the consecration
of the vessels belongs to a bishop only. Much more therefore does the
consecration of ministers.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[38] A[1] OTC Para. 2/3
Further, the sacrament of Order ranks higher than the sacrament of
Confirmation. Now a bishop alone confirms. Much more therefore does a
bishop alone confer the sacrament of Order.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[38] A[1] OTC Para. 3/3
Further, virgins are not placed in a degree of spiritual power by their
consecration, as the ordained are. Yet a bishop alone can consecrate a
virgin. Therefore much more can he alone ordain.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[38] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, The episcopal power stands in the same relation to the
power of the lower Orders, as political science, which seeks the common
good, to the lower acts and virtues which seek some special good, as
appears from what was said above (Q[37], A[1]). Now political science, as
stated in Ethic. i, 2, lays down the law to lower sciences, namely what
science each one ought to cultivate, and how far he should pursue it and
in what way. Wherefore it belongs to a bishop to assign others to places
in all the Divine services. Hence he alone confirms, because those who
are confirmed receive the office, as it were, of confessing the faith;
again he alone blesses virgins who are images of the Church, Christ's
spouse, the care of which is entrusted chiefly to him; and he it is who
consecrates the candidates for ordination to the ministry of Orders, and,
by his consecration, appoints the vessels that they are to use; even as
secular offices in various cities are allotted by him who holds the
highest power, for instance by the king.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[38] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: As stated above (Q[37], A[5]), at the imposition of hands
there is given, not the character of the priestly Order, but grace which
makes a man fit to exercise his Order. And since those who are raised to
the priesthood need most copious grace, the priests together with the
bishop lay hands on them, but the bishop alone lays hands on deacons.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[38] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Since the archdeacon is as it were minister-in-chief, all
things pertaining to the ministry are handed by him, for instance the
candle with which the acolyte serves the deacon by carrying it before him
at the Gospel, and the cruet with which he serves the subdeacon; and in
like manner he gives the subdeacon the things with which the latter
serves the higher Orders. And yet the principal act of the subdeacon does
not consist in these things, but in his co-operation as regards the
matter of the sacrament; wherefore he receives the character through the
chalice being handed to him by the bishop. On the other hand, the acolyte
receives the character by virtue of the words of the bishop when the
aforesaid things---the cruet rather than the candlestick---are handed to
him by the archdeacon. Hence it does not follow that the archdeacon
ordains.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[38] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: The Pope, who has the fulness of episcopal power, can
entrust one who is not a bishop with things pertaining to the episcopal
dignity, provided they bear no immediate relation to the true body of
Christ. Hence by virtue of his commission a simple priest can confer the
minor Orders and confirm; but not one who is not a priest. Nor can a
priest confer the higher Orders which bear an immediate relation to
Christ's body, over the consecration of which the Pope's power is no
greater than that of a simple priest.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[38] A[1] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: Although the Eucharist is in itself the greatest of the
sacraments, it does not place a man in an office as does the sacrament of
Order. Hence the comparison fails.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[38] A[1] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: In order to bestow what one has on another, it is necessary
not only to be near him but also to have fulness of power. And since a
priest has not fulness of power in the hierarchical offices, as a bishop
has, it does not follow that he can raise others to the diaconate,
although the latter Order is near to his.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[38] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether heretics and those who are cut off from the Church can confer
Orders? [*Cf. TP, Q[64], AA[5],9]
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[38] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that heretics and those who are cut off from the
Church cannot confer Orders. For to confer Orders is a greater thing than
to loose or bind anyone. But a heretic cannot loose or bind. Neither
therefore can he ordain.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[38] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, a priest that is separated from the Church can
consecrate, because the character whence he derives this power remains in
him indelibly. But a bishop receives no character when he is raised to
the episcopate. Therefore he does not necessarily retain the episcopal
power after his separation from the Church.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[38] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, in no community can one who is expelled therefrom
dispose of the offices of the community. Now Orders are offices of the
Church. Therefore one who is outside the Church cannot confer Orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[38] A[2] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, the sacraments derive their efficacy from Christ's
passion. Now a heretic is not united to Christ's passion; neither by his
own faith, since he is an unbeliever, nor by the faith of the Church,
since he is severed from the Church. Therefore he cannot confer the
sacrament of Orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[38] A[2] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, a blessing is necessary in the conferring of Orders. But
a heretic cannot bless; in fact his blessing is turned into a curse, as
appears from the authorities quoted in the text (Sent. iv, D, 25).
Therefore he cannot ordain.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[38] A[2] OTC Para. 1/3
On the contrary, When a bishop who has fallen into heresy is reconciled
he is not reconsecrated. Therefore he did not lose the power which he had
of conferring Orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[38] A[2] OTC Para. 2/3
Further, the power to ordain is greater than the power of Orders. But
the power of Orders is not forfeited on account of heresy and the like.
Neither therefore is the power to ordain.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[38] A[2] OTC Para. 3/3
Further, as the one who baptizes exercises a merely outward ministry, so
does one who ordains, while God works inwardly. But one who is cut off
from the Church by no means loses the power to baptize. Neither therefore
does he lose the power to ordain.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[38] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, on this question four opinions are mentioned in the text
(Sent. iv, D, 25). For some said that heretics, so long as they are
tolerated by the Church, retain the power to ordain, but not after they
have been cut off from the Church; as neither do those who have been
degraded and the like. This is the first opinion. Yet this is impossible,
because, happen what may, no power that is given with a consecration can
be taken away so long as the thing itself remains, any more than the
consecration itself can be annulled, for even an altar or chrism once
consecrated remains consecrated for ever. Wherefore, since the episcopal
power is conferred by consecration, it must needs endure for ever,
however much a man may sin or be cut off from the Church. For this reason
others said that those who are cut off from the Church after having
episcopal power in the Church, retain the power to ordain and raise
others, but that those who are raised by them have not this power. This
is the fourth opinion. But this again is impossible, for if those who
were ordained in the Church retain the power they received, it is clear
that by exercising their power they consecrate validly, and therefore
they validly confer whatever power is given with that consecration, and
thus those who receive ordination or promotion from them have the same
power as they. Wherefore others said that even those who are cut off from
the Church can confer Orders and the other sacraments, provided they
observe the due form and intention, both as to the first effect, which is
the conferring of the sacrament, and as to the ultimate effect which is
the conferring of grace. This is the second opinion. But this again is
inadmissible, since by the very fact that a person communicates in the
sacraments with a heretic who is cut off from the Church, he sins, and
thus approaches the sacrament insincerely and cannot obtain grace, except
perhaps in Baptism in a case of necessity. Hence others say that they
confer the sacraments validly, but do not confer grace with them, not
that the sacraments are lacking in efficacy, but on account of the sins
of those who receive the sacraments from such persons despite the
prohibition of the Church. This is the third and the true opinion.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[38] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The effect of absolution is nothing else but the
forgiveness of sins which results from grace, and consequently a heretic
cannot absolve, as neither can he confer grace in the sacraments.
Moreover in order to give absolution it is necessary to have
jurisdiction, which one who is cut off from the Church has not.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[38] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: When a man is raised to the episcopate he receives a power
which he retains for ever. This, however, cannot be called a character,
because a man is not thereby placed in direct relation to God, but to
Christ's mystical body. Nevertheless it remains indelibly even as the
character, because it is given by consecration.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[38] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Those who are ordained by heretics, although they receive
an Order, do not receive the exercise thereof, so as to minister lawfully
in their Orders, for the very reason indicated in the Objection.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[38] A[2] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: They are united to the passion of Christ by the faith of
the Church, for although in themselves they are severed from it, they are
united to it as regards the form of the Church which they observe.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[38] A[2] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: This refers to the ultimate effect of the sacraments, as
the third opinion maintains.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] Out. Para. 1/1
OF THE IMPEDIMENTS TO THIS SACRAMENT (SIX ARTICLES)
We must next consider the impediments to this sacrament. Under this head
there are six points of inquiry:
(1) Whether the female sex is an impediment to receiving this sacrament?
(2) Whether lack of the use of reason is?
(3) Whether the state of slavery is?
(4) Whether homicide is?
(5) Whether illegitimate birth is?
(6) Whether lack of members is?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the female sex is an impediment to receiving Orders?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the female sex is no impediment to receiving
Orders. For the office of prophet is greater than the office of priest,
since a prophet stands midway between God and priests, just as the priest
does between God and people. Now the office of prophet was sometimes
granted to women, as may be gathered from 4 Kgs. 22:14. Therefore the
office of priest also may be competent to them.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, just as Order pertains to a kind of pre-eminence, so
does a position of authority as well as martyrdom and the religious
state. Now authority is entrusted to women in the New Testament, as in
the case of abbesses, and in the Old Testament, as in the case of
Debbora, who judged Israel (Judges 2). Moreover martyrdom and the
religious life are also befitting to them. Therefore the Orders of the
Church are also competent to them.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, the power of orders is founded in the soul. But sex is
not in the soul. Therefore difference in sex makes no difference to the
reception of Orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[1] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, It is said (1 Tim. 2:12): "I suffer not a woman to
teach (in the Church),* nor to use authority over the man." [*The words
in parenthesis are from 1 Cor. 14:34, "Let women keep silence in the
churches."]
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[1] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, the crown is required previous to receiving Orders, albeit not
for the validity of the sacrament. But the crown or tonsure is not
befitting to women according to 1 Cor. 11. Neither therefore is the
receiving of Orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Certain things are required in the recipient of a
sacrament as being requisite for the validity of the sacrament, and if
such things be lacking, one can receive neither the sacrament nor the
reality of the sacrament. Other things, however, are required, not for
the validity of the sacrament, but for its lawfulness, as being congruous
to the sacrament; and without these one receives the sacrament, but not
the reality of the sacrament. Accordingly we must say that the male sex
is required for receiving Orders not only in the second, but also in the
first way. Wherefore even though a woman were made the object of all that
is done in conferring Orders, she would not receive Orders, for since a
sacrament is a sign, not only the thing, but the signification of the
thing, is required in all sacramental actions; thus it was stated above
(Q[32], A[2]) that in Extreme Unction it is necessary to have a sick man,
in order to signify the need of healing. Accordingly, since it is not
possible in the female sex to signify eminence of degree, for a woman is
in the state of subjection, it follows that she cannot receive the
sacrament of Order. Some, however, have asserted that the male sex is
necessary for the lawfulness and not for the validity of the sacrament,
because even in the Decretals (cap. Mulieres dist. 32; cap. Diaconissam,
27, qu. i) mention is made of deaconesses and priestesses. But deaconess
there denotes a woman who shares in some act of a deacon, namely who
reads the homilies in the Church; and priestess [presbytera] means a
widow, for the word "presbyter" means elder.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/2
Reply OBJ 1: Prophecy is not a sacrament but a gift of God. Wherefore
there it is not the signification, but only the thing which is necessary.
And since in matters pertaining to the soul woman does not differ from
man as to the thing (for sometimes a woman is found to be better than
many men as regards the soul), it follows that she can receive the gift
of prophecy and the like, but not the sacrament of Orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 2/2
And thereby appears the Reply to the Second and Third Objections.
However, as to abbesses, it is said that they have not ordinary
authority, but delegated as it were, on account of the danger of men and
women living together. But Debbora exercised authority in temporal, not
in priestly matters, even as now woman may have temporal power.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether boys and those who lack the use of reason can receive Orders?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that boys and those who lack the use of reason
cannot receive Orders. For, as stated in the text (Sent. iv, D, 25), the
sacred canons have appointed a certain fixed age in those who receive
Orders. But this would not be if boys could receive the sacrament of
Orders. Therefore, etc.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the sacrament of Orders ranks above the sacrament of
matrimony. Now children and those who lack the use of reason cannot
contract matrimony. Neither therefore can they receive Orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, act and power are in the same subject, according to the
Philosopher (De Somn. et Vigil. i). Now the act of Orders requires the
use of reason. Therefore the power of Orders does also.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[2] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, one who is raised to Orders before the age of
discretion is sometimes allowed to exercise them without being
reordained, as appears from Extra., De Cler. per salt. prom. But this
would not be the case if he had not received Orders. Therefore a boy can
receive Orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[2] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, boys can receive other sacraments in which a character is
imprinted, namely Baptism and Confirmation. Therefore in like manner they
can receive Orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Boyhood and other defects which remove the use of reason
occasion an impediment to act. Wherefore the like are unfit to receive
all those sacraments which require an act on the part of the recipient of
the sacrament, such as Penance, Matrimony, and so forth. But since
infused powers like natural powers precede acts---although acquired
powers follow acts---and the removal of that which comes after does not
entail the removal of what comes first, it follows that children and
those who lack the use of reason can receive all the sacraments in which
an act on the part of the recipient is not required for the validity of
the sacrament, but some spiritual power is conferred from above; with
this difference, however, that in the minor orders the age of discretion
is required out of respect for the dignity of the sacrament, but not for
its lawfulness, nor for its validity. Hence some can without sin be
raised to the minor orders before the years of discretion, if there be an
urgent reason for it and hope of their proficiency. and they are validly
ordained; for although at the time they are not qualified for the offices
entrusted to them, they will become qualified by being habituated
thereto. For the higher Orders, however, the use of reason is required
both out of respect for, and for the lawfulness of the sacrament, not
only on account of the vow of continency annexed thereto, but also
because the handling of the sacraments is entrusted to them [*See Acts of
the Council of Trent: De Reform., Sess. xxii, cap. 4,11,12]. But for the
episcopate whereby a man receives power also over the mystical body, the
act of accepting the pastoral care of souls is required; wherefore the
use of reason is necessary for the validity of episcopal consecration.
Some, however, maintain that the use of reason is necessary for the
validity of the sacrament in all the Orders. but this statement is not
confirmed either by authority or by reason.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: As stated in the Article, not all that is necessary for the
lawfulness of a sacrament is required for its validity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The cause of matrimony is consent, which cannot be without
the use of reason. Whereas in the reception of Orders no act is required
on the part of the recipients since no act on their part is expressed in
their consecration. Hence there is no comparison.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Act and power are in the same subject; yet sometimes a
power, such as the free-will, precedes its act; and thus it is in the
case in point.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the state of slavery is an impediment to receiving Orders?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the state of slavery is not an impediment to
receiving Orders. For corporal subjection is not incompatible with
spiritual authority. But in a slave there is corporal subjection.
Therefore he is not hindered from receiving the spiritual authority which
is given in orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, that which is an occasion for humility should not be an
impediment to the reception of a sacrament. Now such is slavery, for the
Apostle counsels a man, if possible, rather to remain in slavery (1 Cor.
7:21). Therefore it should not hinder him from being raised to Orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, it is more disgraceful for a cleric to become a slave
than for a slave to be made a cleric. Yet a cleric may lawfully be sold
as a slave; for a bishop of Nola, Paulinus, to wit, sold himself as a
slave as related by Gregory (Dial. iii). Much more therefore can a slave
be made a cleric.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[3] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: On the contrary, It would seem that it is an impediment to the
validity of the sacrament. For a woman, on account of her subjection,
cannot receive the sacrament of Orders. But greater still is the
subjection in a slave; since woman was not given to man as his handmaid
(for which reason she was not made from his feet). Therefore neither can
a slave receive this sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[3] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, a man, from the fact that he receives an Order, is bound
to minister in that Order. But he cannot at the same time serve his
carnal master and exercise his spiritual ministry. Therefore it would
seem that he cannot receive Orders, since the master must be indemnified.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[3] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, By receiving Orders a man pledges himself to the Divine
offices. And since no man can give what is not his, a slave who has not
the disposal of himself, cannot be raised to Orders. If, however, he be
raised, he receives the Order, because freedom is not required for the
validity of the sacrament, although it is requisite for its lawfulness,
since it hinders not the power, but the act only. The same reason applies
to all who are under an obligation to others, such as those who are in
debt and like persons.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The reception of spiritual power involves also an
obligation to certain bodily actions, and consequently it is hindered by
bodily subjection.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: A man may take an occasion for humility from many other
things which do not prove a hindrance to the exercise of Orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: The blessed Paulinus did this out of the abundance of his
charity, being led by the spirit of God; as was proved by the result of
his action, since by his becoming a slave, many of his flock were freed
from slavery. Hence we must not draw a conclusion from this particular
instance, since "where the spirit of the Lord is, there is liberty" (2
Cor. 3:17).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[3] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: The sacramental signs signify by reason of their natural
likeness. Now a woman is a subject by her nature, whereas a slave is not.
Hence the comparison fails.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[3] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: If he be ordained, his master knowing and not dissenting,
by this very fact he becomes a freedman. But if his master be in
ignorance, the bishop and he who presented him are bound to pay the
master double the slave's value, if they knew him to be a slave.
Otherwise if the slave has possessions of his own, he is bound to buy his
freedom, else he would have to return to the bondage of his master,
notwithstanding the impossibility of his exercising his Order.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether a man should be debarred from receiving Orders on account of
homicide?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that a man ought not to be debarred from receiving
Orders on account of homicide. Because our Orders originated with the
office of the Levites, as stated in the previous Distinction (Sent. iv,
D, 24). But the Levites consecrated their hands by shedding the blood of
their brethren (Ex. 32:29). Therefore neither should anyone in the New
Testament be debarred from receiving Orders on account of the shedding of
blood.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, no one should be debarred from a sacrament on account of
an act of virtue. Now blood is sometimes shed for justice' sake, for
instance by a judge; and he who has the office would sin if he did not
shed it. Therefore he is not hindered on that account from receiving
Orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[4] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, punishment is not due save for a fault. Now sometimes a
person commits homicide without fault, for instance by defending himself,
or again by mishap. Therefore he ought not to incur the punishment of
irregularity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[4] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, Against this there are many canonical statutes [*Cap.
Miror; cap. Clericum; cap. De his Cler., dist. 1; cap. Continebatur, De
homic. volunt.], as also the custom of the Church.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[4] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, All the Orders bear a relation to the sacrament of the
Eucharist, which is the sacrament of the peace vouchsafed to us by the
shedding of Christ's blood. And since homicide is most opposed to peace,
and those who slay are conformed to Christ's slayers rather than to
Christ slain, to whom all the ministers of the aforesaid sacrament ought
to be conformed, it follows that it is unlawful, although not invalid,
for homicides to be raised to Orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The Old Law inflicted the punishment of blood, whereas the
New Law does not. Hence the comparison fails between the ministers of
the Old Testament and those of the New, which is a sweet yoke and a light
burden (Mt. 11:30).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Irregularity is incurred not only on account of sin, but
chiefly on account of a person being unfit to administer the sacrament of
the Eucharist. Hence the judge and all who take part with him in a cause
of blood, are irregular, because the shedding of blood is unbecoming to
the ministers of that sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[4] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: No one does a thing without being the cause thereof, and in
man this is something voluntary. Hence he who by mishap slays a man
without knowing that it is a man, is not called a homicide, nor does he
incur irregularity (unless he was occupying himself in some unlawful
manner, or failed to take sufficient care, since in this case the slaying
becomes somewhat voluntary). But this is not because he is not in fault,
since irregularity is incurred even without fault. Wherefore even he who
in a particular case slays a man in self-defense without committing a
sin, is none the less irregular [*St. Thomas is speaking according to the
canon law of his time. This is no longer the case now.].
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[5] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether those of illegitimate birth should be debarred from receiving
Orders?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[5] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that those who are of illegitimate birth should not
be debarred from receiving Orders. For the son should not bear the
iniquity of the father (Ezech. 18:20); and yet he would if this were an
impediment to his receiving Orders. Therefore, etc.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[5] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, one's own fault is a greater impediment than the fault
of another. Now unlawful intercourse does not always debar a man from
receiving Orders. Therefore neither should he be debarred by the unlawful
intercourse of his father.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[5] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, It is written (Dt. 23:2): "A mamzer, that is to say,
one born of a prostitute, shall not enter into the Church of the Lord
until the tenth generation." Much less therefore should he be ordained.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[5] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Those who are ordained are placed in a position of
dignity over others. Hence by a kind of propriety it is requisite that
they should be without reproach, not for the validity but for the
lawfulness of the sacrament, namely that they should be of good repute,
bedecked with a virtuous life, and not publicly penitent. And since a
man's good name is bedimmed by a sinful origin, therefore those also who
are born of an unlawful union are debarred from receiving orders, unless
they receive a dispensation; and this is the more difficult to obtain,
according as their origin is more discreditable.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[5] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Irregularity is not a punishment due for sin. Hence it is
clear that those who are of illegitimate birth do not bear the iniquity
of their father through being irregular.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[5] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: What a man does by his own act can be removed by repentance
and by a contrary act; not so the things which are from nature. Hence the
comparison fails between sinful act and sinful origin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[6] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether lack of members should be an impediment?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[6] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that a man ought not to be debarred from receiving
Orders on account of a lack of members. For one who is afflicted should
not receive additional affliction. Therefore a man ought not to be
deprived of the degree of Orders on account of his suffering a bodily
defect.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[6] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, integrity of discretion is more necessary for the act of
orders than integrity of body. But some can be ordained before the years
of discretion. Therefore they can also be ordained though deficient in
body.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[6] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, The like were debarred from the ministry of the Old Law
(Lev. 21:18, seqq.). Much more therefore should they be debarred in the
New Law.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[6] OTC Para. 2/2
We shall speak of bigamy in the treatise on Matrimony (Q[66]).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[6] Body Para. 1/2
I answer that, As appears from what we have said above (AA[3],4,5), a
man is disqualified from receiving Orders, either on account of an
impediment to the act, or on account of an impediment affecting his
personal comeliness. Hence he who suffers from a lack of members is
debarred from receiving Orders, if the defect be such as to cause a
notable blemish, whereby a man's comeliness is bedimmed (for instance if
his nose be cut off) or the exercise of his Order imperilled; otherwise
he is not debarred. This integrity, however, is necessary for the
lawfulness and not for the validity of the sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[39] A[6] Body Para. 2/2
This suffices for the Replies to the Objections.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] Out. Para. 1/1
OF THE THINGS ANNEXED TO THE SACRAMENT OF ORDER (SEVEN ARTICLES)
We must now consider the things that are annexed to the sacrament of
Order. Under this head there are seven points of inquiry:
(1) Whether those who are ordained ought to be shaven and tonsured in
the form of a crown?
(2) Whether the tonsure is an Order?
(3) Whether by receiving the tonsure one renounces temporal goods?
(4) Whether above the priestly Order there should be an episcopal power?
(5) Whether the episcopate is an Order?
(6) Whether in the Church there can be any power above the episcopate?
(7) Whether the vestments of the ministers are fittingly instituted by
the Church?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether those who are ordained ought to wear the tonsure?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that those who are ordained ought not to wear the
tonsure in the shape of a crown. For the Lord threatened captivity and
dispersion to those who were shaven in this way: "Of the captivity of the
bare head of the enemies" (Dt. 32:42), and: "I will scatter into every
wind them that have their hair cut round" (Jer. 49:32). Now the ministers
of Christ should not be captives, but free. Therefore shaving and tonsure
in the shape of a crown does not become them.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the truth should correspond to the figure. Now the crown
was prefigured in the Old Law by the tonsure of the Nazarenes, as stated
in the text (Sent. iv, D, 24). Therefore since the Nazarenes were not
ordained to the Divine ministry, it would seem that the ministers of the
Church should not receive the tonsure or shave the head in the form of a
crown. The same would seem to follow from the fact that lay brothers, who
are not ministers of the Church, receive a tonsure in the religious
Orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, the hair signifies superabundance, because it grows from
that which is superabundant. But the ministers of the Church should cast
off all superabundance. Therefore they should shave the head completely
and not in the shape of a crown.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[1] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, According to Gregory, "to serve God is to reign" (Super
Ps. 101:23). Now a crown is the sign of royalty. Therefore a crown is
becoming to those who are devoted to the Divine ministry.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[1] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, according to 1 Cor. 11:15, hair is given us "for a covering."
But the ministers of the altar should have the mind uncovered. Therefore
the tonsure is becoming to them.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, It is becoming for those who apply themselves to the
Divine ministry to be shaven or tonsured in the form of a crown by reason
of the shape. Because a crown is the sign of royalty; and of perfection,
since it is circular; and those who are appointed to the Divine service
acquire a royal dignity and ought to be perfect in virtue. It is also
becoming to them as it involves the hair being taken both from the higher
part of the head by shaving, lest their mind be hindered by temporal
occupations from contemplating Divine things, and from the lower part by
clipping, lest their senses be entangled in temporal things.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The Lord threatens those who did this for the worship of
demons.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The things that were done in the Old Testament represent
imperfectly the things of the New Testament. Hence things pertaining to
the ministers of the New Testament were signified not only by the offices
of the Levites, but also by all those persons who professed some degree
of perfection. Now the Nazarenes professed a certain perfection by having
their hair cut off, thus signifying their contempt of temporal things,
although they did not have it cut in the shape of a crown, but cut it off
completely, for as yet it was not the time of the royal and perfect
priesthood. In like manner lay brothers have their hair cut because they
renounce temporalities. but they do not shave the head, because they are
not occupied in the Divine ministry, so as to have to contemplate Divine
things with the mind.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Not only the renunciation of temporalities, but also the
royal dignity has to be signified by the form of a crown; wherefore the
hair should not be cut off entirely. Another reason is that this would be
unbecoming.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the tonsure is an Order?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the tonsure is an Order. For in the acts of
the Church the spiritual corresponds to the corporal. Now the tonsure is
a corporal sign employed by the Church. Therefore seemingly there is some
interior signification corresponding thereto; so that a person receives a
character when he receives the tonsure, and consequently the latter is an
Order.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, just as Confirmation and the other Orders are given by a
bishop alone, so is the tonsure. Now a character is imprinted in
Confirmation, and the other Orders. Therefore one is imprinted likewise
in receiving the tonsure. Therefore the same conclusion follows.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, Order denotes a degree of dignity. Now a cleric by the
very fact of being a cleric is placed on a degree above the people.
Therefore the tonsure by which he is made a cleric is an Order.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[2] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, No Order is given except during the celebration of
Mass. But the tonsure is given even outside the office of the Mass.
Therefore it is not an Order.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[2] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, in the conferring of every Order mention is made of some power
granted, but not in the conferring of the tonsure. Therefore it is not an
Order.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, The ministers of the Church are severed from the people
in order that they may give themselves entirely to the Divine worship.
Now in the Divine worship are certain actions that have to be exercised
by virtue of certain definite powers, and for this purpose the spiritual
power of order is given; while other actions are performed by the whole
body of ministers in common, for instance the recital of the Divine
praises. For such things it is not necessary to have the power of Order,
but only to be deputed to such an office; and this is done by the
tonsure. Consequently it is not an Order but a preamble to Orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The tonsure has some spiritual thing inwardly corresponding
to it, as signate corresponds to sign; but this is not a spiritual power.
Wherefore a character is not imprinted in the tonsure as in an Order.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Although a man does not receive a character in the tonsure,
nevertheless he is appointed to the Divine worship. Hence this
appointment should be made by the supreme minister, namely the bishop,
who moreover blesses the vestments and vessels and whatsoever else is
employed in the Divine worship.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: A man through being a cleric is in a higher state than a
layman; but as regards power he has not the higher degree that is
required for Orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether by receiving the tonsure a man renounces temporal goods?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that men renounce temporal goods by receiving the
tonsure, for when they are tonsured they say: "The Lord is the portion of
my inheritance." But as Jerome says (Ep. ad Nepot.), "the Lord disdains
to be made a portion together with these temporal things." Therefore he
renounces temporalities.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the justice of the ministers of the New Testament ought
to abound more than that of the ministers of the Old Testament (Mt.
5:20). But the ministers of the Old Testament, namely the Levites, did
not receive a portion of inheritance with their brethren (Dt. 10; Dt.
18). Therefore neither should the ministers of the New Testament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, Hugh says (De Sacram. ii) that "after a man is made a
cleric, he must from thenceforward live on the pay of the Church." But
this would not be so were he to retain his patrimony. Therefore he would
seem to renounce it by becoming a cleric.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[3] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, Jeremias was of the priestly order (Jer. 1:1). Yet he
retained possession of his inheritance (Jer. 32:8). Therefore clerics can
retain their patrimony.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[3] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, if this were not so there would seem to be no difference
between religious and the secular clergy.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[3] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Clerics by receiving the tonsure, do not renounce their
patrimony or other temporalities; since the possession of earthly things
is not contrary to the Divine worship to which clerics are appointed,
although excessive care for such things is; for as Gregory says (Moral.
x, 30), "it is not wealth but the love of wealth that is sinful."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[3] R.O. 11 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 11: The Lord disdains to be a portion as being loved equally
with other things, so that a man place his end in God and the things of
the world. He does not, however, disdain to be the portion of those who
so possess the things of the world as not to be withdrawn thereby from
the Divine worship.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: In the Old Testament the Levites had a right to their
paternal inheritance; and the reason why they did not receive a portion
with the other tribes was because they were scattered throughout all the
tribes, which would have been impossible if, like the other tribes, they
had received one fixed portion of the soil.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Clerics promoted to holy orders, if they be poor, must be
provided for by the bishop who ordained them; otherwise he is not so
bound. And they are bound to minister to the Church in the Order they
have received. The words of Hugh refer to those who have no means of
livelihood.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether above the priestly Order there ought to be an episcopal power?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that there ought not to be an episcopal power above
the priestly Order. For as stated in the text (Sent. iv, D, 24) "the
priestly Order originated from Aaron." Now in the Old Law there was no
one above Aaron. Therefore neither in the New Law ought there to be any
power above that of the priests.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, powers rank according to acts. Now no sacred act can be
greater than to consecrate the body of Christ, whereunto the priestly
power is directed. Therefore there should not be an episcopal above the
priestly power.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[4] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, the priest, in offering, represents Christ in the
Church, Who offered Himself for us to the Father. Now no one is above
Christ in the Church, since He is the Head of the Church. Therefore there
should not be an episcopal above the priestly power.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[4] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, A power is so much the higher according as it extends
to more things. Now the priestly power, according to Dionysius (Eccl.
Hier. v), extends only to cleansing and enlightening, whereas the
episcopal power extends both to this and to perfecting. Therefore the
episcopal should be above the priestly power.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[4] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, the Divine ministries should be more orderly than human
ministries. Now the order of human ministries requires that in each
office there should be one person to preside, just as a general is placed
over soldiers. Therefore there should also be appointed over priests one
who is the chief priest, and this is the bishop. Therefore the episcopal
should be above the priestly power.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[4] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, A priest has two acts: one is the principal, namely to
consecrate the body of Christ. the other is secondary, namely to prepare
God's people for the reception of this sacrament, as stated above (Q[37],
AA[2],4). As regards the first act, the priest's power does not depend on
a higher power save God's; but as to the second, it depends on a higher
and that a human power. For every power that cannot exercise its act
without certain ordinances, depends on the power that makes those
ordinances. Now a priest cannot loose and bind, except we presuppose him
to have the jurisdiction of authority, whereby those whom he absolves are
subject to him. But he can consecrate any matter determined by Christ,
nor is anything else required for the validity of the sacrament;
although, on account of a certain congruousness, the act of the bishop is
pre-required in the consecration of the altar, vestments, and so forth.
Hence it is clear that it behooves the episcopal to be above the priestly
power, as regards the priest's secondary act, but not as regards his
primary act.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Aaron was both priest and pontiff, that is chief priest.
Accordingly the priestly power originated from him, in so far as he was a
priest offering sacrifices, which was lawful even to the lesser priests;
but it does not originate from him as pontiff, by which power he was able
to do certain things; for instance, to enter once a year the Holy of
Holies, which it was unlawful for the other priests to do.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: There is no higher power with regard to this act, but with
regard to another, as stated above.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[4] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Just as the perfections of all natural things pre-exist in
God as their exemplar, so was Christ the exemplar of all ecclesiastical
offices. Wherefore each minister of the Church is, in some respect, a
copy of Christ, as stated in the text (Sent. iv, D, 24). Yet he is the
higher who represents Christ according to a greater perfection. Now a
priest represents Christ in that He fulfilled a certain ministry by
Himself, whereas a bishop represents Him in that He instituted other
ministers and founded the Church. Hence it belongs to a bishop to
dedicate a thing to the Divine offices, as establishing the Divine
worship after the manner of Christ. For this reason also a bishop is
especially called the bridegroom of the Church even as Christ is.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[5] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the episcopate is an Order?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[5] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the episcopate is an Order. First of all,
because Dionysius (Eccl. Hier. v) assigns these three orders to the
ecclesiastical hierarchy, the bishop, the priest, and the minister. In
the text also (Sent. iv, D, 24) it is stated that the episcopal Order is
fourfold.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[5] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, Order is nothing else but a degree of power in the
dispensing of spiritual things. Now bishops can dispense certain
sacraments which priests cannot dispense, namely Confirmation and Order.
Therefore the episcopate is an Order.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[5] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, in the Church there is no spiritual power other than of
Order or jurisdiction. But things pertaining to the episcopal power are
not matters of jurisdiction, else they might be committed to one who is
not a bishop, which is false. Therefore they belong to the power of
Order. Therefore the bishop has an Order which a simple priest has not;
and thus the episcopate is an Order.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[5] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, One Order does not depend on a preceding order as
regards the validity of the sacrament. But the episcopal power depends on
the priestly power, since no one can receive the episcopal power unless
he have previously the priestly power. Therefore the episcopate is not an
Order.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[5] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, the greater Orders are not conferred except on Saturdays [*The
four Ember Saturdays]. But the episcopal power is bestowed on Sundays
[*Dist. lxxv, can. Ordinationes]. Therefore it is not an Order.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[5] Body Para. 1/2
I answer that, Order may be understood in two ways. In one way as a
sacrament, and thus, as already stated (Q[37], AA[2],4), every Order is
directed to the sacrament of the Eucharist. Wherefore since the bishop
has not a higher power than the priest, in this respect the episcopate is
not an Order. In another way Order may be considered as an office in
relation to certain sacred actions: and thus since in hierarchical
actions a bishop has in relation to the mystical body a higher power than
the priest, the episcopate is an Order. It is in this sense that the
authorities quoted speak.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[5] Body Para. 2/2
Hence the Reply to the First Objection is clear.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[5] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Order considered as a sacrament which imprints a character
is specially directed to the sacrament of the Eucharist, in which Christ
Himself is contained, because by a character we are made like to Christ
Himself [*Cf. TP, Q[63], A[3]]. Hence although at his promotion a bishop
receives a spiritual power in respect of certain sacraments, this power
nevertheless has not the nature of a character. For this reason the
episcopate is not an Order, in the sense in which an Order is a sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[5] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: The episcopal power is one not only of jurisdiction but
also of Order, as stated above, taking Order in the sense in which it is
generally understood.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[6] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether in the Church there can be anyone above the bishops?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[6] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that there cannot be anyone in the Church higher
than the bishops. For all the bishops are the successors of the apostles.
Now the power so given to one of the apostles, namely Peter (Mt. 16:19),
was given to all the apostles (Jn. 20:23). Therefore all bishops are
equal, and one is not above another.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[6] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the rite of the Church ought to be more conformed to the
Jewish rite than to that of the Gentiles. Now the distinction of the
episcopal dignity and the appointment of one over another, were
introduced by the Gentiles. as stated in the text (Sent. iv, D, 24); and
there was no such thing in the Old Law. Therefore neither in the Church
should one bishop be above another.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[6] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, a higher power cannot be conferred by a lower, nor equal
by equal, because "without all contradiction that which is less is
blessed by the greater [Vulg.: 'better']"; hence a priest does not
consecrate a bishop or a priest, but a bishop consecrates a priest. But a
bishop can consecrate any bishop, since even the bishop of Ostia
consecrates the Pope. Therefore the episcopal dignity is equal in all
matters, and consequently one bishop should not be subject to another, as
stated in the text (Sent. iv, D, 24).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[6] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, We read in the council of Constantinople: "In
accordance with the Scriptures and the statutes and definitions of the
canons, we venerate the most holy bishop of ancient Rome the first and
greatest of bishops, and after him the bishop of Constantinople."
Therefore one bishop is above another.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[6] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, the blessed Cyril, bishop of Alexandria, says: "That we may
remain members of our apostolic head, the throne of the Roman Pontiffs,
of whom it is our duty to seek what we are to believe and what we are to
hold, venerating him, beseeching him above others; for his it is to
reprove, to correct, to appoint, to loose, and to bind in place of Him
Who set up that very throne, and Who gave the fulness of His own to no
other, but to him alone, to whom by divine right all bow the head, and
the primates of the world are obedient as to our Lord Jesus Christ
Himself." Therefore bishops are subject to someone even by divine right.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[6] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Wherever there are several authorities directed to one
purpose, there must needs be one universal authority over the particular
authorities, because in all virtues and acts the order is according to
the order of their ends (Ethic. i, 1,2). Now the common good is more
Godlike than the particular good. Wherefore above the governing power
which aims at a particular good there must be a universal governing power
in respect of the common good, otherwise there would be no cohesion
towards the one object. Hence since the whole Church is one body, it
behooves, if this oneness is to be preserved, that there be a governing
power in respect of the whole Church, above the episcopal power whereby
each particular Church is governed, and this is the power of the Pope.
Consequently those who deny this power are called schismatics as causing
a division in the unity of the Church. Again, between a simple bishop and
the Pope there are other degrees of rank corresponding to the degrees of
union, in respect of which one congregation or community includes
another; thus the community of a province includes the community of a
city, and the community of a kingdom includes the community of one
province, and the community of the whole world includes the community of
one kingdom.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[6] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Although the power of binding and loosing was given to all
the apostles in common, nevertheless in order to indicate some order in
this power, it was given first of all to Peter alone, to show that this
power must come down from him to the others. For this reason He said to
him in the singular: "Confirm thy brethren" (Lk. 22:32), and: "Feed My
sheep" (Jn. 21:17), i.e. according to Chrysostom: "Be thou the president
and head of thy brethren in My stead, that they, putting thee in My
place, may preach and confirm thee throughout the world whilst thou
sittest on thy throne."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[6] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The Jewish rite was not spread abroad in various kingdoms
and provinces, but was confined to one nation; hence there was no need to
distinguish various pontiffs under the one who had the chief power. But
the rite of the Church, like that of the Gentiles, is spread abroad
through various nations; and consequently in this respect it is necessary
for the constitution of the Church to be like the rite of the Gentiles
rather than that of the Jews.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[6] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: The priestly power is surpassed by the episcopal power, as
by a power of a different kind; but the episcopal is surpassed by the
papal power as by a power of the same kind. Hence a bishop can perform
every hierarchical act that the Pope can; whereas a priest cannot perform
every act that a bishop can in conferring the sacraments. Wherefore as
regards matters pertaining to the episcopal Order, all bishops are equal,
and for this reason any bishop can consecrate another bishop.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[7] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the vestments of the ministers are fittingly instituted in the
Church?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[7] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the vestments of the ministers are not
fittingly instituted in the Church. For the ministers of the New
Testament are more bound to chastity than were the ministers of the Old
Testament. Now among the vestments of the Old Testament there were the
breeches as a sign of chastity. Much more therefore should they have a
place among the vestments of the Church's ministers.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[7] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the priesthood of the New Testament is more worthy than
the priesthood of the Old. But the priests of the Old Testament had
mitres, which are a sign of dignity. Therefore the priests of the New
Testament should also have them.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[7] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, the priest is nearer than the episcopal Order to the
Orders of ministers. Now the bishop uses the vestments of the ministers,
namely the dalmatic, which is the deacon's vestment, and the tunic, which
is the subdeacon's. Much more therefore should simple priests use them.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[7] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, in the Old Law the pontiff wore the ephod
[*Superhumerale, i.e. over-the-shoulders], which signified the burden of
the Gospel, as Bede observes (De Tabernac. iii). Now this is especially
incumbent on our pontiffs. Therefore they ought to wear the ephod.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[7] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, "Doctrine and Truth" were inscribed on the "rational"
which the pontiffs of the Old Testament wore. Now truth was made known
especially in the New Law. Therefore it is becoming to the pontiffs of
the New Law.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[7] Obj. 6 Para. 1/1
OBJ 6: Further, the golden plate on which was written the most admirable
name of God, was the most admirable of the adornments of the Old Law.
Therefore it should especially have been transferred to the New Law.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[7] Obj. 7 Para. 1/1
OBJ 7: Further, the things which the ministers of the Church wear
outwardly are signs of inward power. Now the archbishop has no other kind
of power than a bishop, as stated above (A[6]). Therefore he should not
have the pallium which other bishops have not.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[7] Obj. 8 Para. 1/1
OBJ 8: Further, the fulness of power resides in the Roman Pontiff. But
he has not a crozier. Therefore other bishops should not have one.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[7] Body Para. 1/4
I answer that, The vestments of the ministers denote the qualifications
required of them for handling Divine things. And since certain things are
required of all, and some are required of the higher, that are not so
exacted of the lower ministers, therefore certain vestments are common to
all the ministers, while some pertain to the higher ministers only.
Accordingly it is becoming to all the ministers to wear the "amice" which
covers the shoulders, thereby signifying courage in the exercise of the
Divine offices to which they are deputed; and the "alb," which signifies
a pure life, and the "girdle," which signifies restraint of the flesh.
But the subdeacon wears in addition the "maniple" on the left arm; this
signifies the wiping away of the least stains, since a maniple is a kind
of handkerchief for wiping the face; for they are the first to be
admitted to the handling of sacred things. They also have the "narrow
tunic," signifying the doctrine of Christ; wherefore in the Old Law
little bells hung therefrom, and subdeacons are the first admitted to
announce the doctrine of the New Law. The deacon has in addition the
"stole" over the left shoulder, as a sign that he is deputed to a
ministry in the sacraments themselves, and the "dalmatic" (which is a
full vestment, so called because it first came into use in Dalmatia), to
signify that he is the first to be appointed to dispense the sacraments:
for he dispenses the blood, and in dispensing one should be generous.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[7] Body Para. 2/4
But in the case of the priest the "stole" hangs from both shoulders, to
show that he has received full power to dispense the sacraments, and not
as the minister of another man, for which reason the stole reaches right
down. He also wears the "chasuble," which signifies charity, because he
it is who consecrates the sacrament of charity, namely the Eucharist.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[7] Body Para. 3/4
Bishops have nine ornaments besides those which the priest has; these
are the "stockings, sandals, succinctory, tunic, dalmatic, mitre, gloves,
ring, and crozier," because there are nine things which they can, but
priests cannot, do, namely ordain clerics, bless virgins, consecrate
bishops, impose hands, dedicate churches, depose clerics, celebrate
synods, consecrate chrism, bless vestments and vessels.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[7] Body Para. 4/4
We may also say that the "stockings" signify his upright walk; the
"sandals" which cover the feet, his contempt of earthly things; the
"succinctory" which girds the stole with the alb, his love of probity;
the "tunic," perseverance, for Joseph is said (Gn. 37:23) to have had a
long tunic---"talaric," because it reached down to the ankles [talos],
which denote the end of life; the "dalmatic," generosity in works of
mercy; the "gloves," prudence in action; the "mitre," knowledge of both
Testaments, for which reason it has two crests; the "crozier," his
pastoral care, whereby he has to gather together the wayward (this is
denoted by the curve at the head of the crozier), to uphold the weak
(this is denoted by the stem of the crozier), and to spur on the laggards
(this is denoted by the point at the foot of the crozier). Hence the line:
"Gather, uphold, spur on
The wayward, the weak, and the laggard."
The "ring" signifies the sacraments of that faith whereby the Church is
espoused to Christ. For bishops are espoused to the Church in the place
of Christ. Furthermore archbishops have the "pallium" in sign of their
privileged power, for it signifies the golden chain which those who
fought rightfully were wont to receive.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[7] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The priests of the Old Law were enjoined continency only
for the time of their attendance for the purpose of their ministry.
Wherefore as a sign of the chastity which they had then to observe, they
wore the breeches while offering sacrifices. But the ministers of the New
Testament are enjoined perpetual continency; and so the comparison fails.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[7] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The mitre was not a sign of dignity, for it was a kind of
hat, as Jerome says (Ep. ad Fabiol.). But the diadem which was a sign of
dignity was given to the pontiffs alone, as the mitre is now.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[7] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: The power of the ministers resides in the bishop as their
source, but not in the priest, for he does not confer those Orders.
Wherefore the bishop, rather than the priest, wears those vestments.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[7] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: Instead of the ephod, they wear the stole, which is
intended for the same signification as the ephod.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[7] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: The pallium takes the place of the "rational."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[7] R.O. 6 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 6: Instead of that plate our pontiff wears the cross, as
Innocent III says (De Myst. Miss. i), just as the breeches are replaced
by the sandals, the linen garment by the alb, the belt by the girdle, the
long or talaric garment by the tunic, the ephod by the amice, the
"rational" by the pallium, the diadem by the mitre.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[7] R.O. 7 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 7: Although he has not another kind of power he has the same
power more fully. and so in order to designate this perfection, he
receives the pallium which surrounds him on all sides.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[40] A[7] R.O. 8 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 8: The Roman Pontiff does not use a pastoral staff because
Peter sent his to restore to life a certain disciple who afterwards
became bishop of Treves. Hence in the diocese of Treves the Pope carries
a crozier but not elsewhere; or else it is a sign of his not having a
restricted power denoted by the curve of the staff.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] Out. Para. 1/1
MATRIMONY (QQ[41]-67)
OF THE SACRAMENT OF MATRIMONY AS DIRECTED TO AN OFFICE OF NATURE (FOUR
ARTICLES)
In the next place we must consider matrimony. We must treat of it (1) as
directed to an office of nature; (2) as a sacrament; (3) as considered
absolutely and in itself. Under the first head there are four points of
inquiry:
(1) Whether it is of natural law?
(2) Whether it is a matter of precept?
(3) Whether its act is lawful?
(4) Whether its act can be meritorious?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether matrimony is of natural law?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that matrimony is not natural. Because "the natural
law is what nature has taught all animals" [*Digest. I, i, de justitia et
jure, 1]. But in other animals the sexes are united without matrimony.
Therefore matrimony is not of natural law.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: Further, that which is of natural law is found in all men with
regard to their every state. But matrimony was not in every state of man,
for as Tully says (De Inv. Rhet.), "at the beginning men were savages and
then no man knew his own children, nor was he bound by any marriage tie,"
wherein matrimony consists. Therefore it is not natural.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, natural things are the same among all. But matrimony is
not in the same way among all, since its practice varies according to
the various laws. Therefore it is not natural.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[1] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, those things without which the intention of nature can
be maintained would seem not to be natural. But nature intends the
preservation of the species by generation which is possible without
matrimony, as in the case of fornicators. Therefore matrimony is not
natural.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[1] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, At the commencement of the Digests it is stated: "The
union of male and female, which we call matrimony, is of natural law."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[1] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, the Philosopher (Ethic. viii, 12) says that "man is an animal
more inclined by nature to connubial than political society." But "man is
naturally a political and gregarious animal," as the same author asserts
(Polit. i, 2). Therefore he is naturally inclined to connubial union, and
thus the conjugal union or matrimony is natural.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, A thing is said to be natural in two ways. First, as
resulting of necessity from the principles of nature; thus upward
movement is natural to fire. In this way matrimony is not natural, nor
are any of those things that come to pass at the intervention or motion
of the free-will. Secondly, that is said to be natural to which nature
inclines although it comes to pass through the intervention of the
free-will; thus acts of virtue and the virtues themselves are called
natural; and in this way matrimony is natural, because natural reason
inclines thereto in two ways. First, in relation to the principal end of
matrimony, namely the good of the offspring. For nature intends not only
the begetting of offspring, but also its education and development until
it reach the perfect state of man as man, and that is the state of
virtue. Hence, according to the Philosopher (Ethic. viii, 11,12), we
derive three things from our parents, namely "existence," "nourishment,"
and "education." Now a child cannot be brought up and instructed unless
it have certain and definite parents, and this would not be the case
unless there were a tie between the man and a definite woman and it is in
this that matrimony consists. Secondly, in relation to the secondary end
of matrimony, which is the mutual services which married persons render
one another in household matters. For just as natural reason dictates
that men should live together, since one is not self-sufficient in all
things concerning life, for which reason man is described as being
naturally inclined to political society, so too among those works that
are necessary for human life some are becoming to men, others to women.
Wherefore nature inculcates that society of man and woman which consists
in matrimony. These two reasons are given by the Philosopher (Ethic.
viii, 11,12).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Man's nature inclines to a thing in two ways. In one way,
because that thing is becoming to the generic nature, and this is common
to all animals; in another way because it is becoming to the nature of
the difference, whereby the human species in so far as it is rational
overflows the genus; such is an act of prudence or temperance. And just
as the generic nature, though one in all animals, yet is not in all in
the same way, so neither does it incline in the same way in all, but in a
way befitting each one. Accordingly man's nature inclines to matrimony on
the part of the difference, as regards the second reason given above;
wherefore the Philosopher (Ethic. viii, 11,12; Polit. i) gives this
reason in men over other animals; but as regards the first reason it
inclines on the part of the genus; wherefore he says that the begetting
of offspring is common to all animals. Yet nature does not incline
thereto in the same way in all animals; since there are animals whose
offspring are able to seek food immediately after birth, or are
sufficiently fed by their mother; and in these there is no tie between
male and female; whereas in those whose offspring needs the support of
both parents, although for a short time, there is a certain tie, as may
be seen in certain birds. In man, however, since the child needs the
parents' care for a long time, there is a very great tie between male and
female, to which tie even the generic nature inclines.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The assertion of Tully may be true of some particular
nation, provided we understand it as referring to the proximate beginning
of that nation when it became a nation distinct from others; for that to
which natural reason inclines is not realized in all things, and this
statement is not universally true, since Holy Writ states that there has
been matrimony from the beginning of the human race.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: According to the Philosopher (Ethic. vii) "human nature is
not unchangeable as the Divine nature is." Hence things that are of
natural law vary according to the various states and conditions of men;
although those which naturally pertain to things Divine nowise vary.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[1] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: Nature intends not only being in the offspring, but also
perfect being, for which matrimony is necessary, as shown above.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether matrimony still comes under a precept?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that matrimony still comes under a precept. For a
precept is binding so long as it is not recalled. But the primary
institution of matrimony came under a precept, as stated in the text
(Sent. iv, D, 26); nor do we read anywhere that this precept was
recalled, but rather that it was confirmed (Mt. 19:6): "What . . . God
hath joined together let no man put asunder." Therefore matrimony still
comes under a precept.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the precepts of natural law are binding in respect of
all time. Now matrimony is of natural law, as stated above (A[1]).
Therefore, etc.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, the good of the species is better than the good of the
individual, "for the good of the State is more Godlike than the good of
one man" (Ethic. i, 2). Now the precept given to the first man concerning
the preservation of the good of the individual by the act of the
nutritive power is still in force. Much more therefore does the precept
concerning matrimony still hold, since it refers to the preservation of
the species.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[2] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, where the reason of an obligation remains the same, the
obligation must remain the same. Now the reason why men were bound to
marry in olden times was lest the human race should cease to multiply.
Since then the result would be the same, if each one were free to abstain
from marriage, it would seem that matrimony comes under a precept.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[2] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, It is written (1 Cor. 7:38): "He that giveth not his
virgin in marriage doth better [*Vulg.: 'He that giveth his virgin in
marriage doth well, and he that giveth her not doth better']," namely
than he that giveth her in marriage. Therefore the contract of marriage
is not now a matter of precept.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[2] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, no one deserves a reward for breaking a precept. Now a special
reward, namely the aureole, is due to virgins [*Cf. Q[96], A[5]].
Therefore matrimony does not come under a precept.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Nature inclines to a thing in two ways. In one way as to
that which is necessary for the perfection of the individual, and such an
obligation is binding on each one, since natural perfections are common
to all. In another way it inclines to that which is necessary for the
perfection of the community; and since there are many things of this
kind, one of which hinders another, such an inclination does not bind
each man by way of precept; else each man would be bound to husbandry and
building and to such offices as are necessary to the human community; but
the inclination of nature is satisfied by the accomplishment of those
various offices by various individuals. Accordingly, since the perfection
of the human community requires that some should devote themselves to the
contemplative life to which marriage is a very great obstacle, the
natural inclination to marriage is not binding by way of precept even
according to the philosophers. Hence Theophrastus proves that it is not
advisable for a wise man to marry, as Jerome relates (Contra Jovin. i).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/2
Reply OBJ 1: This precept has not been recalled, and yet it is not
binding on each individual, for the reason given above, except at that
time when the paucity of men required each one to betake himself to the
begetting of children.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 2/2
The Replies to objections 2 and 3 are clear from what has been said.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[2] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: Human nature has a general inclination to various offices
and acts, as already stated. But since it is variously in various
subjects, as individualized in this or that one, it inclines one subject
more to one of those offices, and another subject more to another,
according to the difference of temperament of various individuals. And
it is owing to this difference, as well as to Divine providence which
governs all, that one person chooses one office such as husbandry, and
another person another. And so it is too that some choose the married
life and some the contemplative. Wherefore no danger threatens.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the marriage act is always sinful?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the marriage act is always sinful. For it is
written (1 Cor. 7:29): "That they . . . who have wives, be as if they had
none." But those who are not married do not perform the marriage act.
Therefore even those who are married sin in that act.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, "Your iniquities have divided between you and your God."
Now the marriage act divides man from God wherefore the people who were
to see God (Ex. 19:11) were commanded not to go near their wives (Ex.
19:20); and Jerome says (Ep. ad Ageruch.: Contra Jovini, 18) that in the
marriage act "the Holy Ghost touches not the hearts of the prophets."
Therefore it is sinful.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, that which is shameful in itself can by no means be well
done. Now the marriage act is always connected with concupiscence, which
is always shameful. Therefore it is always sinful.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[3] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, nothing is the object of excuse save sin. Now the
marriage act needs to be excused by the marriage blessings, as the Master
says (Sent. iv, D, 26). Therefore it is a sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[3] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, things alike in species are judged alike. But marriage
intercourse is of the same species as the act of adultery, since its end
is the same, namely the human species. Therefore since the act of
adultery is a sin, the marriage act is likewise.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[3] Obj. 6 Para. 1/1
OBJ 6: Further, excess in the passions corrupts virtue. Now there is
always excess of pleasure in the marriage act, so much so that it absorbs
the reason which is man's principal good, wherefore the Philosopher says
(Ethic. vii, 11) that "in that act it is impossible to understand
anything." Therefore the marriage act is always a sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[3] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, It is written (1 Cor. 7:28): "If a virgin marry she
hath not sinned," and (1 Tim. 5:14): "I will . . . that the younger
should marry," and "bear children." But there can be no bearing of
children without carnal union. Therefore the marriage act is not a sin;
else the Apostle would not have approved of it.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[3] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, no sin is a matter of precept. But the marriage act is a matter
of precept (1 Cor. 7:3): "Let the husband render the debt to his life."
Therefore it is not a sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[3] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, If we suppose the corporeal nature to be created by the
good God we cannot hold that those things which pertain to the
preservation of the corporeal nature and to which nature inclines, are
altogether evil; wherefore, since the inclination to beget an offspring
whereby the specific nature is preserved is from nature, it is impossible
to maintain that the act of begetting children is altogether unlawful, so
that it be impossible to find the mean of virtue therein; unless we
suppose, as some are mad enough to assert, that corruptible things were
created by an evil god, whence perhaps the opinion mentioned in the text
is derived (Sent. iv, D, 26); wherefore this is a most wicked heresy.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: By these words the Apostle did not forbid the marriage act,
as neither did he forbid the possession of things when he said (1 Cor.
7:31): "They that use this world" (let them be) "as if they used it not."
In each case he forbade enjoyment [*"Fruitionem," i.e. enjoyment of a
thing sought as one's last end]; which is clear from the way in which he
expresses himself; for he did not say "let them not use it," or "let them
not have them," but let them be "as if they used it not" and "as if they
had none."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: We are united to God by the habit of grace and by the act
of contemplation and love. Therefore whatever severs the former of these
unions is always a sin, but not always that which severs the latter,
since a lawful occupation about lower things distracts the mind so that
it is not fit for actual union with God; and this is especially the case
in carnal intercourse wherein the mind is withheld by the intensity of
pleasure. For this reason those who have to contemplate Divine things or
handle sacred things are enjoined not to have to do with their wives for
that particular time; and it is in this sense that the Holy Ghost, as
regards the actual revelation of hidden things, did not touch the hearts
of the prophets at the time of the marriage act.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: The shamefulness of concupiscence that always accompanies
the marriage act is a shamefulness not of guilt, but of punishment
inflicted for the first sin, inasmuch as the lower powers and the members
do not obey reason. Hence the argument does not prove.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[3] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: Properly speaking, a thing is said to be excused when it
has some appearance of evil, and yet is not evil, or not as evil as it
seems, because some things excuse wholly, others in part. And since the
marriage act, by reason of the corruption of concupiscence, has the
appearance of an inordinate act, it is wholly excused by the marriage
blessing, so as not to be a sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[3] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: Although they are the same as to their natural species,
they differ as to their moral species, which differs in respect of one
circumstance, namely intercourse with one's wife and with another than
one's wife; just as to kill a man by assault or by justice differentiates
the moral species, although the natural species is the same; and yet the
one is lawful and the other unlawful.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[3] R.O. 6 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 6: The excess of passions that corrupts virtue not only
hinders the act of reason, but also destroys the order of reason. The
intensity of pleasure in the marriage act does not do this, since,
although for the moment man is not being directed, he was previously
directed by his reason.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the marriage act is meritorious?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the marriage act is not meritorious. For
Chrysostom [*Hom. i in the Opus Imperfectum, falsely ascribed to St. John
Chrysostom] says in his commentary on Matthew: "Although marriage brings
no punishment to those who use it, it affords them no meed." Now merit
bears a relation to meed. Therefore the marriage act is not meritorious.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, to refrain from what is meritorious deserves not praise.
Yet virginity whereby one refrains from marriage is praiseworthy.
Therefore the marriage act is not meritorious.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[4] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, he who avails himself of an indulgence granted him,
avails himself of a favor received. But a man does not merit by receiving
a favor. Therefore the marriage act is not meritorious.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[4] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, merit like virtue, consists in difficulty. But the
marriage act affords not difficulty but pleasure. Therefore it is not
meritorious.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[4] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, that which cannot be done without venial sin is never
meritorious, for a man cannot both merit and demerit at the same time.
Now there is always a venial sin in the marriage act, since even the
first movement in such like pleasures is a venial sin. Therefore the
aforesaid act cannot be meritorious.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[4] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, Every act whereby a precept is fulfilled is meritorious
if it be done from charity. Now such is the marriage act, for it is said
(1 Cor. 7:3): "Let the husband render the debt to his wife." Therefore,
etc.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[4] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, every act of virtue is meritorious. Now the aforesaid act is an
act of justice, for it is called the rendering of a debt. Therefore it is
meritorious.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[4] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Since no act proceeding from a deliberate will is
indifferent, as stated in the Second Book (Sent. ii, D, 40, Q[1], A[3];
FS, Q[18], A[9]), the marriage act is always either sinful or meritorious
in one who is in a state of grace. For if the motive for the marriage act
be a virtue, whether of justice that they may render the debt, or of
religion, that they may beget children for the worship of God, it is
meritorious. But if the motive be lust, yet not excluding the marriage
blessings, namely that he would by no means be willing to go to another
woman, it is a venial sin; while if he exclude the marriage blessings, so
as to be disposed to act in like manner with any woman, it is a mortal
sin. And nature cannot move without being either directed by reason, and
thus it will be an act of virtue, or not so directed, and then it will be
an act of lust.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The root of merit, as regards the essential reward, is
charity itself; but as regards an accidental reward, the reason for merit
consists in the difficulty of an act; and thus the marriage act is not
meritorious except in the first way.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The difficulty required for merit of the accidental reward
is a difficulty of labor, but the difficulty required for the essential
reward is the difficulty of observing the mean, and this is the
difficulty in the marriage act.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[41] A[4] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: First movements in so far as they are venial sins are
movements of the appetite to some inordinate object of pleasure. This is
not the case in the marriage act, and consequently the argument does not
prove.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] Out. Para. 1/1
OF MATRIMONY AS A SACRAMENT (FOUR ARTICLES)
We must next consider matrimony as a sacrament. Under this head there
are four points of inquiry:
(1) Whether matrimony is a sacrament?
(2) Whether it ought to have been instituted before sin was committed?
(3) Whether it confers grace?
(4) Whether carnal intercourse belongs to the integrity of matrimony?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether matrimony is a sacrament?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that matrimony is not a sacrament. For every
sacrament of the New Law has a form that is essential to the sacrament.
But the blessing given by the priest at a wedding is not essential to
matrimony. Therefore it is not a sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, a sacrament according to Hugh (De Sacram. i) is "a
material element." But matrimony has not a material element for its
matter. Therefore it is not a sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, the sacraments derive their efficacy from Christ's
Passion. But matrimony, since it has pleasure annexed to it, does not
conform man to Christ's Passion, which was painful. Therefore it is not a
sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[1] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, every sacrament of the New Law causes that which it
signifies. Yet matrimony does not cause the union of Christ with the
Church, which union it signifies. Therefore matrimony is not a sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[1] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, in the other sacraments there is something which is
reality and sacrament. But this is not to be found in matrimony, since it
does not imprint a character, else it would not be repeated. Therefore it
is not a sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[1] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, It is written (Eph. 5:32): "This is a great sacrament."
Therefore, etc.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[1] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, a sacrament is the sign of a sacred thing. But such is
Matrimony. Therefore, etc.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, A sacrament denotes a sanctifying remedy against sin
offered to man under sensible signs [*Cf. TP, Q[61], A[1]; TP, Q[65],
A[1]]. Wherefore since this is the case in matrimony, it is reckoned
among the sacraments.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The words whereby the marriage consent is expressed are the
form of this sacrament, and not the priest's blessing, which is a
sacramental.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The sacrament of Matrimony, like that of Penance, is
perfected by the act of the recipient. Wherefore just as Penance has no
other matter than the sensible acts themselves, which take the place of
the material element, so it is in Matrimony.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Although Matrimony is not conformed to Christ's Passion as
regards pain, it is as regards charity, whereby He suffered for the
Church who was to be united to Him as His spouse.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[1] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: The union of Christ with the Church is not the reality
contained in this sacrament, but is the reality signified and not
contained---and no sacrament causes a reality of that kind---but it has
another both contained and signified which it causes, as we shall state
further on (ad 5). The Master, however (Sent. iv, D, 26), asserts that it
is a non-contained reality, because he was of opinion that Matrimony has
no reality contained therein.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[1] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: In this sacrament also those three things [*Cf. TP, Q[66],
A[1]] are to be found, for the acts externally apparent are the sacrament
only; the bond between husband and wife resulting from those acts is
reality and sacrament; and the ultimate reality contained is the effect
of this sacrament, while the non-contained reality is that which the
Master assigns (Sent. iv, D, 26).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether this sacrament ought to have been instituted before sin was
committed?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that Matrimony ought not to have been instituted
before sin. Because that which is of natural law needs not to be
instituted. Now such is Matrimony, as stated above (Q[41], A[1]).
Therefore it ought not to have been instituted.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, sacraments are medicines against the disease of sin. But
a medicine is not made ready except for an actual disease. Therefore it
should not have been instituted before sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, one institution suffices for one thing. Now Matrimony
was instituted also after sin, as stated in the text (Sent. iv, D, 26).
Therefore it was not instituted before sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[2] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, the institution of a sacrament must come from God. Now
before sin, the words relating to Matrimony were not definitely said by
God but by Adam; the words which God uttered (Gn. 1:22), "Increase and
multiply," were addressed also to the brute creation where there is no
marriage. Therefore Matrimony was not instituted before sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[2] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, Matrimony is a sacrament of the New Law. But the
sacraments of the New Law took their origin from Christ. Therefore it
ought not to have been instituted before sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[2] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, It is said (Mt. 19:4): "Have ye not read that He Who
made man from the beginning 'made them male and female'"?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[2] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, Matrimony was instituted for the begetting of children. But the
begetting of children was necessary to man before sin. Therefore it
behooved Matrimony to be instituted before sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Nature inclines to marriage with a certain good in view,
which good varies according to the different states of man, wherefore it
was necessary for matrimony to be variously instituted in the various
states of man in reference to that good. Consequently matrimony as
directed to the begetting of children, which was necessary even when
there was no sin, was instituted before sin; according as it affords a
remedy for the wound of sin, it was instituted after sin at the time of
the natural law; its institution belongs to the Mosaic Law as regards
personal disqualifications; and it was instituted in the New Law in so
far as it represents the mystery of Christ's union with the Church, and
in this respect it is a sacrament of the New Law. As regards other
advantages resulting from matrimony, such as the friendship and mutual
services which husband and wife render one another, its institution
belongs to the civil law. Since, however, a sacrament is essentially a
sign and a remedy, it follows that the nature of sacrament applies to
matrimony as regards the intermediate institution; that it is fittingly
intended to fulfill an office of nature as regards the first institution;
and. as regards the last-mentioned institution, that it is directed to
fulfill an office of society.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Things which are of natural law in a general way, need to
be instituted as regards their determination which is subject to
variation according to various states; just as it is of natural law that
evil-doers be punished, but that such and such a punishment be appointed
for such and such a crime is determined by positive law.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Matrimony is not only for a remedy against sin, but is
chiefly for an office of nature; and thus it was instituted before sin,
not as intended for a remedy.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: There is no reason why matrimony should not have had
several institutions corresponding to the various things that had to be
determined in connection with marriage. Hence these various institutions
are not of the same thing in the same respect.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[2] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: Before sin matrimony was instituted by God, when He
fashioned a helpmate for man out of his rib, and said to them: "Increase
and multiply." And although this was said also to the other animals, it
was not to be fulfilled by them in the same way as by men. As to Adam's
words, he uttered them inspired by God to understand that the institution
of marriage was from God.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[2] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: As was clearly stated, matrimony was not instituted before
Christ as a sacrament of the New Law.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether matrimony confers grace?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that matrimony does not confer grace. For,
according to Hugh (De Sacram. i) "the sacraments, by virtue of their
sanctification, confer an invisible grace." But matrimony has no
sanctification essential to it. Therefore grace is not conferred therein.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, every sacrament that confers grace confers it by virtue
of its matter and form. Now the acts which are the matter in this
sacrament are not the cause of grace (for it would be the heresy of
Pelagius to assert that our acts cause grace); and the words expressive
of consent are not the cause of grace, since no sanctification results
from them. Therefore grace is by no means given in matrimony.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, the grace that is directed against the wound of sin is
necessary to all who have that wound. Now the wound of concupiscence is
to be found in all. Therefore if grace were given in matrimony against
the wound of concupiscence, all men ought to contract marriage, and it
would be very stupid to refrain from matrimony.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[3] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, sickness does not seek a remedy where it finds
aggravation. Now concupiscence is aggravated by concupiscence, because,
according to the Philosopher (Ethic. iii, 12), "the desire of
concupiscence is insatiable, and is increased by congenial actions."
Therefore it would seem that grace is not conferred in matrimony, as a
remedy for concupiscence.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[3] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, Definition and thing defined should be convertible. Now
causality of grace is included in the definition of a sacrament. Since,
then, matrimony is a sacrament, it is a cause of grace.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[3] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, Augustine says (De Bono Viduit. viii; Gen. ad lit. ix, 7) that
"matrimony affords a remedy to the sick." But it is not a remedy except
in so far as it has some efficacy. Therefore it has some efficacy for the
repression of concupiscence. Now concupiscence is not repressed except by
grace. Therefore grace is conferred therein.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[3] Body Para. 1/3
I answer that, There have been three opinions on this point. For some
[*Peter Lombard, Sent. iv, D, 2] said that matrimony is nowise the cause
of grace, but only a sign thereof. But this cannot be maintained, for in
that case it would in no respect surpass the sacraments of the Old Law.
Wherefore there would be no reason for reckoning it among the sacraments
of the New Law; since even in the Old Law by the very nature of the act
it was able to afford a remedy to concupiscence lest the latter run riot
when held in too strict restraint.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[3] Body Para. 2/3
Hence others [*St. Albert Magnus, Sent. iv, D, 26] said that grace is
conferred therein as regards the withdrawal from evil, because the act is
excused from sin, for it would be a sin apart from matrimony. But this
would be too little, since it had this also in the Old Law. And so they
say that it makes man withdraw from evil, by restraining the
concupiscence lest it tend to something outside the marriage blessings,
but that this grace does not enable a man to do good works. But this
cannot be maintained, since the same grace hinders sin and inclines to
good, just as the same heat expels cold and gives heat.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[3] Body Para. 3/3
Hence others [*St. Bonaventure, Sent. iv, D, 26] say that matrimony,
inasmuch as it is contracted in the faith of Christ, is able to confer
the grace which enables us to do those works which are required in
matrimony. and this is more probable, since wherever God gives the
faculty to do a thing, He gives also the helps whereby man is enabled to
make becoming use of that faculty; thus it is clear that to all the
soul's powers there correspond bodily members by which they can proceed
to act. Therefore, since in matrimony man receives by Divine institution
the faculty to use his wife for the begetting of children, he also
receives the grace without which he cannot becomingly do so; just as we
have said of the sacrament of orders (Q[35], A[1]). And thus this grace
which is given is the last thing contained in this sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Just as the baptismal water by virtue of its contact with
Christ's body [*Cf. TP, Q[66], A[3], ad 4] is able to "touch the body and
cleanse the heart" [*St. Augustine, Tract. lxxx in Joan.], so is
matrimony able to do so through Christ having represented it by His
Passion, and not principally through any blessing of the priest.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Just as the water of Baptism together with the form of
words results immediately not in the infusion of grace, but in the
imprinting of the character, so the outward acts and the words expressive
of consent directly effect a certain tie which is the sacrament of
matrimony; and this tie by virtue of its Divine institution works
dispositively [*Cf. Q[18], A[1], where St. Thomas uses the same
expression; and Editor's notes at the beginning of the Supplement and on
that Article] to the infusion of grace.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: This argument would hold if no more efficacious remedy
could be employed against the disease of concupiscence; but a yet more
powerful remedy is found in spiritual works and mortification of the
flesh by those who make no use of matrimony.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[3] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: A remedy can be employed against concupiscence in two ways.
First, on the part of concupiscence by repressing it in its root, and
thus matrimony affords a remedy by the grace given therein. Secondly, on
the part of its act, and this in two ways: first, by depriving the act to
which concupiscence inclines of its outward shamefulness, and this is
done by the marriage blessings which justify carnal concupiscence;
secondly, by hindering the shameful act, which is done by the very nature
of the act. because concupiscence, being satisfied by the conjugal act,
does not incline so much to other wickedness. For this reason the Apostle
says (1 Cor. 7:9): "It is better to marry than to burn." For though the
works congenial to concupiscence are in themselves of a nature to
increase concupiscence, yet in so far as they are directed according to
reason they repress concupiscence, because like acts result in like
dispositions and habits.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether carnal intercourse is an integral part of this sacrament?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that carnal intercourse is an integral part of
marriage. For at the very institution of marriage it was declared (Gn.
2:24): "They shall be two in one flesh." Now this is not brought about
save by carnal intercourse. Therefore it is an integral part of marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, that which belongs to the signification of a sacrament
is necessary for the sacrament, as we have stated above (A[2]; Q[9], A[1]
). Now carnal intercourse belongs to the signification of matrimony, as
stated in the text (Sent. iv, D, 26). Therefore it is an integral part of
the sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[4] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, this sacrament is directed to the preservation of the
species. But the species cannot be preserved without carnal intercourse.
Therefore it is an integral part of the sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[4] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, Matrimony is a sacrament inasmuch as it affords a remedy
against concupiscence; according to the Apostle's saying (1 Cor. 7:9):
"It is better to marry than to burn." But it does not afford this remedy
to those who have no carnal intercourse. Therefore the same conclusion
follows as before.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[4] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, There was matrimony in Paradise, and yet there was no
carnal intercourse. Therefore carnal intercourse is not an integral part
of matrimony.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[4] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, a sacrament by its very name denotes a sanctification. But
matrimony is holier without carnal intercourse, according to the text
(Sent. D, 26). Therefore carnal intercourse is not necessary for the
sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[4] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Integrity is twofold. One regards the primal perfection
consisting in the very essence of a thing; the other regards the
secondary perfection consisting in operation. Since then carnal
intercourse is an operation or use of marriage which gives the faculty
for that intercourse, it follows, that carnal intercourse belongs to the
latter, and not to the former integrity of marriage [*Cf. TP, Q[29], A[2]
].
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Adam expressed the integrity of marriage in regard to both
perfections, because a thing is known by its operation.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Signification of the thing contained is necessary for the
sacrament. Carnal intercourse belongs not to this signification, but to
the thing not contained, as appears from what was said above (A[1], ad
4,5).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[4] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: A thing does not reach its end except by its own act.
Wherefore, from the fact that the end of matrimony is not attained
without carnal intercourse, it follows that it belongs to the second and
not to the first integrity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[42] A[4] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: Before carnal intercourse marriage is a remedy by virtue of
the grace given therein, although not by virtue of the act, which belongs
to the second integrity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] Out. Para. 1/2
OF MATRIMONY WITH REGARD TO THE BETROTHAL (THREE ARTICLES)
In the next place we must consider matrimony absolutely; and here we
must treat (1) of the betrothal; (2) of the nature of matrimony; (3) of
its efficient cause, namely the consent; (4) of its blessings; (5) of the
impediments thereto; (6) of second marriages; (7) of certain things
annexed to marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] Out. Para. 2/2
Under the first head there are three points of inquiry:
(1) What is the betrothal?
(2) Who can contract a betrothal?
(3) Whether a betrothal can be canceled?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether a betrothal is a promise of future marriage?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that a betrothal is not rightly defined "a promise
of future marriage," as expressed in the words of Pope Nicholas I (Resp.
ad Consul. Bulgar., iii). For as Isidore says (Etym. iv), "a man is
betrothed not by a mere promise, but by giving his troth [spondet] and
providing sureties [sponsores]". Now a person is said to be betrothed by
reason of his betrothal. Therefore it is wrongly described as a promise.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, whoever promises a thing must be compelled to fulfill
his promise. But those who have contracted a betrothal are not compelled
by the Church to fulfill the marriage. Therefore a betrothal is not a
promise.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, sometimes a betrothal does not consist of a mere
promise, but an oath is added, as also certain pledges. Therefore
seemingly it should not be defined as a mere promise.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[1] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, marriage should be free and absolute. But a betrothal is
sometimes expressed under a condition even of money to be received.
Therefore it is not fittingly described as a promise of marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[1] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, promising about the future is blamed in James 4:13,
seqq. But there should be nothing blameworthy about the sacraments.
Therefore one ought not to make a promise of future marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[1] Obj. 6 Para. 1/1
OBJ 6: Further, no man is called a spouse except on account of his
espousals. But a man is said to be a spouse on account of actual
marriage, according to the text (Sent. iv, D, 27). Therefore espousals
are not always a promise of future marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Consent to conjugal union if expressed in words of the
future does not make a marriage, but a promise of marriage; and this
promise is called "a betrothal from plighting one's troth," as Isidore
says (Etym. iv). For before the use of writing-tablets, they used to give
pledges of marriage, by which they plighted their mutual consent under
the marriage code, and they provided guarantors. This promise is made in
two ways, namely absolutely, or conditionally. Absolutely, in four ways:
firstly, a mere promise, by saying: "I will take thee for my wife," and
conversely; secondly, by giving betrothal pledges, such as money and the
like; thirdly, by giving an engagement ring; fourthly, by the addition of
an oath. If, however, this promise be made conditionally, we must draw a
distinction; for it is either an honorable condition, for instance if we
say: "I will take thee, if thy parents consent," and then the promise
holds if the condition is fulfilled, and does not hold if the condition
is not fulfilled; or else the condition is dishonorable, and this in two
ways: for either it is contrary to the marriage blessings, as if we were
to say: "I will take thee if thou promise means of sterility," and then
no betrothal is contracted; or else it is not contrary to the marriage
blessings, as were one to say: "I will take thee if thou consent to my
thefts," and then the promise holds, but the condition should be removed.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The betrothal itself and giving of sureties are a
ratification of the promise, wherefore it is denominated from these as
from that which is more perfect.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: By this promise one party is bound to the other in respect
of contracting marriage; and he who fulfills not his promise sins
mortally, unless a lawful impediment arise; and the Church uses
compulsion in the sense that she enjoins a penance for the sin. But he is
not compelled by sentence of the court, because compulsory marriages are
wont to have evil results; unless the parties be bound by oath, for then
he ought to be compelled, in the opinion of some, although others think
differently on account of the reason given above, especially if there be
fear of one taking the other's life.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Such things are added only in confirmation of the promise,
and consequently they are not distinct from it.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[1] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: The condition that is appended does not destroy the liberty
of marriage; for if it be unlawful, it should be renounced; and if it be
lawful, it is either about things that are good simply, as were one to
say, "I will take thee, if thy parents consent," and such a condition
does not destroy the liberty of the betrothal, but gives it an increase
of rectitude. or else it is about things that are useful, as were one to
say: "I will marry thee if thou pay me a hundred pounds," and then this
condition is appended, not as asking a price for the consent of marriage,
but as referring to the promise of a dowry; so that the marriage does not
lose its liberty. Sometimes, however, the condition appended is the
payment of a sum of money by way of penalty, and then, since marriage
should be free, such a condition does not hold, nor can such a penalty be
exacted from a person who is unwilling to fulfill the promise of marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[1] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: James does not intend to forbid altogether the making of
promises about the future, but the making of promises as though one were
certain of one's life; hence he teaches that we ought to add the
condition. "If the Lord will," which, though it be not expressed in
words, ought nevertheless to be impressed on the heart.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[1] R.O. 6 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 6: In marriage we may consider both the marriage union and the
marriage act; and on account of his promise of the first as future a man
is called a "spouse" from his having contracted his espousals by words
expressive of the future; but from the promise of the second a man is
called a "spouse," even when the marriage has been contracted by words
expressive of the present, because by this very fact he promises
[spondet] the marriage act. However, properly speaking, espousals are so
called from the promise [sponsione] in the first sense, because espousals
are a kind of sacramental annexed to matrimony, as exorcism to baptism.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether seven years is fittingly assigned as the age for betrothal?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that seven years is not fittingly assigned as the
age for betrothal. For a contract that can be formed by others does not
require discretion in those whom it concerns. Now a betrothal can be
arranged by the parents without the knowledge of either of the persons
betrothed. Therefore a betrothal can be arranged before the age of seven
years as well as after.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, just as some use of reason is necessary for the contract
of betrothal, so is there for the consent to mortal sin. Now, as Gregory
says (Dial. iv), a boy of five years of age was carried off by the devil
on account of the sin of blasphemy. Therefore a betrothal can take place
before the age of seven years.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, a betrothal is directed to marriage. But for marriage
the same age is not assigned to boy and girl.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[2] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, one can become betrothed as soon as future marriage can
be agreeable to one. Now signs of this agreeableness are often apparent
in boys before the age of seven. Therefore they can become betrothed
before that age.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[2] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, if persons become betrothed before they are seven years
old, and subsequently after the age of seven and before the age of
maturity renew their promise in words expressive of the present, they are
reckoned to be betrothed. Now this is not by virtue of the second
contract, since they intend to contract not betrothal but marriage.
Therefore it is by the virtue of the first; and thus espousals can be
contracted before the age of seven.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[2] Obj. 6 Para. 1/1
OBJ 6: Further, when a thing is done by many persons in common, if one
fails he is supplied by another, as in the case of those who row a boat.
Now the contract of betrothal is an action common to the contracting
parties. Therefore if one be of mature age, he can contract a betrothal
with a girl who is not seven years old, since the lack of age in one is
more than counterbalanced in the other.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[2] Obj. 7 Para. 1/1
OBJ 7: Further, those who at about the age of puberty, but before it,
enter into the marriage contract by words expressive of the present are
reputed to be married. Therefore in like manner if they contract marriage
by words expressive of the future, before yet close on the age of
puberty, they are to be reputed as betrothed.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, The age of seven years is fixed reasonably enough by law
for the contracting of betrothals, for since a betrothal is a promise of
the future, as already stated (A[1]), it follows that they are within the
competency of those who can make a promise in some way, and this is only
for those who can have some foresight of the future, and this requires
the use of reason, of which three degrees are to be observed, according
to the Philosopher (Ethic. i, 4). The first is when a person neither
understands by himself nor is able to learn from another; the second
stage is when a man can learn from another but is incapable by himself of
consideration and understanding; the third degree is when a man is both
able to learn from another and to consider by himself. And since reason
develops in man by little and little, in proportion as the movement and
fluctuation of the humors is calmed, man reaches the first stage of
reason before his seventh year; and consequently during that period he is
unfit for any contract, and therefore for betrothal. But he begins to
reach the second stage at the end of his first seven years, wherefore
children at that age are sent to school. But man begins to reach the
third stage at the end of his second seven years, as regards things
concerning his person, when his natural reason develops; but as regards
things outside his person, at the end of his third seven years. Hence
before his first seven years a man is not fit to make any contract, but
at the end of that period he begins to be fit to make certain promises
for the future, especially about those things to which natural reason
inclines us more, though he is not fit to bind himself by a perpetual
obligation, because as yet he has not a firm will. Hence at that age
betrothals can be contracted. But at the end of the second seven years he
can already bind himself in matters concerning his person, either to
religion or to wedlock. And after the third seven years he can bind
himself in other matters also; and according to the laws he is given the
power of disposing of his property after his twenty-second year.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: If the parties are betrothed by another person before they
reach the age of puberty, either of them or both can demur; wherefore in
that case the betrothal does not take effect, so that neither does any
affinity result therefrom. Hence a betrothal made between certain persons
by some other takes effect, in so far as those between whom the betrothal
is arranged do not demur when they reach the proper age, whence they are
understood to consent to what others have done.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Some say that the boy of whom Gregory tells this story was
not lost, and that he did not sin mortally; and that this vision was for
the purpose of making the father sorrowful, for he had sinned in the boy
through failing to correct him. But this is contrary to the express
intention of Gregory, who says (Dial. iv) that "the boy's father having
neglected the soul of his little son, fostered no little sinner for the
flames of hell." Consequently it must be said that for a mortal sin it is
sufficient to give consent to something present, whereas in a betrothal
the consent is to something future; and greater discretion of reason is
required for looking to the future than for consenting to one present
act. Wherefore a man can sin mortally before he can bind himself to a
future obligation.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Regarding the age for the marriage contract a disposition
is required not only on the part of the use of reason, but also on the
part of the body, in that it is necessary to be of an age adapted to
procreation. And since a girl becomes apt for the act of procreation in
her twelfth year, and a boy at the end of his second seven years, as the
Philosopher says (De Hist. Anim. vii), whereas the age is the same in
both for attaining the use of reason which is the sole condition for
betrothal, hence it is that the one age is assigned for both as regards
betrothal, but not as regards marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[2] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: This agreeableness in regard to boys under the age of seven
does not result from the perfect use of reason, since they are not as yet
possessed of complete self-control; it results rather from the movement
of nature than from any process of reason. Consequently, this
agreeableness does not suffice for contracting a betrothal.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[2] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: In this case, although the second contract does not amount
to marriage, nevertheless the parties show that they ratify their former
promise; wherefore the first contract is confirmed by the second.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[2] R.O. 6 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 6: Those who row a boat act by way of one cause, and
consequently what is lacking in one can be supplied by another. But those
who make a contract of betrothal act as distinct persons, since a
betrothal can only be between two parties; wherefore it is necessary for
each to be qualified to contract, and thus the defect of one is an
obstacle to their betrothal, nor can it be supplied by the other.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[2] R.O. 7 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 7: It is true that in the matter of betrothal if the
contracting parties are close upon the age of seven, the contract of
betrothal is valid, since, according to the Philosopher (Phys. ii, 56),
"when little is lacking it seems as though nothing were lacking." Some
fix the margin at six months. but it is better to determine it according
to the condition of the contracting parties, since the use of reason
comes sooner to some than to others.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether a betrothal can be dissolved?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that a betrothal cannot be dissolved if one of the
parties enter religion. For if I have promised a thing to someone I
cannot lawfully pledge it to someone else. Now he who betroths himself
promises his body to the woman. Therefore he cannot make a further
offering of himself to God in religion.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Again, seemingly it should not be dissolved when one of the
parties leaves for a distant country, because in doubtful matters one
should always choose the safer course. Now the safer course would be to
wait for him. Therefore she is bound to wait for him.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Again, neither seemingly is it dissolved by sickness contracted
after betrothal, for no man should be punished for being under a penalty.
Now the man who contracts an infirmity would be punished if he were to
lose his right to the woman betrothed to him. Therefore a betrothal
should not be dissolved on account of a bodily infirmity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[3] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Again, neither seemingly should a betrothal be dissolved on
account of a supervening affinity, for instance if the spouse were to
commit fornication with a kinswoman of his betrothed; for in that case
the affianced bride would be penalized for the sin of her affianced
spouse, which is unreasonable.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[3] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Again, seemingly they cannot set one another free; for it would
be a proof of greatest fickleness if they contracted together and then
set one another free; and such conduct ought not to be tolerated by the
Church. Therefore, etc.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[3] Obj. 6 Para. 1/1
OBJ 6: Again, neither seemingly ought a betrothal to be dissolved on
account of the fornication of one of the parties. For a betrothal does
not yet give the one power over the body of the other; wherefore it would
seem that they nowise sin against one another if meanwhile they commit
fornication. Consequently a betrothal should not be dissolved on that
account.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[3] Obj. 7 Para. 1/1
OBJ 7: Again, neither seemingly on account of his contracting with
another woman by words expressive of the present. For a subsequent sale
does not void a previous sale. Therefore neither should a second contract
void a previous one.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[3] Obj. 8 Para. 1/1
OBJ 8: Again, neither seemingly should it be dissolved on account of
deficient age; since what is not cannot be dissolved. Now a betrothal is
null before the requisite age. Therefore it cannot be dissolved.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[3] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, In all the cases mentioned above the betrothal that has
been contracted is dissolved, but in different ways. For in two of
them---namely when a party enters religion, and when either of the
affianced spouses contracts with another party by words expressive of the
present---the betrothal is dissolved by law, whereas in the other cases
it has to be dissolved according to the judgment of the Church.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The like promise is dissolved by spiritual death, for that
promise is purely spiritual, as we shall state further on (Q[61], A[2]).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: This doubt is solved by either party not putting in an
appearance at the time fixed for completing the marriage. Wherefore if it
was no fault of that party that the marriage was not completed, he or she
can lawfully marry without any sin. But if he or she was responsible for
the non-completion of the marriage, this responsibility involves the
obligation of doing penance for the broken promise---or oath if the
promise was confirmed by oath---and he or she can contract with another
if they wish it, subject to the judgment of the Church.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: If either of the betrothed parties incur an infirmity which
notably weakens the subject (as epilepsy or paralysis), or causes a
deformity (as loss of the nose or eyes, and the like), or is contrary to
the good of the offspring (as leprosy, which is wont to be transmitted to
the children), the betrothal can be dissolved, lest the betrothed be
displeasing to one another, and the marriage thus contracted have an evil
result. Nor is one punished for being under a penalty, although one
incurs a loss from one's penalty, and this is not unreasonable.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[3] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: If the affianced bridegroom has carnal knowledge of a
kinswoman of his spouse, or "vice versa," the betrothal must be
dissolved; and for proof it is sufficient that the fact be the common
talk, in order to avoid scandal; for causes whose effects mature in the
future are voided of their effects, not only by what actually is, but
also by what happens subsequently. Hence just as affinity, had it existed
at the time of the betrothal, would have prevented that contract, so, if
it supervene before marriage, which is an effect of the betrothal, the
previous contract is voided of its effect. Nor does the other party
suffer in consequence, indeed he or she gains, being set free from one
who has become hateful to God by committing fornication.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[3] R.O. 5 Para. 1/2
Reply OBJ 5: Some do not admit this case. Yet they have against them the
Decretal (cap. Praeterea, De spons. et matr.) which says expressly: "Just
as those who enter into a contract of fellowship by pledging their faith
to one another and afterwards give it back, so it may be patiently
tolerated that those who are betrothed to one another should set one
another free." Yet to this they say that the Church allows this lest
worse happen rather than because it is according to strict law. But this
does not seem to agree with the example quoted by the Decretal.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[3] R.O. 5 Para. 2/2
Accordingly we must reply that it is not always a proof of fickleness to
rescind an agreement, since "our counsels are uncertain" (Wis. 9:14).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[3] R.O. 6 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 6: Although when they become betrothed they have not yet given
one another power over one another's body, yet if this [*Referring to the
contention of the Objection] were to happen it would make them suspicious
of one another's fidelity; and so one can ensure himself against the
other by breaking off the engagement.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[3] R.O. 7 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 7: This argument would hold if each contract were of the same
kind; whereas the second contract of marriage has greater force than the
first, and consequently dissolves it.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[43] A[3] R.O. 8 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 8: Although it was not a true betrothal, there was a betrothal
of a kind; and consequently, lest approval should seem to be given when
they come to the lawful age, they should seek a dissolution of the
betrothal by the judgment of the Church, for the sake of a good example.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[44] Out. Para. 1/1
OF THE DEFINITION OF MATRIMONY (THREE ARTICLES)
We must now consider the nature of matrimony. Under this head there are
three points of inquiry:
(1) Whether matrimony is a kind of joining?
(2) Whether it is fittingly named?
(3) Whether it is fittingly defined?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[44] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether matrimony is a kind of joining?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[44] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that matrimony is not a kind of joining. Because
the bond whereby things are tied together differs from their joining, as
cause from effect. Now matrimony is the bond whereby those who are joined
in matrimony are tied together. Therefore it is not a kind of joining.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[44] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, every sacrament is a sensible sign. But no relation is a
sensible accident. Therefore since matrimony is a sacrament, it is not a
kind of relation, and consequently neither is it a kind of joining.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[44] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, a joining is a relation of equiparance as well as of
equality. Now according to Avicenna the relation of equality is not
identically the same in each extreme. Neither therefore is there an
identically same joining; and consequently if matrimony is a kind of
joining, there is not only one matrimony between man and wife.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[44] A[1] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, It is by relation that things are related to one
another. Now by matrimony certain things are related to one another; for
the husband is the wife's husband, and the wife is the husband's wife.
Therefore matrimony is a kind of relation, nor is it other than a joining.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[44] A[1] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, the union of two things into one can result only from their
being joined. Now such is the effect of matrimony (Gn. 2:24): "They shall
be two in one flesh." Therefore matrimony is a kind of joining.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[44] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, A joining denotes a kind of uniting, and so wherever
things are united there must be a joining. Now things directed to one
purpose are said to be united in their direction thereto, thus many men
are united in following one military calling or in pursuing one business,
in relation to which they are called fellow-soldiers or business
partners. Hence, since by marriage certain persons are directed to one
begetting and upbringing of children, and again to one family life, it is
clear that in matrimony there is a joining in respect of which we speak
of husband and wife; and this joining, through being directed to some one
thing, is matrimony; while the joining together of bodies and minds is a
result of matrimony.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[44] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Matrimony is the bond by which they are tied formally, not
effectively, and so it need not be distinct from the joining.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[44] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Although relation is not itself a sensible accident, its
causes may be sensible. Nor is it necessary in a sacrament for that which
is both reality and sacrament [*Cf. TP, Q[66], A[1]] to be sensible (for
such is the relation of the aforesaid joining to this sacrament), whereas
the words expressive of consent, which are sacrament only and are the
cause of that same joining, are sensible.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[44] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: A relation is founded on something as its cause---for
instance likeness is founded on quality---and on something as its
subject---for instance in the things themselves that are like; and on
either hand we may find unity and diversity of relation. Since then it is
not the same identical quality that conduces to likeness, but the same
specific quality in each of the like subjects, and since, moreover, the
subjects of likeness are two in number, and the same applies to equality,
it follows that both equality and likeness are in every way numerically
distinct in either of the like or equal subjects. But the relations of
matrimony, on the one hand, have unity in both extremes, namely on the
part of the cause, since it is directed to the one identical begetting;
whereas on the part of the subject there is numerical diversity. The fact
of this relation having a diversity of subjects is signified by the terms
"husband" and "wife," while its unity is denoted by its being called
matrimony.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[44] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether matrimony is fittingly named?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[44] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that matrimony is unfittingly named. Because a
thing should be named after that which ranks higher. But the father ranks
above the mother. Therefore the union of father and mother should rather
be named after the father.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[44] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, a thing should be named from that which is essential to
it, since a "definition expresses the nature signified by a name"
(Metaph. iv, 28). Now nuptials are not essential to matrimony. Therefore
matrimony should not be called nuptials.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[44] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, a species cannot take its proper name from that which
belongs to the genus. Now a joining [conjunctio] is the genus of
matrimony. Therefore it should not be called a conjugal union.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[44] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, stands the common use of speech.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[44] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Three things may be considered in matrimony. First, its
essence, which is a joining together, and in reference to this it is
called the "conjugal union"; secondly, its cause, which is the wedding,
and in reference to this it is called the "nuptial union" from "nubo"
[*The original meaning of 'nubo' is 'to veil'], because at the wedding
ceremony, whereby the marriage is completed, the heads of those who are
wedded are covered with a veil [*This is still done in some countries];
thirdly, the effect, which is the offspring, and in reference to this it
is called "matrimony," as Augustine says (Contra Faust. xix, 26),
because "a woman's sole purpose in marrying should be motherhood."
Matrimony may also be resolved into "matris munium" [*i.e. munus], i.e. a
mother's duty, since the duty of bringing up the children chiefly
devolves on the women; or into "matrem muniens," because it provides the
mother with a protector and support in the person of her husband; or into
"matrem monens," as admonishing her not to leave her husband and take up
with another man; or into "materia unius," because it is a joining
together for the purpose of providing the matter of one offspring as
though it were derived from {monos} and "materia"; or into "matre" and
"nato," as Isidore says (Etym. ix), because it makes a woman the mother
of a child.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[44] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Although the father ranks above the mother, the mother has
more to do with the offspring than the father has. or we may say that
woman was made chiefly in order to be man's helpmate in relation to the
offspring, whereas the man was not made for this purpose. Wherefore the
mother has a closer relation to the nature of marriage than the father
has.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[44] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Sometimes essentials are known by accidentals, wherefore
some things can be named even after their accidentals, since a name is
given to a thing for the purpose that it may become known.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[44] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Sometimes a species is named after something pertaining to
the genus on account of an imperfection in the species, when namely it
has the generic nature completely, yet adds nothing pertaining to
dignity; thus the accidental property retains the name of property, which
is common to it and to the definition. Sometimes, however, it is on
account of a perfection, when we find the generic nature completely in
one species and not in another; thus animal is named from soul [anima],
and this belongs to an animate body, which is the genus of animal; yet
animation is not found perfectly in those animate beings that are not
animals. It is thus with the case in point. for the joining of husband
and wife by matrimony is the greatest of all joinings, since it is a
joining of soul and body, wherefore it is called a "conjugal" union.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[44] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether matrimony is fittingly defined in the text?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[44] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that matrimony is unfittingly defined in the text*
(Sent. iv, D, 27). [*The definition alluded to is as follows: "Marriage
is the marital union of man and woman involving living together in
undivided partnership."] For it is necessary to mention matrimony in
defining a husband, since it is the husband who is joined to the woman in
matrimony. Now "marital union" is put in the definition of matrimony.
Therefore in these definitions there would seem to be a vicious circle.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[44] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, matrimony makes the woman the man's wife no less than it
makes the man the woman's husband. Therefore it should not be described
as a "marital union" rather than an uxorial union.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[44] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, habit [consuetudo] pertains to morals. Yet it often
happens that married persons differ very much in habit. Therefore the
words "involving their living together [consuetudinem] in undivided
partnership" should have no place in the definition of matrimony.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[44] A[3] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, we find other definitions given of matrimony, for
according to Hugh (Sum. Sent. vii, 6), "matrimony is the lawful consent
of two apt persons to be joined together." Also, according to some,
"matrimony is the fellowship of a common life and a community regulated
by Divine and human law"; and we ask how these definitions differ.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[44] A[3] Body Para. 1/2
I answer that, As stated above (A[2]), three things are to be considered
in matrimony, namely its cause, its essence, and its effect; and
accordingly we find three definitions given of matrimony. For the
definition of Hugh indicates the cause, namely the consent, and this
definition is self-evident. The definition given in the text indicates
the essence of matrimony, namely the "union," and adds determinate
subjects by the words "between lawful persons." It also points to the
difference of the contracting parties in reference to the species, by the
word "marital," for since matrimony is a joining together for the purpose
of some one thing, this joining together is specified by the purpose to
which it is directed, and this is what pertains to the husband [maritum].
It also indicates the force of this joining---for it is indissoluble---by
the words "involving," etc.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[44] A[3] Body Para. 2/2
The remaining definition indicates the effect to which matrimony is
directed, namely the common life in family matters. And since every
community is regulated by some law, the code according to which this
community is directed, namely Divine and human law, finds a place in this
definition. while other communities, such as those of traders or
soldiers, are established by human law alone.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[44] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Sometimes the prior things from which a definition ought to
be given are not known to us, and consequently certain things are defined
from things that are posterior simply, but prior to us; thus in the
definition of quality the Philosopher employs the word "such" [quale]
when he says (Cap. De Qualitate) that "quality is that whereby we are
said to be such." Thus, too, in defining matrimony we say that it is a
"marital union," by which we mean that matrimony is a union for the
purpose of those things required by the marital office, all of which
could not be expressed in one word.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[44] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: As stated (A[2]), this difference indicates the end of the
union. And since, according to the Apostle (1 Cor. 11:9), the "man is not
[Vulg.: 'was not created'] for the woman, but the woman for the man," it
follows that this difference should be indicated in reference to the man
rather than the woman.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[44] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/2
Reply OBJ 3: Just as the civic life denotes not the individual act of
this or that one, but the things that concern the common action of the
citizens, so the conjugal life is nothing else than a particular kind of
companionship pertaining to that common action. wherefore as regards this
same life the partnership of married persons is always indivisible,
although it is divisible as regards the act belonging to each party.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[44] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 2/2
The Reply to the Fourth Objection is clear from what has been said above.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] Out. Para. 1/2
OF THE MARRIAGE CONSENT CONSIDERED IN ITSELF (FIVE ARTICLES)
In the next place we have to consider the consent; and the first point
to discuss is the consent considered in itself; the second is the consent
confirmed by oath or by carnal intercourse; the third is compulsory
consent and conditional consent; and the fourth is the object of the
consent.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] Out. Para. 2/2
Under the first head there are five points of inquiry:
(1) Whether the consent is the efficient cause of matrimony?
(2) Whether the consent needs to be expressed in words?
(3) Whether consent given in words expressive of the future makes a
marriage?
(4) Whether consent given in words expressive of the present, without
inward consent, makes a true marriage outwardly?
(5) Whether consent given secretly in words expressive of the present
makes a marriage?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether consent is the efficient cause of matrimony?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that consent is not the efficient cause of
matrimony. For the sacraments depend not on the human will but on the
Divine institution, as shown above (Sent. iv, D, 2; TP, Q[64], A[2]). But
consent belongs to the human will. Therefore it is no more the cause of
matrimony than of the other sacraments.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, nothing is its own cause. But seemingly matrimony is
nothing else than the consent, since it is the consent which signifies
the union of Christ with the Church.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, of one thing there should be one cause. Now there is one
marriage between two persons, as stated above (Q[44], A[1]); whereas the
consents of the two parties are distinct, for they are given by different
persons and to different things, since on the one hand there is consent
to take a husband, and on the other hand consent to take a wife.
Therefore mutual consent is not the cause of matrimony.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[1] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, Chrysostom [*Hom. xxxii in the Opus Imperfectum,
falsely ascribed to St. John Chrysostom] says: "It is not coition but
consent that makes a marriage."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[1] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, one person does not receive power over that which is at the
free disposal of another, without the latter's consent. Now by marriage
each of the married parties receives power over the other's body (1 Cor.
7:4), whereas hitherto each had free power over his own body. Therefore
consent makes a marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, In every sacrament there is a spiritual operation by
means of a material operation which signifies it; thus in Baptism the
inward spiritual cleansing is effected by a bodily cleansing. Wherefore,
since in matrimony there is a kind of spiritual joining together, in so
far as matrimony is a sacrament, and a certain material joining together,
in so far as it is directed to an office of nature and of civil life, it
follows that the spiritual joining is the effect of the Divine power by
means of the material joining. Therefore seeing that the joinings of
material contracts are effected by mutual consent, it follows that the
joining together of marriage is effected in the same way.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The first cause of the sacraments is the Divine power which
works in them the welfare of the soul; but the second or instrumental
causes are material operations deriving their efficacy from the Divine
institution, and thus consent is the cause in matrimony.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Matrimony is not the consent itself, but the union of
persons directed to one purpose, as stated above (Q[44], A[1]), and this
union is the effect of the consent. Moreover, the consent, properly
speaking, signifies not the union of Christ with the Church, but His will
whereby His union with the Church was brought about.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Just as marriage is one on the part of the object to which
the union is directed, whereas it is more than one on the part of the
persons united, so too the consent is one on the part of the thing
consented to, namely the aforesaid union, whereas it is more than one on
the part of the persons consenting. Nor is the direct object of consent a
husband but union with a husband on the part of the wife, even as it is
union with a wife on the part of the husband.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the consent needs to be expressed in words?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that there is no need for the consent to be
expressed in words. For a man is brought under another's power by a vow
just as he is by matrimony. Now a vow is binding in God's sight, even
though it be not expressed in words. Therefore consent also makes a
marriage binding even without being expressed in words.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, there can be marriage between persons who are unable to
express their mutual consent in words, through being dumb or of different
languages. Therefore expression of the consent by words is not required
for matrimony.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, if that which is essential to a sacrament be omitted for
any reason whatever, there is no sacrament. Now there is a case of
marriage without the expression of words if the maid is silent through
bashfulness when her parents give her away to the bridegroom. Therefore
the expression of words is not essential to matrimony.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[2] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, Matrimony is a sacrament. Now a sensible sign is
required in every sacrament. Therefore it is also required in matrimony,
and consequently there must needs be at least words by which the consent
is made perceptible to the senses.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[2] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, in matrimony there is a contract between husband and wife. Now
in every contract there must be expression of the words by which men bind
themselves mutually to one another. Therefore in matrimony also the
consent must be expressed in words.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, As stated above (A[1]), the marriage union is effected in
the same way as the bond in material contracts. And since material
contracts are not feasible unless the contracting parties express their
will to one another in words, it follows that the consent which makes a
marriage must also be expressed in words, so that the expression of words
is to marriage what the outward washing is to Baptism.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: In a vow there is not a sacramental but only a spiritual
bond, wherefore there is no need for it to be done in the same way as
material contracts, in order that it be binding, as in the case of
matrimony.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Although the like cannot plight themselves to one another
in words, they can do so by signs, and such signs count for words.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: According to Hugh of S. Victor (Tract. vii, Sum. Sent.),
persons who are being married should give their consent by accepting one
another freely. and this is judged to be the case if they show no dissent
when they are being wedded. Wherefore in such a case the words of the
parents are taken as being the maid's, for the fact that she does not
contradict them is a sign that they are her words.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether consent given in words expressive of the future makes a marriage?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that consent given in words expressive of the
future makes a marriage. For as present is to present, so is future to
future. But consent given in words expressive of the present makes a
marriage in the present. Therefore consent given in words expressive of
the future makes a marriage in the future.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, in other civil contracts, just as in matrimony, a
certain obligation results from the words expressing consent. Now in
other contracts it matters not whether the obligation is effected by
words of the present or of the future tense. Therefore neither does it
make any difference in matrimony.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, by the religious vow man contracts a spiritual marriage
with God. Now the religious vow is expressed in words of the future
tense, and is binding. Therefore carnal marriage also can be effected by
words of the future tense.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[3] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, A man who consents in words of the future tense to take
a particular woman as his wife, and after, by words of the present tense,
consents to take another, according to law must take the second for his
wife (cap. Sicut ex Litteris, De spons. et matr.). But this would not be
the case if consent given in words of the future tense made a marriage,
since from the very fact that his marriage with the one is valid, he
cannot, as long as she lives, marry another. Therefore consent given in
words of the future tense does not make a marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[3] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, he who promises to do a certain thing does it not yet. Now he
who consents in words of the future tense, promises to marry a certain
woman. Therefore he does not marry her yet.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[3] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, The sacramental causes produce their effect by signifying
it; hence they effect what they signify. Since therefore when a man
expresses his consent by words of the future tense, he does not signify
that he is marrying, but promises that he will marry, it follows that a
consent expressed in this manner does not make a marriage, but a promise
[sponsionem] of marriage, and this promise is known as a betrothal
[sponsalia].
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: When consent is expressed in words of the present tense,
not only are the words actually present, but consent is directed to the
present, so that they coincide in point of time; but when consent is
given in words of the future tense, although the words are actually
present, the consent is directed to a future time, and hence they do not
coincide in point of time. For this reason the comparison fails.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Even in other contracts, a man who uses words referring to
the future, does not transfer the power over his property to another
person---for instance if he were to say "I will give thee"---but only
when he uses words indicative of the present.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: In the vow of religious profession it is not the spiritual
marriage itself that is expressed in words which refer to the future, but
an act of the spiritual marriage, namely obedience or observance of the
rule. If, however, a man vow spiritual marriage in the future, it is not
a spiritual marriage, for a man does not become a monk by taking such a
vow, but promises to become one.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether, in the absence of inward consent, a marriage is made by consent
given in words of the present?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that even in the absence of inward consent a
marriage is made by consent expressed in words of the present. For "fraud
and deceit should benefit no man," according to the law (cap. Ex Tenore,
De Rescrip., cap. Si Vir, De cognat. spir.). Now he who gives consent in
words without consenting in heart commits a fraud. Therefore he should
not benefit by it, through being released of the bond of marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the mental consent of one person cannot be known to
another, except in so far as it is expressed in words. If then the
expression of the words is not enough, and inward consent is required in
both parties, neither of them will be able to know that he is truly
married to the other; and consequently whenever he uses marriage he will
commit fornication.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[4] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, if a man is proved to have consented to take a certain
woman to wife in words of the present tense, he is compelled under pain
of excommunication to take her as his wife, even though he should say
that he was wanting in mental consent, notwithstanding that afterwards he
may have contracted marriage with another woman by words expressive of
consent in the present. But this would not be the case if mental consent
were requisite for marriage. Therefore it is not required.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[4] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, Innocent III says in a Decretal (cap. Tua Nos, De
Spons. et matr.) in reference to this case: "Other things cannot complete
the marriage bond in the absence of consent."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[4] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, intention is necessary in all the sacraments. Now he who
consents not in his heart has no intention of contracting marriage; and
therefore he does not contract a marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[4] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, The outward cleansing stands in the same relation to
baptism as the expression of words to this sacrament, as stated above
(A[2]). Wherefore just as were a person to receive the outward cleansing,
with the intention, not of receiving the sacrament, but of acting in jest
or deceit, he would not be baptized; so, too, expression of words without
inward consent makes no marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: There are two things here, namely the lack of
consent---which benefits him in the tribunal of his conscience so that he
is not bound by the marriage tie, albeit not in the tribunal of the
Church where judgment is pronounced according to the evidence---and the
deceit in the words, which does not benefit him, neither in the tribunal
of his conscience nor in the tribunal of the Church, since in both he is
punished for this.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: If mental consent is lacking in one of the parties, on
neither side is there marriage, since marriage consists in a mutual
joining together, as stated above (Q[44], A[1]). However one may believe
that in all probability there is no fraud unless there be evident signs
thereof; because we must presume good of everyone, unless there be proof
of the contrary. Consequently the party in whom there is no fraud is
excused from sin on account of ignorance.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[4] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: In such a case the Church compels him to hold to his first
wife, because the Church judges according to outward appearances; nor is
she deceived in justice or right, although she is deceived in the facts
of the case. Yet such a man ought to bear the excommunication rather than
return to his first wife; or else he should go far away into another
country.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[5] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether consent given secretly in words of the present makes a marriage?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[5] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that consent given secretly in words of the present
does not make a marriage. For a thing that is in one person's power is
not transferred to the power of another without the consent of the person
in whose power it was. Now the maid is in her father's power. Therefore
she cannot by marriage be transferred to a husband's power without her
father's consent. Wherefore if consent be given secretly, even though it
should be expressed in words of the present, there will be no marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[5] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, in penance, just as in matrimony, our act is as it were
essential to the sacrament. But the sacrament of penance is not made
complete except by means of the ministers of the Church, who are the
dispensers of the sacraments. Therefore neither can marriage be perfected
without the priest's blessing.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[5] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, the Church does not forbid baptism to be given secretly,
since one may baptize either privately or publicly. But the Church does
forbid the celebration of clandestine marriages (cap. Cum inhibitio, De
clandest. despons.). Therefore they cannot be done secretly.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[5] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, marriage cannot be contracted by those who are related
in the second degree, because the Church has forbidden it. But the Church
has also forbidden clandestine marriages. Therefore they cannot be valid
marriages.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[5] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, Given the cause the effect follows. Now the sufficient
cause of matrimony is consent expressed in words of the present.
Therefore whether this be done in public or in private the result is a
marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[5] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, wherever there is the due matter and the due form of a
sacrament there is the sacrament. Now in a secret marriage there is the
due matter, since there are persons who are able lawfully to
contract---and the due form, since there are the words of the present
expressive of consent. Therefore there is a true marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[5] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Just as in the other sacraments certain things are
essential to the sacrament, and if they are omitted there is no
sacrament, while certain things belong to the solemnization of the
sacrament, and if these be omitted the sacrament is nevertheless validly
performed, although it is a sin to omit them; so, too, consent expressed
in words of the present between persons lawfully qualified to contract
makes a marriage, because these two conditions are essential to the
sacrament; while all else belongs to the solemnization of the sacrament,
as being done in order that the marriage may be more fittingly performed.
Hence if these be omitted it is a true marriage, although the contracting
parties sin, unless they have a lawful motive for being excused.
[*Clandestine marriages have since been declared invalid by the Council
of Trent (sess. xxiv). It must be borne in mind that throughout the
treatise on marriage St. Thomas gives the Canon Law of his time.]
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[5] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The maid is in her father's power, not as a female slave
without power over her own body, but as a daughter, for the purpose of
education. Hence, in so far as she is free, she can give herself into
another's power without her father's consent, even as a son or daughter,
since they are free, may enter religion without their parent's consent.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[5] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: In penance our act, although essential to the sacrament,
does not suffice for producing the proximate effect of the sacrament,
namely forgiveness of sins, and consequently it is necessary that the act
of the priest intervene in order that the sacrament be perfected. But in
matrimony our acts are the sufficient cause for the production of the
proximate effect, which is the marriage bond, because whoever has the
right to dispose of himself can bind himself to another. Consequently the
priest's blessing is not required for matrimony as being essential to the
sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[5] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: It is also forbidden to receive baptism otherwise than from
a priest, except in a case of necessity. But matrimony is not a necessary
sacrament: and consequently the comparison fails. However, clandestine
marriages are forbidden on account of the evil results to which they are
liable, since it often happens that one of the parties is guilty of fraud
in such marriages; frequently, too, they have recourse to other nuptials
when they repent of having married in haste; and many other evils result
therefrom, besides which there is something disgraceful about them.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[45] A[5] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: Clandestine marriages are not forbidden as though they were
contrary to the essentials of marriage, in the same way as the marriages
of unlawful persons, who are undue matter for this sacrament; and hence
there is no comparison.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[46] Out. Para. 1/1
OF THE CONSENT TO WHICH AN OATH OR CARNAL INTERCOURSE IS APPENDED (TWO
ARTICLES)
We must now consider the consent to which an oath or carnal intercourse
is appended. Under this head there are two points of inquiry:
(1) Whether an oath added to the consent that is expressed in words of
the future tense makes a marriage?
(2) Whether carnal intercourse supervening to such a consent makes a
marriage?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[46] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether an oath added to the consent that is expressed in words of the
future tense makes a marriage?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[46] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that if an oath be added to a consent that is
expressed in words of the future tense it makes a marriage. For no one
can bind himself to act against the Divine Law. But the fulfilling of an
oath is of Divine law according to Mt. 5:33, "Thou shalt perform thy
oaths to the Lord." Consequently no subsequent obligation can relieve a
man of the obligation to keep an oath previously taken. If, therefore,
after consenting to marry a woman by words expressive of the future and
confirming that consent with an oath, a man binds himself to another
woman by words expressive of the present, it would seem that none the
less he is bound to keep his former oath. But this would not be the case
unless that oath made the marriage complete. Therefore an oath affixed to
a consent expressed in words of the future tense makes a marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[46] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, Divine truth is stronger than human truth. Now an oath
confirms a thing with the Divine truth. Since then words expressive of
consent in the present in which there is mere human truth complete a
marriage, it would seem that much more is this the case with words of the
future confirmed by an oath.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[46] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, according to the Apostle (Heb. 6:16), "An oath for
confirmation is the end of all . . . controversy"; wherefore in a court
of justice at any rate one must stand by an oath rather than by a mere
affirmation. Therefore if a man consent to marry a woman by a simple
affirmation expressed in words of the present, after having consented to
marry another in words of the future confirmed by oath, it would seem
that in the judgment of the Church he should be compelled to take the
first and not the second as his wife.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[46] A[1] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, the simple uttering of words relating to the future
makes a betrothal. But the addition of an oath must have some effect.
Therefore it makes something more than a betrothal. Now beyond a
betrothal there is nothing but marriage. Therefore it makes a marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[46] A[1] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, What is future is not yet. Now the addition of an oath
does not make words of the future tense signify anything else than
consent to something future. Therefore it is not a marriage yet.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[46] A[1] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, after a marriage is complete, no further consent is required
for the marriage. But after the oath there is yet another consent which
makes the marriage, else it would be useless to swear to a future
marriage. Therefore it does not make a marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[46] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, An oath is employed in confirmation of one's words;
wherefore it confirms that only which is signified by the words, nor does
it change their signification. Consequently, since it belongs to words of
the future tense, by their very signification, not to make a marriage,
since what is promised in the future is not done yet, even though an oath
be added to the promise, the marriage is not made yet, as the Master says
in the text (Sent. iv, D, 28).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[46] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The fulfilling of a lawful oath is of Divine law, but not
the fulfilling of an unlawful oath. Wherefore if a subsequent obligation
makes that oath unlawful, whereas it was lawful before, he who does not
keep the oath he took previously does not disobey the Divine law. And so
it is in the case in point; since he swears unlawfully who promises
unlawfully; and a promise about another's property is unlawful.
Consequently the subsequent consent by words of the present, whereby a
man transfers the power over his body to another woman, makes the
previous oath unlawful which was lawful before.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[46] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The Divine truth is most efficacious in confirming that to
which it is applied. Hence the Reply to the Third Objection is clear.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[46] A[1] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: The oath has some effect, not by causing a new obligation,
but confirming that which is already made, and thus he who violates it
sins more grievously.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[46] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether carnal intercourse after consent expressed in words of the future
makes a marriage?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[46] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that carnal intercourse after consent expressed in
words of the future makes a marriage. For consent by deed is greater than
consent by word. But he who has carnal intercourse consents by deed to
the promise he has previously made. Therefore it would seem that much
more does this make a marriage than if he were to consent to mere words
referring to the present.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[46] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, not only explicit but also interpretive consent makes a
marriage. Now there can be no better interpretation of consent than
carnal intercourse. Therefore marriage is completed thereby.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[46] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, all carnal union outside marriage is a sin. But the
woman, seemingly, does not sin by admitting her betrothed to carnal
intercourse. Therefore it makes a marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[46] A[2] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, "Sin is not forgiven unless restitution be made," as
Augustine says (Ep. cliii ad Macedon.). Now a man cannot reinstate a
woman whom he has violated under the pretense of marriage unless he marry
her. Therefore it would seem that even if, after his carnal intercourse,
he happen to contract with another by words of the present tense, he is
bound to return to the first; and this would not be the case unless he
were married to her. Therefore carnal intercourse after consent referring
to the future makes a marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[46] A[2] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, Pope Nicholas I says (Resp. ad Consult. Bulg. iii; Cap.
Tuas dudum, De clandest. despons.), "Without the consent to marriage,
other things, including coition, are of no effect."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[46] A[2] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, that which follows a thing does not make it. But carnal
intercourse follows the actual marriage, as effect follows cause.
Therefore it cannot make a marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[46] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, We may speak of marriage in two ways. First, in reference
to the tribunal of conscience, and thus in very truth carnal intercourse
cannot complete a marriage the promise of which has previously been made
in words expressive of the future, if inward consent is lacking, since
words, even though expressive of the present, would not make a marriage
in the absence of mental consent, as stated above (Q[45], A[4]).
Secondly, in reference to the judgment of the Church; and since in the
external tribunal judgment is given in accordance with external evidence,
and since nothing is more expressly significant of consent than carnal
intercourse, it follows that in the judgment of the Church carnal
intercourse following on betrothal is declared to make a marriage, unless
there appear clear signs of deceit or fraud [*According to the
pre-Tridentine legislation] (De sponsal. et matrim., cap. Is qui fidem).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[46] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: In reality he who has carnal intercourse consents by deed
to the act of sexual union, and does not merely for this reason consent
to marriage except according to the interpretation of the law.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[46] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: This interpretation does not alter the truth of the matter,
but changes the judgment which is about external things.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[46] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: If the woman admit her betrothed, thinking that he wishes
to consummate the marriage, she is excused from the sin, unless there be
clear signs of fraud; for instance if they differ considerably in birth
or fortune, or some other evident sign appear. Nevertheless the affianced
husband is guilty of fornication, and should be punished for this fraud
he has committed.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[46] A[2] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: In a case of this kind the affianced husband, before his
marriage with the other woman, is bound to marry the one to whom he was
betrothed, if she be his equal or superior in rank. But if he has married
another woman, he is no longer able to fulfill his obligation, wherefore
it suffices if he provide for her marriage. Nor is he bound even to do
this, according to some, if her affianced husband is of much higher rank
than she, or if there be some evident sign of fraud, because it may be
presumed that in all probability she was not deceived but pretended to be.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] Out. Para. 1/1
OF COMPULSORY AND CONDITIONAL CONSENT (SIX ARTICLES)
We must now consider compulsory and conditional consent. Under this head
there are six points of inquiry:
(1) Whether compulsory consent is possible?
(2) Whether a constant man can be compelled by fear?
(4) Whether compulsory consent makes a marriage as regards the party
using compulsion?
(5) Whether conditional consent makes a marriage?
(6) Whether one can be compelled by one's father to marry?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether a compulsory consent is possible?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that no consent can be compulsory. For, as stated
above (Sent. ii, D, 25 [*FS, Q[6], A[4]]) the free-will cannot be
compelled. Now consent is an act of the free-will. Therefore it cannot be
compulsory.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, violent is the same as compulsory. Now, according to the
Philosopher (Ethic. iii, 1), "a violent action is one the principle of
which is without, the patient concurring not at all." But the principle
of consent is always within. Therefore no consent can be compulsory.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, every sin is perfected by consent. But that which
perfects a sin cannot be compulsory, for, according to Augustine (De Lib.
Arb. iii, 18), "no one sins in what he cannot avoid." Since then violence
is defined by jurists (i, ff. de eo quod vi metusve) as the "force of a
stronger being that cannot be repulsed," it would seem that consent
cannot be compulsory or violent.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[1] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, power is opposed to liberty. But compulsion is allied to
power, as appears from a definition of Tully's in which he says that
"compulsion is the force of one who exercises his power to detain a thing
outside its proper bounds." Therefore the free-will cannot be compelled,
and consequently neither can consent which is an act thereof.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[1] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, That which cannot be, cannot be an impediment. But
compulsory consent is an impediment to matrimony, as stated in the text
(Sent. iv, D, 29). Therefore consent can be compelled.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[1] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, in marriage there is a contract. Now the will can be compelled
in the matter of contracts; for which reason the law adjudges that
restitution should be made of the whole, for it does not ratify "that
which was done under compulsion or fear" (Sent. iv, D[29]). Therefore in
marriage also it is possible for the consent to be compulsory.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[1] Body Para. 1/2
I answer that, Compulsion or violence is twofold. One is the cause of
absolute necessity, and violence of this kind the Philosopher calls
(Ethic. iii, 1) "violent simply," as when by bodily strength one forces a
person to move; the other causes conditional necessity, and the
Philosopher calls this a "mixed violence," as when a person throws his
merchandise overboard in order to save himself. In the latter kind of
violence, although the thing done is not voluntary in itself, yet taking
into consideration the circumstances of place and time it is voluntary.
And since actions are about particulars, it follows that it is voluntary
simply, and involuntary in a certain respect (Cf. FS, Q[6], A[6]).
Wherefore this latter violence or compulsion is consistent with consent,
but not the former. And since this compulsion results from one's fear of
a threatening danger, it follows that this violence coincides with fear
which, in a manner, compels the will, whereas the former violence has to
do with bodily actions. Moreover, since the law considers not merely
internal actions, but rather external actions, consequently it takes
violence to mean absolute compulsion, for which reason it draws a
distinction between violence and fear. Here, however, it is a question of
internal consent which cannot be influenced by compulsion or violence as
distinct from fear. Therefore as to the question at issue compulsion and
fear are the same. Now, according to lawyers fear is "the agitation of
the mind occasioned by danger imminent or future" (Ethic. iii, 1).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[1] Body Para. 2/2
This suffices for the Replies to the Objections; for the first set of
arguments consider the first kind of compulsion, and the second set of
arguments consider the second.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether a constant man can be compelled by fear?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that "a constant man" [*Cap. Ad audientiam, De his
quae vi.] cannot be compelled by fear. Because the nature of a constant
man is not to be agitated in the midst of dangers. Since then fear is
"agitation of the mind occasioned by imminent danger," it would seem that
he is not compelled by fear.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, "Of all fearsome things death is the limit," according
to the Philosopher (Ethic. iii, 6), as though it were the most perfect of
all things that inspire fear. But the constant man is not compelled by
death, since the brave face even mortal dangers. Therefore no fear
influences a constant man.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, of all dangers a good man fears most that which affects
his good name. But the fear of disgrace is not reckoned to influence a
constant man, because, according to the law (vii, ff, de eo quod metus,
etc.), "fear of disgrace is not included under the ordinance, 'That which
is done through fear'" [*Dig. iv, 2, Quod metus causa]. Therefore
neither does any other kind of fear influence a constant man.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[2] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, in him who is compelled by fear, fear leaves a sin, for
it makes him promise what he is unwilling to fulfill, and thus it makes
him lie. But a constant man does not commit a sin, not even a very slight
one, for fear. Therefore no fear influences a constant man.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[2] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, Abraham and Isaac were constant. Yet they were
influenced by fear, since on account of fear each said that his wife was
his sister (Gn. 12:12; 26:7).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[2] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, wherever there is mixed violence, it is fear that compels. But
however constant a man may be he may suffer violence of that kind, for if
he be on the sea, he will throw his merchandise overboard if menaced with
shipwreck. Therefore fear can influence a constant man.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, By fear influencing a man we mean his being compelled by
fear. A man is compelled by fear when he does that which otherwise he
would not wish to do, in order to avoid that which he fears. Now the
constant differs from the inconstant man in two respects. First, in
respect of the quality of the danger feared, because the constant man
follows right reason, whereby he knows whether to omit this rather than
that, and whether to do this rather than that. Now the lesser evil or the
greater good is always to be chosen in preference; and therefore the
constant man is compelled to bear with the lesser evil through fear of
the greater evil, but he is not compelled to bear with the greater evil
in order to avoid the lesser. But the inconstant man is compelled to bear
with the greater evil through fear of a lesser evil, namely to commit sin
through fear of bodily suffering; whereas on the contrary the obstinate
man cannot be compelled even to permit or to do a lesser evil, in order
to avoid a greater. Hence the constant man is a mean between the
inconstant and the obstinate. Secondly, they differ as to their estimate
of the threatening evil, for a constant man is not compelled unless for
grave and probable reasons, while the inconstant man is compelled by
trifling motives: "The wicked man seeth when no man pursueth" (Prov.
28:1).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The constant man, like the brave man, is fearless, as the
Philosopher states (Ethic. iii, 4), not that he is altogether without
fear, but because he fears not what he ought not to fear, or where, or
when he ought not to fear.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Sin is the greatest of evils, and consequently a constant
man can nowise be compelled to sin; indeed a man should die rather than
suffer the like, as again the Philosopher says (Ethic. iii, 6,9). Yet
certain bodily injuries are less grievous than certain others; and chief
among them are those which relate to the person, such as death, blows,
the stain resulting from rape, and slavery. Wherefore the like compel a
constant man to suffer other bodily injuries. They are contained in the
verse: "Rape, status, blows, and death." Nor does it matter whether they
refer to his own person, or to the person of his wife or children, or the
like.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Although disgrace is a greater injury it is easy to remedy
it. Hence fear of disgrace is not reckoned to influence a constant man
according to law.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[2] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: The constant man is not compelled to lie, because at the
time he wishes to give; yet afterwards he wishes to ask for restitution,
or at least to appeal to the judge, if he promised not to ask for
restitution. But he cannot promise not to appeal, for since this is
contrary to the good of justice, he cannot be compelled thereto, namely
to act against justice.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether compulsory consent invalidates a marriage?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that compulsory consent does not invalidate a
marriage. For just as consent is necessary for matrimony, so is intention
necessary for Baptism. Now one who is compelled by fear to receive
Baptism, receives the sacrament. Therefore one who is compelled by fear
to consent is bound by his marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, according to the Philosopher (Ethic. iii, 1), that which
is done on account of mixed violence is more voluntary than involuntary.
Now consent cannot be compelled except by mixed violence. Therefore it is
not entirely involuntary, and consequently the marriage is valid.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, seemingly he who has consented to marriage under
compulsion ought to be counseled to stand to that marriage; because to
promise and not to fulfill has an "appearance of evil," and the Apostle
wishes us to refrain from all such things (1 Thess 5:22). But that would
not be the case if compulsory consent invalidated a marriage altogether.
Therefore, etc.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[3] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, A Decretal says (cap. Cum locum, De sponsal. et
matrim.): "Since there is no room for consent where fear or compulsion
enters in, it follows that where a person's consent is required, every
pretext for compulsion must be set aside." Now mutual contract is
necessary in marriage. Therefore, etc.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[3] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, Matrimony signifies the union of Christ with the Church, which
union is according to the liberty of love. Therefore it cannot be the
result of compulsory consent.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[3] Body Para. 1/2
I answer that, The marriage bond is everlasting. Hence whatever is
inconsistent with its perpetuity invalidates marriage. Now the fear which
compels a constant man deprives the contract of its perpetuity, since its
complete rescission can be demanded. Wherefore this compulsion by fear
which influences a constant man, invalidates marriage, but not the other
compulsion. Now a constant man is reckoned a virtuous man who, according
to the Philosopher (Ethic. iii, 4), is a measure in all human actions.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[3] Body Para. 2/2
However, some say that if there be consent although compulsory, the
marriage is valid in conscience and in God's sight, but not in the eyes
of the Church, who presumes that there was no inward consent on account
of the fear. But this is of no account, because the Church should not
presume a person to sin until it be proved; and he sinned if he said that
he consented whereas he did not consent. Wherefore the Church presumes
that he did consent, but judges this compulsory consent to be
insufficient for a valid marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The intention is not the efficient cause of the sacrament
in baptism, it is merely the cause that elicits the action of the agent;
whereas the consent is the efficient cause in matrimony. Hence the
comparison fails.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Not any kind of voluntariness suffices for marriage: it
must be completely voluntary, because it has to be perpetual; and
consequently it is invalidated by violence of a mixed nature.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: He ought not always to be advised to stand to that
marriage, but only when evil results are feared from its dissolution. Nor
does he sin if he does otherwise, because there is no appearance of evil
in not fulfilling a promise that one has made unwillingly.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether compulsory consent makes a marriage as regards the party who uses
compulsion?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that compulsory consent makes a marriage, at least
as regards the party who uses compulsion. For matrimony is a sign of a
spiritual union. But spiritual union which is by charity may be with one
who has not charity. Therefore marriage is possible with one who wills it
not.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, if she who was compelled consents afterwards, it will be
a true marriage. But he who compelled her before is not bound by her
consent. Therefore he was married to her by virtue of the consent he gave
before.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[4] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, Matrimony is an equiparant relation. Now a relation of
that kind is equally in both terms. Therefore if there is an impediment
on the part of one, there will be no marriage on the part of the other.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[4] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Since marriage is a kind of relation, and a relation
cannot arise in one of the terms without arising in the other, it follows
that whatever is an impediment to matrimony in the one, is an impediment
to matrimony in the other; since it is impossible for a man to be the
husband of one who is not his wife, or for a woman to be a wife without
a husband, just as it is impossible to be a mother without having a
child. Hence it is a common saying that "marriage is not lame."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Although the act of the lover can be directed to one who
loves not, there can be no union between them, unless love be mutual.
Wherefore the Philosopher says (Ethic. viii, 2) that friendship which
consists in a kind of union requires a return of love.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Marriage does not result from the consent of her who was
compelled before, except in so far as the other party's previous consent
remains in force; wherefore if he were to withdraw his consent there
would be no marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[5] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether conditional consent makes a marriage?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[5] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that not even a conditional consent makes a
marriage, because a statement is not made simply if it is made subject to
a condition. But in marriage the words expressive of consent must be
uttered simply. Therefore a conditional consent makes no marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[5] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, marriage should be certain. But where a statement is
made under a condition it is rendered doubtful. Therefore a like consent
makes no marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[5] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, In other contracts an obligation is undertaken
conditionally, and holds so long as the condition holds. Therefore since
marriage is a contract, it would seem that it can be made by a
conditional consent.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[5] Body Para. 1/2
I answer that, The condition made is either of the present or of the
future. If it is of the present and is not contrary to marriage, whether
it be moral or immoral, the marriage holds if the condition is verified,
and is invalid if the condition is not verified. If, however, it be
contrary to the marriage blessings, the marriage is invalid, as we have
also said in reference to betrothals (Q[43], A[1]). But if the condition
refer to the future, it is either necessary, as that the sun will rise
tomorrow---and then the marriage is valid, because such future things are
present in their causes---or else it is contingent, as the payment of a
sum of money, or the consent of the parents, and then the judgment about
a consent of this kind is the same as about a consent expressed in words
of the future tense; wherefore it makes no marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[5] Body Para. 2/2
This suffices for the Replies to the Objections.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[6] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether one can be compelled by one's father's command to marry?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[6] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that one can be compelled by one's father's command
to marry. For it is written (Col. 3:20): "Children, obey your parents in
all things." Therefore they are bound to obey them in this also.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[6] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, Isaac charged Jacob (Gn. 28:1) not to take a wife from
the daughters of Chanaan. But he would not have charged him thus unless
he had the right to command it. Therefore a son is bound to obey his
father in this.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[6] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, no one should promise, especially with an oath, for one
whom he cannot compel to keep the promise. Now parents promise future
marriages for their children, and even confirm their promise by oath.
Therefore they can compel their children to keep that promise.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[6] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, our spiritual father, the Pope to wit, can by his
command compel a man to a spiritual marriage, namely to accept a
bishopric. Therefore a carnal father can compel his son to marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[6] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, A son may lawfully enter religion though his father
command him to marry. Therefore he is not bound to obey him in this.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[6] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, if he were bound to obey, a betrothal contracted by the parents
would hold good without their children's consent. But this is against the
law (cap. Ex litteris, De despon. impub.). Therefore, etc.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[6] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Since in marriage there is a kind of perpetual service,
as it were, a father cannot by his command compel his son to marry, since
the latter is of free condition: but he may induce him for a reasonable
cause; and thus the son will be affected by his father's command in the
same way as he is affected by that cause, so that if the cause be
compelling as indicating either obligation or fitness, his father's
command will compel him in the same measure: otherwise he may not compel
him.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[6] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The words of the Apostle do not refer to those matters in
which a man is his own master as the father is. Such is marriage by which
the son also becomes a father.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[6] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: There were other motives why Jacob was bound to do what
Isaac commanded him, both on account of the wickedness of those women,
and because the seed of Chanaan was to be cast forth from the land which
was promised to the seed of the patriarchs. Hence Isaac could command
this.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[6] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: They do not swear except with the implied condition "if it
please them"; and they are bound to induce them in good faith.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[47] A[6] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: Some say that the Pope cannot command a man to accept a
bishopric, because consent should be free. But if this be granted there
would be an end of ecclesiastical order, for unless a man can be
compelled to accept the government of a church, the Church could not be
preserved, since sometimes those who are qualified for the purpose are
unwilling to accept unless they be compelled. Therefore we must reply
that the two cases are not parallel; for there is no bodily service in a
spiritual marriage as there is in the bodily marriage; because the
spiritual marriage is a kind of office for dispensing the public weal:
"Let a man so account of us as of the ministers of Christ, and the
dispensers of the mysteries of God" (1 Cor. 4:1).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[48] Out. Para. 1/1
OF THE OBJECT OF THE CONSENT (TWO ARTICLES)
We must now consider the object of the consent. Under this head there
are two points of inquiry:
(1) Whether the consent that makes a marriage is a consent to carnal
intercourse?
(2) Whether consent to marry a person for an immoral motive makes a
marriage?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[48] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the consent that makes a marriage is a consent to carnal
intercourse?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[48] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the consent which makes a marriage is a
consent to carnal intercourse. For Jerome [*The words quoted are found
implicitly in St. Augustine (De Bono Viduit ix)] says that "for those who
have vowed virginity it is wicked, not only to marry, but even to wish to
marry." But it would not be wicked unless it were contrary to virginity,
and marriage is not contrary to virginity except by reason of carnal
intercourse. Therefore the will's consent in marriage is a consent to
carnal intercourse.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[48] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, whatever there is in marriage between husband and wife
is lawful between brother and sister except carnal intercourse. But there
cannot lawfully be a consent to marriage between them. Therefore the
marriage consent is a consent to carnal intercourse.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[48] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, if the woman say to the man: "I consent to take thee
provided however that you know me not," it is not a marriage consent,
because it contains something against the essence of that consent. Yet
this would not be the case unless the marriage consent were a consent to
carnal intercourse. Therefore, etc.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[48] A[1] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, in everything the beginning corresponds to the
consummation. Now marriage is consummated by carnal intercourse.
Therefore, since it begins by the consent, it would seem that the consent
is to carnal intercourse.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[48] A[1] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, No one that consents to carnal intercourse is a virgin
in mind and body. Yet Blessed John the evangelist after consenting to
marriage was a virgin both in mind and body. Therefore he did not consent
to carnal intercourse.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[48] A[1] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, the effect corresponds to its cause. Now consent is the cause
of marriage. Since then carnal intercourse is not essential to marriage,
seemingly neither is the consent which causes marriage a consent to
carnal intercourse.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[48] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, The consent that makes a marriage is a consent to
marriage, because the proper effect of the will is the thing willed.
Wherefore, according as carnal intercourse stands in relation to
marriage, so far is the consent that causes marriage a consent to carnal
intercourse. Now, as stated above (Q[44], A[1]; Q[45], AA[1],2), marriage
is not essentially the carnal union itself, but a certain joining
together of husband and wife ordained to carnal intercourse, and a
further consequent union between husband and wife, in so far as they each
receive power over the other in reference to carnal intercourse, which
joining together is called the nuptial bond. Hence it is evident that
they said well who asserted that to consent to marriage is to consent to
carnal intercourse implicitly and not explicitly. For carnal intercourse
is not to be understood, except as an effect is implicitly contained in
its cause, for the power to have carnal intercourse, which power is the
object of the consent, is the cause of carnal intercourse, just as the
power to use one's own property is the cause of the use.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[48] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The reason why consent to marriage after taking the vow of
virginity is sinful, is because that consent gives a power to do what is
unlawful: even so would a man sin if he gave another man the power to
receive that which he has in deposit, and not only by actually delivering
it to him. With regard to the consent of the Blessed Virgin, we have
spoken about it above (Sent. iv, D, 3; TP, Q[29], A[2]).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[48] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Between brother and sister there can be no power of one
over the other in relation to carnal intercourse, even as neither can
there be lawfully carnal intercourse itself. Consequently the argument
does not prove.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[48] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Such an explicit condition is contrary not only to the act
but also to the power of carnal intercourse, and therefore it is contrary
to marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[48] A[1] R.O. 4 Para. 1/2
Reply OBJ 4: Marriage begun corresponds to marriage consummated, as
habit or power corresponds to the act which is operation.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[48] A[1] R.O. 4 Para. 2/2
The arguments on the contrary side show that consent is not given
explicitly to carnal intercourse; and this is true.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[48] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether marriage can result from one person's consent to take another for
a base motive?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[48] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that marriage cannot result from one person's
consent to take another for a base motive. For there is but one reason
for one thing. Now marriage is one sacrament. Therefore it cannot result
from the intention of any other end than that for which it was instituted
by God; namely the begetting of children.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[48] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the marriage union is from God, according to Mt. 19:6,
"What . . . God hath joined together let no man put asunder." But a union
that is made for immoral motives is not from God. Therefore it is not a
marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[48] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, in the other sacraments, if the intention of the Church
be not observed, the sacrament is invalid. Now the intention of the
Church in the sacrament of matrimony is not directed to a base purpose.
Therefore, if a marriage be contracted for a base purpose, it will not be
a valid marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[48] A[2] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, according to Boethius (De Diff., Topic. ii) "a thing is
good if its end be good." But matrimony is always good. Therefore it is
not matrimony if it is done for an evil end.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[48] A[2] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, matrimony signifies the union of Christ with the Church;
and in this there can be nothing base. Neither therefore can marriage be
contracted for a base motive.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[48] A[2] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, He who baptizes another for the sake of gain baptizes
validly. Therefore if a man marries a woman for the purpose of gain it is
a valid marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[48] A[2] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, the same conclusion is proved by the examples and authorities
quoted in the text (Sent. iv, D, 30).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[48] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, The final cause of marriage may be taken as twofold,
namely essential and accidental. The essential cause of marriage is the
end to which it is by its very nature ordained, and this is always good,
namely the begetting of children and the avoiding of fornication. But the
accidental final cause thereof is that which the contracting parties
intend as the result of marriage. And since that which is intended as the
result of marriage is consequent upon marriage, and since that which
comes first is not altered by what comes after, but conversely; marriage
does not become good or evil by reason of that cause, but the contracting
parties to whom this cause is the essential end. And since accidental
causes are infinite in number, it follows that there can be an infinite
number of such causes in matrimony, some of which are good and some bad.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[48] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: This is true of the essential and principal cause; but that
which has one essential and principal end may have several secondary
essential ends, and an infinite number of accidental ends.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[48] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The joining together can be taken for the relation itself
which is marriage, and that is always from God, and is good, whatever be
its cause; or for the act of those who are being joined together, and
thus it is sometimes evil and is not from God simply. Nor is it
unreasonable that an effect be from God, the cause of which is evil, such
as a child born of adultery; for it is not from that cause as evil, but
as having some good in so far as it is from God, although it is not from
God simply.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[48] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: The intention of the Church whereby she intends to confer a
sacrament is essential to each sacrament, so that if it be not observed,
all sacraments are null. But the intention of the Church whereby she
intends an advantage resulting from the sacrament belongs to the
well-being and not to the essence of a sacrament; wherefore, if it be not
observed, the sacrament is none the less valid. Yet he who omits this
intention sins; for instance if in baptism one intend not the healing of
the mind which the Church intends. In like manner he who intends to
marry, although he fail to direct it to the end which the Church intends,
nevertheless contracts a valid marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[48] A[2] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: This evil which is intended is the end not of marriage, but
of the contracting parties.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[48] A[2] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: The union itself, and not the action of those who are
united, is the sign of the union of Christ with the Church: wherefore the
conclusion does not follow.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] Out. Para. 1/2
OF THE MARRIAGE GOODS* (SIX ARTICLES) [*"Bona matrimonii," variously
rendered marriage goods, marriage blessings, and advantages of marriage.]
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] Out. Para. 2/2
In the next place we must consider the marriage goods. Under this head
there are six points of inquiry:
(1) Whether certain goods are necessary in order to excuse marriage?
(2) Whether those assigned are sufficient?
(3) Whether the sacrament is the principal among the goods?
(4) Whether the marriage act is excused from sin by the aforesaid goods?
(5) Whether it can ever be excused from sin without them?
(6) Whether in their absence it is always a mortal sin?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether certain blessings are necessary in order to excuse marriage?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that certain blessings are not necessary in order
to excuse marriage. For just as the preservation of the individual which
is effected by the nutritive power is intended by nature, so too is the
preservation of the species which is effected by marriage; and indeed so
much the more as the good of the species is better and more exalted than
the good of the individual. But no goods are necessary to excuse the act
of the nutritive power. Neither therefore are they necessary to excuse
marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, according to the Philosopher (Ethic. viii, 12) the
friendship between husband and wife is natural, and includes the
virtuous, the useful, and the pleasant. But that which is virtuous in
itself needs no excuse. Therefore neither should any goods be assigned
for the excuse of matrimony.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, matrimony was instituted as a remedy and as an office,
as stated above (Q[42], A[2]). Now it needs no excuse in so far as it is
instituted as an office, since then it would also have needed an excuse
in paradise, which is false, for there, as Augustine says, "marriage
would have been without reproach and the marriage-bed without stain"
(Gen. ad lit. ix). In like manner neither does it need an excuse in so
far as it is intended as a remedy, any more than the other sacraments
which were instituted as remedies for sin. Therefore matrimony does not
need these excuses.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[1] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, the virtues are directed to whatever can be done aright.
If then marriage can be righted by certain goods, it needs nothing else
to right it besides the virtues of the soul; and consequently there is no
need to assign to matrimony any goods whereby it is righted, any more
than to other things in which the virtues direct us.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[1] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, Wherever there is indulgence, there must needs be some
reason for excuse. Now marriage is allowed in the state of infirmity "by
indulgence" (1 Cor. 7:6). Therefore it needs to be excused by certain
goods.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[1] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, the intercourse of fornication and that of marriage are of the
same species as regards the species of nature. But the intercourse of
fornication is wrong in itself. Therefore, in order that the marriage
intercourse be not wrong, something must be added to it to make it right,
and draw it to another moral species.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, No wise man should allow himself to lose a thing except
for some compensation in the shape of an equal or better good. Wherefore
for a thing that has a loss attached to it to be eligible, it needs to
have some good connected with it, which by compensating for that loss
makes that thing ordinate and right. Now there is a loss of reason
incidental to the union of man and woman, both because the reason is
carried away entirely on account of the vehemence of the pleasure, so
that it is unable to understand anything at the same time, as the
Philosopher says (Ethic. vii, 11); and again because of the tribulation
of the flesh which such persons have to suffer from solicitude for
temporal things (1 Cor. 7:28). Consequently the choice of this union
cannot be made ordinate except by certain compensations whereby that same
union is righted. and these are the goods which excuse marriage and make
it right.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: In the act of eating there is not such an intense pleasure
overpowering the reason as in the aforesaid action, both because the
generative power, whereby original sin is transmitted, is infected and
corrupt, whereas the nutritive power, by which original sin is not
transmitted, is neither corrupt nor infected; and again because each one
feels in himself a defect of the individual more than a defect of the
species. Hence, in order to entice a man to take food which supplies a
defect of the individual, it is enough that he feel this defect; but in
order to entice him to the act whereby a defect of the species is
remedied, Divine providence attached pleasure to that act, which moves
even irrational animals in which there is not the stain of original sin.
Hence the comparison fails.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: These goods which justify marriage belong to the nature of
marriage, which consequently needs them, not as extrinsic causes of its
rectitude, but as causing in it that rectitude which belongs to it by
nature.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: From the very fact that marriage is intended as an office
or as a remedy it has the aspect of something useful and right;
nevertheless both aspects belong to it from the fact that it has these
goods by which it fulfills the office and affords a remedy to
concupiscence.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[1] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: An act of virtue may derive its rectitude both from the
virtue as its elicitive principle, and from its circumstances as its
formal principles; and the goods of marriage are related to marriage as
circumstances to an act of virtue which owes it to those circumstances
that it can be an act of virtue.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the goods of marriage are sufficiently enumerated?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the goods of marriage are insufficiently
enumerated by the Master (Sent. iv, D, 31), namely "faith, offspring, and
sacrament." For the object of marriage among men is not only the
begetting and feeding of children, but also the partnership of a common
life, whereby each one contributes his share of work to the common stock,
as stated in Ethic. viii, 12. Therefore as the offspring is reckoned a
good of matrimony, so also should the communication of works.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the union of Christ with the Church, signified by
matrimony, is the effect of charity. Therefore charity rather than faith
should be reckoned among the goods of matrimony.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, in matrimony, just as it is required that neither party
have intercourse with another, so is it required that the one pay the
marriage debt to the other. Now the former pertains to faith according to
the Master (Sent. iv, D, 31). Therefore justice should also be reckoned
among the goods of marriage on account of the payment of the debt.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[2] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, in matrimony as signifying the union of Christ with the
Church, just as indivisibility is required, so also is unity, whereby one
man has one wife. But the sacrament which is reckoned among the three
marriage goods pertains to indivisibility. Therefore there should be
something else pertaining to unity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[2] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: On the other hand, it would seem that they are too many. For one
virtue suffices to make one act right. Now faith is one virtue. Therefore
it was not necessary to add two other goods to make marriage right.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[2] Obj. 6 Para. 1/1
OBJ 6: Further, the same cause does not make a thing both useful and
virtuous, since the useful and the virtuous are opposite divisions of the
good. Now marriage derives its character of useful from the offspring.
Therefore the offspring should not be reckoned among the goods that make
marriage virtuous.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[2] Obj. 7 Para. 1/1
OBJ 7: Further, nothing should be reckoned as a property or condition of
itself. Now these goods are reckoned to be conditions of marriage.
Therefore since matrimony is a sacrament, the sacrament should not be
reckoned a condition of matrimony.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Matrimony is instituted both as an office of nature and
as a sacrament of the Church. As an office of nature it is directed by
two things, like every other virtuous act. one of these is required on
the part of the agent and is the intention of the due end, and thus the
"offspring" is accounted a good of matrimony; the other is required on
the part of the act, which is good generically through being about a due
matter; and thus we have "faith," whereby a man has intercourse with his
wife and with no other woman. Besides this it has a certain goodness as a
sacrament, and this is signified by the very word "sacrament."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Offspring signifies not only the begetting of children, but
also their education, to which as its end is directed the entire
communion of works that exists between man and wife as united in
marriage, since parents naturally "lay up" for their "children" (2 Cor.
12:14); so that the offspring like a principal end includes another, as
it were, secondary end.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Faith is not taken here as a theological virtue, but as
part of justice, in so far as faith [fides] signifies the suiting of deed
to word [fiant dicta] by keeping one's promises; for since marriage is a
contract it contains a promise whereby this man is assigned to this woman.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Just as the marriage promise means that neither party is to
have intercourse with a third party, so does it require that they should
mutually pay the marriage debt. The latter is indeed the chief of the
two, since it follows from the power which each receives over the other.
Consequently both these things pertain to faith, although the Book of
Sentences mentions that which is the less manifest.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[2] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: By sacrament we are to understand not only indivisibility,
but all those things that result from marriage being a sign of Christ's
union with the Church. We may also reply that the unity to which the
objection refers pertains to faith, just as indivisibility belongs to
the sacrament.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[2] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: Faith here does not denote a virtue, but that condition of
virtue which is a part of justice and is called by the name of faith.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[2] R.O. 6 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 6: Just as the right use of a useful good derives its
rectitude not from the useful but from the reason which causes the right
use, so too direction to a useful good may cause the goodness of
rectitude by virtue of the reason causing the right direction; and in
this way marriage, through being directed to the offspring, is useful,
and nevertheless righteous, inasmuch as it is directed aright.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[2] R.O. 7 Para. 1/2
Reply OBJ 7: As the Master says (Sent. iv, D, 31), sacrament here does
not mean matrimony itself, but its indissolubility, which is a sign of
the same thing as matrimony is.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[2] R.O. 7 Para. 2/2
We may also reply that although marriage is a sacrament, marriage as
marriage is not the same as marriage as a sacrament, since it was
instituted not only as a sign of a sacred thing, but also as an office of
nature. Hence the sacramental aspect is a condition added to marriage
considered in itself, whence also it derives its rectitude. Hence its
sacramentality, if I may use the term, is reckoned among the goods which
justify marriage; and accordingly this third good of marriage, the
sacrament to wit, denotes not only its indissolubility, but also whatever
pertains to its signification.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the sacrament is the chief of the marriage goods?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the "sacrament" is not the chief of the
marriage goods. For the end is principal in everything. Now the end of
marriage is the offspring. Therefore the offspring is the chief marriage
good.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, in the specific nature the difference is more important
than the genus, even as the form is more important than matter in the
composition of a natural thing. Now "sacrament" refers to marriage on the
part of its genus, while "offspring" and "faith" refer thereto on the
part of the difference whereby it is a special kind of sacrament.
Therefore these other two are more important than sacrament in reference
to marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, just as we find marriage without "offspring" and without
"faith," so do we find it without indissolubility, as in the case where
one of the parties enters religion before the marriage is consummated.
Therefore neither from this point of view is "sacrament" the most
important marriage good.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[3] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, an effect cannot be more important than its cause. Now
consent, which is the cause of matrimony, is often changed. Therefore the
marriage also can be dissolved and consequently inseparability is not
always a condition of marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[3] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, the sacraments which produce an everlasting effect
imprint a character. But no character is imprinted in matrimony.
Therefore it is not conditioned by a lasting inseparability. Consequently
just as there is marriage without "offspring" so is there marriage
without "sacrament," and thus the same conclusion follows as above.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[3] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, That which has a place in the definition of a thing is
most essential thereto. Now inseparability, which pertains to sacrament,
is placed in the definition of marriage (Q[44], A[3]), while offspring
and faith are not. Therefore among the other goods sacrament is the most
essential to matrimony.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[3] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, the Divine power which works in the sacraments is more
efficacious than human power. But "offspring" and "faith" pertain to
matrimony as directed to an office of human nature, whereas "sacrament"
pertains to it as instituted by God. Therefore sacrament takes a more
important part in marriage than the other two.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[3] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, This or that may be more important to a thing in two
ways, either because it is more essential or because it is more
excellent. If the reason is because it is more excellent, then
"sacrament" is in every way the most important of the three marriage
goods, since it belongs to marriage considered as a sacrament of grace;
while the other two belong to it as an office of nature; and a perfection
of grace is more excellent than a perfection of nature. If, however, it
is said to be more important because it is more essential, we must draw a
distinction; for "faith" and "offspring" can be considered in two ways.
First, in themselves, and thus they regard the use of matrimony in
begetting children and observing the marriage compact; while
inseparability, which is denoted by "sacrament," regards the very
sacrament considered in itself, since from the very fact that by the
marriage compact man and wife give to one another power the one over the
other in perpetuity, it follows that they cannot be put asunder. Hence
there is no matrimony without inseparability, whereas there is matrimony
without "faith" and "offspring," because the existence of a thing does
not depend on its use; and in this sense "sacrament" is more essential to
matrimony than "faith" and "offspring." Secondly, "faith" and "offspring"
may be considered as in their principles, so that "offspring" denote the
intention of having children, and "faith" the duty of remaining faithful,
and there can be no matrimony without these also, since they are caused
in matrimony by the marriage compact itself, so that if anything contrary
to these were expressed in the consent which makes a marriage, the
marriage would be invalid. Taking "faith" and "offspring" in this sense,
it is clear that "offspring" is the most essential thing in marriage,
secondly "faith," and thirdly "sacrament"; even as to man it is more
essential to be in nature than to be in grace, although it is more
excellent to be in grace.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The end as regards the intention stands first in a thing,
but as regards the attainment it stands last. It is the same with
"offspring" among the marriage goods; wherefore in a way it is the most
important and in another way it is not.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Sacrament, even as holding the third place among the
marriage goods, belongs to matrimony by reason of its difference; for it
is called "sacrament" from its signification of that particular sacred
thing which matrimony signifies.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: According to Augustine (De Bono Conjug. ix), marriage is a
good of mortals, wherefore in the resurrection "they shall neither marry
nor be married" (Mt. 22:30). Hence the marriage bond does not last after
the life wherein it is contracted, and consequently it is said to be
inseparable, because it cannot be sundered in this life, but either by
bodily death after carnal union, or by spiritual death after a merely
spiritual union.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[3] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: Although the consent which makes a marriage is not
everlasting materially, i.e. in regard to the substance of the act, since
that act ceases and a contrary act may succeed it, nevertheless formally
speaking it is everlasting, because it is a consent to an ever lasting
bond, else it would not make a marriage, for a consent to take a woman
for a time makes no marriage. Hence it is everlasting formally, inasmuch
as an act takes its species from its object; and thus it is that
matrimony derives its inseparability from the consent.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[3] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: In those sacraments wherein a character is imprinted, power
is given to perform spiritual actions; but in matrimony, to perform
bodily actions. Wherefore matrimony by reason of the power which man and
wife receive over one another agrees with the sacraments in which a
character is imprinted, and from this it derives its inseparability, as
the Master says (Sent. iv, D, 31); yet it differs from them in so far as
that power regards bodily acts; hence it does not confer a spiritual
character.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the marriage act is excused by the aforesaid goods?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the marriage act cannot be altogether excused
from sin by the aforesaid goods. For whoever allows himself to lose a
greater good for the sake of a lesser good sins because he allows it
inordinately. Now the good of reason which is prejudiced in the marriage
act is greater than these three marriage goods. Therefore the aforesaid
goods do not suffice to excuse marriage intercourse.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, if a moral good be added to a moral evil the sum total
is evil and not good, since one evil circumstance makes an action evil,
whereas one good circumstance does not make it good. Now the marriage act
is evil in itself, else it would need no excuse. Therefore the addition
of the marriage goods cannot make the act good.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[4] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, wherever there is immoderate passion there is moral
vice. Now the marriage goods cannot prevent the pleasure in that act from
being immoderate. Therefore they cannot excuse it from being a sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[4] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, according to Damascene (De Fide Orth. ii, 15), shame is
only caused by a disgraceful deed. Now the marriage goods do not deprive
that deed of its shame. Therefore they cannot excuse it from sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[4] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, The marriage act differs not from fornication except by
the marriage goods. If therefore these were not sufficient to excuse it
marriage would be always unlawful; and this is contrary to what was
stated above (Q[41], A[3]).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[4] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, the marriage goods are related to its act as its due
circumstances, as stated above (A[1], ad 4). Now the like circumstances
are sufficient to prevent an action from being evil. Therefore these
goods can excuse marriage so that it is nowise a sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[4] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, An act is said to be excused in two ways. First, on the
part of the agent, so that although it be evil it is not imputed as sin
to the agent, or at least not as so grave a sin. thus ignorance is said
to excuse a sin wholly or partly. Secondly, an act is said to be excused
on its part, so that, namely, it is not evil; and it is thus that the
aforesaid goods are said to excuse the marriage act. Now it is from the
same cause that an act is not morally evil, and that it is good, since
there is no such thing as an indifferent act, as was stated in the Second
Book (Sent. ii, D, 40; FS, Q[18], A[9]). Now a human act is said to be
good in two ways. In one way by goodness of virtue, and thus an act
derives its goodness from those things which place it in the mean. This
is what "faith" and "offspring" do in the marriage act, as stated above
(A[2]). In another way, by goodness of the "sacrament," in which way an
act is said to be not only good, but also holy, and the marriage act
derives this goodness from the indissolubility of the union, in respect
of which it signifies the union of Christ with the Church. Thus it is
clear that the aforesaid goods sufficiently excuse the marriage act.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: By the marriage act man does not incur harm to his reason
as to habit, but only as to act. Nor is it unfitting that a certain act
which is generically better be sometimes interrupted for some less good
act; for it is possible to do this without sin, as in the case of one who
ceases from the act of contemplation in order meanwhile to devote himself
to action.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: This argument would avail if the evil that is inseparable
from carnal intercourse were an evil of sin. But in this case it is an
evil not of sin but of punishment alone, consisting in the rebellion of
concupiscence against reason; and consequently the conclusion does not
follow.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[4] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: The excess of passion that amounts to a sin does not refer
to the passion's quantitative intensity, but to its proportion to reason;
wherefore it is only when a passion goes beyond the bounds of reason that
it is reckoned to be immoderate. Now the pleasure attaching to the
marriage act, while it is most intense in point of quantity, does not go
beyond the bounds previously appointed by reason before the commencement
of the act, although reason is unable to regulate them during the
pleasure itself.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[4] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: The turpitude that always accompanies the marriage act and
always causes shame is the turpitude of punishment, not of sin, for man
is naturally ashamed of any defect.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[5] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the marriage act can be excused without the marriage goods?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[5] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the marriage act can be excused even without
the marriage goods. For he who is moved by nature alone to the marriage
act, apparently does not intend any of the marriage goods, since the
marriage goods pertain to grace or virtue. Yet when a person is moved to
the aforesaid act by the natural appetite alone, seemingly he commits no
sin, for nothing natural is an evil, since "evil is contrary to nature
and order," as Dionysius says (Div. Nom. iv). Therefore the marriage act
can be excused even without the marriage goods.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[5] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, he who has intercourse with his wife in order to avoid
fornication, does not seemingly intend any of the marriage goods. Yet he
does not sin apparently, because marriage was granted to human weakness
for the very purpose of avoiding fornication (1 Cor. 7:2,6). Therefore
the marriage act can be excused even without the marriage goods.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[5] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, he who uses as he will that which is his own does not
act against justice, and thus seemingly does not sin. Now marriage makes
the wife the husband's own, and "vice versa." Therefore, if they use one
another at will through the instigation of lust, it would seem that it is
no sin; and thus the same conclusion follows.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[5] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, that which is good generically does not become evil
unless it be done with an evil intention. Now the marriage act whereby a
husband knows his wife is generically good. Therefore it cannot be evil
unless it be done with an evil intention. Now it can be done with a good
intention, even without intending any marriage good, for instance by
intending to keep or acquire bodily health. Therefore it seems that this
act can be excused even without the marriage goods.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[5] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, If the cause be removed the effect is removed. Now the
marriage goods are the cause of rectitude in the marriage act. Therefore
the marriage act cannot be excused without them.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[5] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, the aforesaid act does not differ from the act of fornication
except in the aforesaid goods. But the act of fornication is always evil.
Therefore the marriage act also will always be evil unless it be excused
by the aforesaid goods.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[5] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Just as the marriage goods, in so far as they consist in
a habit, make a marriage honest and holy, so too, in so far as they are
in the actual intention, they make the marriage act honest, as regards
those two marriage goods which relate to the marriage act. Hence when
married persons come together for the purpose of begetting children, or
of paying the debt to one another (which pertains to "faith") they are
wholly excused from sin. But the third good does not relate to the use of
marriage, but to its excuse, as stated above (A[3]); wherefore it makes
marriage itself honest, but not its act, as though its act were wholly
excused from sin, through being done on account of some signification.
Consequently there are only two ways in which married persons can come
together without any sin at all, namely in order to have offspring, and
in order to pay the debt. otherwise it is always at least a venial sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[5] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The offspring considered as a marriage good includes
something besides the offspring as a good intended by nature. For nature
intends offspring as safeguarding the good of the species, whereas the
offspring as a good of the sacrament of marriage includes besides this
the directing of the child to God. Wherefore the intention of nature
which intends the offspring must needs be referred either actually or
habitually to the intention of having an offspring, as a good of the
sacrament: otherwise the intention would go no further than a creature;
and this is always a sin. Consequently whenever nature alone moves a
person to the marriage act, he is not wholly excused from sin, except in
so far as the movement of nature is further directed actually or
habitually to the offspring as a good of the sacrament. Nor does it
follow that the instigation of nature is evil, but that it is imperfect
unless it be further directed to some marriage good.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[5] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: If a man intends by the marriage act to prevent fornication
in his wife, it is no sin, because this is a kind of payment of the debt
that comes under the good of "faith." But if he intends to avoid
fornication in himself, then there is a certain superfluity, and
accordingly there is a venial sin, nor was the sacrament instituted for
that purpose, except by indulgence, which regards venial sins.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[5] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: One due circumstance does not suffice to make a good act,
and consequently it does not follow that, no matter how one use one's own
property, the use is good, but when one uses it as one ought according to
all the circumstances.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[5] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: Although it is not evil in itself to intend to keep oneself
in good health, this intention becomes evil, if one intend health by
means of something that is not naturally ordained for that purpose; for
instance if one sought only bodily health by the sacrament of baptism,
and the same applies to the marriage act in the question at issue.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[6] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether it is a mortal sin for a man to have knowledge of his wife, with
the intention not of a marriage good but merely of pleasure?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[6] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that whenever a man has knowledge of his wife, with
the intention not of a marriage good but merely of pleasure, he commits a
mortal sin. For according to Jerome (Comment. in Eph. 5:25), as quoted in
the text (Sent. iv, D, 31), "the pleasure taken in the embraces of a
wanton is damnable in a husband." Now nothing but mortal sin is said to
be damnable. Therefore it is always a mortal sin to have knowledge of
one's wife for mere pleasure.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[6] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, consent to pleasure is a mortal sin, as stated in the
Second Book (Sent. ii, D, 24). Now whoever knows his wife for the sake of
pleasure consents to the pleasure. Therefore he sins mortally.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[6] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, whoever fails to refer the use of a creature to God
enjoys a creature, and this is a mortal sin. But whoever uses his wife
for mere pleasure does not refer that use to God. Therefore he sins
mortally.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[6] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, no one should be excommunicated except for a mortal sin.
Now according to the text (Sent. ii, D, 24) a man who knows his wife for
mere pleasure is debarred from entering the Church, as though he were
excommunicate. Therefore every such man sins mortally.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[6] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, As stated in the text (Sent. ii, D, 24), according to
Augustine (Contra Jul. ii, 10; De Decem Chord. xi; Serm. xli, de Sanct.),
carnal intercourse of this kind is one of the daily sins, for which we
say the "Our Father." Now these are not mortal sins. Therefore, etc.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[6] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, it is no mortal sin to take food for mere pleasure. Therefore
in like manner it is not a mortal sin for a man to use his wife merely to
satisfy his desire.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[6] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Some say that whenever pleasure is the chief motive for
the marriage act it is a mortal sin; that when it is an indirect motive
it is a venial sin; and that when it spurns the pleasure altogether and
is displeasing, it is wholly void of venial sin; so that it would be a
mortal sin to seek pleasure in this act, a venial sin to take the
pleasure when offered, but that perfection requires one to detest it. But
this is impossible, since according to the Philosopher (Ethic. x, 3,4)
the same judgment applies to pleasure as to action, because pleasure in a
good action is good, and in an evil action, evil; wherefore, as the
marriage act is not evil in itself, neither will it be always a mortal
sin to seek pleasure therein. Consequently the right answer to this
question is that if pleasure be sought in such a way as to exclude the
honesty of marriage, so that, to wit, it is not as a wife but as a woman
that a man treats his wife, and that he is ready to use her in the same
way if she were not his wife, it is a mortal sin; wherefore such a man is
said to be too ardent a lover of his wife, because his ardor carries him
away from the goods of marriage. If, however, he seek pleasure within the
bounds of marriage, so that it would not be sought in another than his
wife, it is a venial sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[6] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: A man seeks wanton pleasure in his wife when he sees no
more in her that he would in a wanton.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[6] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Consent to the pleasure of the intercourse that is a mortal
sin is itself a mortal sin; but such is not the consent to the marriage
act.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[6] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Although he does not actually refer the pleasure to God, he
does not place his will's last end therein; otherwise he would seek it
anywhere indifferently. Hence it does not follow that he enjoys a
creature; but he uses a creature actually for his own sake, and himself
habitually, though not actually, for God's sake.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[49] A[6] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: The reason for this statement is not that man deserves to
be excommunicated for this sin, but because he renders himself unfit for
spiritual things, since in that act, he becomes flesh and nothing more.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[50] Out. Para. 1/1
OF THE IMPEDIMENTS OF MARRIAGE, IN GENERAL (ONE ARTICLE)
In the next place we must consider the impediments of marriage: (1) In
general; (2) In particular.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[50] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether it is fitting that impediments should be assigned to marriage?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[50] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem unfitting for impediments to be assigned to
marriage. For marriage is a sacrament condivided with the others. But no
impediments are assigned to the others. Neither therefore should they be
assigned to marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[50] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the less perfect a thing is the fewer its obstacles. Now
matrimony is the least perfect of the sacraments. Therefore it should
have either no impediments or very few.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[50] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, wherever there is disease, it is necessary to have a
remedy for the disease. Now concupiscence, a remedy for which is
permitted in matrimony (1 Cor. 7:6), is in all. Therefore there should
not be any impediment making it altogether unlawful for a particular
person to marry.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[50] A[1] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, unlawful means against the law. Now these impediments
that are assigned to matrimony are not against the natural law, because
they are not found to be the same in each state of the human race, since
more degrees of kindred come under prohibition at one time than at
another. Nor, seemingly, can human law set impediments against marriage,
since marriage, like the other sacraments, is not of human but of Divine
institution. Therefore impediments should not be assigned to marriage,
making it unlawful for a person to marry.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[50] A[1] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, lawful and unlawful differ as that which is against the
law from that which is not, and between these there is no middle term,
since they are opposed according to affirmation and negation. Therefore
there cannot be impediments to marriage, placing a person in a middle
position between those who are lawful and those who are unlawful subjects
of marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[50] A[1] Obj. 6 Para. 1/1
OBJ 6: Further, union of man and woman is unlawful save in marriage. Now
every unlawful union should be dissolved. Therefore if anything prevent a
marriage being contracted, it will "de facto" dissolve it after it has
been contracted; and thus impediments should not be assigned to marriage,
which hinder it from being contracted, and dissolve it after it has been
contracted.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[50] A[1] Obj. 7 Para. 1/1
OBJ 7: Further, no impediment can remove from a thing that which is part
of its definition. Now indissolubility is part of the definition of
marriage. Therefore there cannot be any impediments which annul a
marriage already contracted.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[50] A[1] Obj. 8 Para. 1/1
OBJ 8: On the other hand, it would seem that there should be an infinite
number of impediments to marriage. For marriage is a good. Now good may
be lacking in an infinite number of ways, as Dionysius says (Div. Nom.
iii). Therefore there is an infinite number of impediments to marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[50] A[1] Obj. 9 Para. 1/1
OBJ 9: Further, the impediments to marriage arise from the conditions of
individuals. But such like conditions are infinite in number. Therefore
the impediments to marriage are also infinite.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[50] A[1] Body Para. 1/4
I answer that, In marriage, as in other sacraments, there are certain
things essential to marriage, and others that belong to its
solemnization. And since even without the things that pertain to its
solemnization it is still a true sacrament, as also in the case of the
other sacraments, it follows that the impediments to those things that
pertain to the solemnization of this sacrament do not derogate from the
validity of the marriage. These impediments are said to hinder the
contracting of marriage, but they do not dissolve the marriage once
contracted; such are the veto of the Church, or the holy seasons. Hence
the verse:
"The veto of the Church and holy tide
Forbid the knot, but loose it not if tied."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[50] A[1] Body Para. 2/4
On the other hand, those impediments which regard the essentials of
marriage make a marriage invalid, wherefore they are said not only to
hinder the contracting of marriage, but to dissolve it if contracted; and
they are contained in the following verse:
"Error, station, vow, kinship, crime,
Difference of worship, force, holy orders,
Marriage bond, honesty, affinity, impotence,
All these forbid marriage, and annul it though
contracted."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[50] A[1] Body Para. 3/4
The reason for this number may be explained as follows: Marriage may be
hindered either on the part of the contract or in regard to the
contracting parties. If in the first way, since the marriage contract is
made by voluntary consent, and this is incompatible with either ignorance
or violence, there will be two impediments to marriage, namely "force,"
i.e. compulsion, and "error" in reference to ignorance. Wherefore the
Master pronounced on these two impediments when treating of the cause of
matrimony (Sent. iv, DD 29,30). Here, however, he is treating of the
impediments as arising from the contracting parties, and these may be
differentiated as follows. A person may be hindered from contracting
marriage either simply, or with some particular person. If simply, so
that he be unable to contract marriage with any woman, this can only be
because he is hindered from performing the marriage act. This happens in
two ways. First, because he cannot "de facto," either through being
altogether unable---and thus we have the impediment of "impotence"---or
through being unable to do so freely, and thus we have the impediment of
the "condition of slavery." Secondly, because he cannot do it lawfully,
and this because he is bound to continence, which happens in two ways,
either through his being bound on account of the office he has undertaken
to fulfill---and thus we have the impediment of "Order"---or on account
of his having taken a vow---and thus "Vow" is an impediment.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[50] A[1] Body Para. 4/4
If, however, a person is hindered from marrying, not simply but in
reference to a particular person, this is either because he is bound to
another person, and thus he who is married to one cannot marry another,
which constitutes the impediment of the "bond of marriage"---or through
lack of proportion to the other party, and this for three reasons. First,
on account of too great a distance separating them, and thus we have
"difference of worship"; secondly, on account of their being too closely
related, and thus we have three impediments, namely "kinship," then
"affinity," which denotes the close relationship between two persons, in
reference to a third united to one of them by marriage, and the "justice
of public honesty," where we have a close relationship between two
persons arising out of the betrothal of one of them to a third person;
thirdly, on account of a previous undue union between him and the woman,
and thus the "crime of adultery" previously committed with her is an
impediment.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[50] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: There may be impediments to the other sacraments also in
the omission either of that which is essential, or of that which pertains
to the solemnization of the sacrament, as stated above. However,
impediments are assigned to matrimony rather than to the other sacraments
for three reasons. First, because matrimony consists of two persons, and
consequently can be impeded in more ways than the other sacraments which
refer to one person taken individually; secondly, because matrimony has
its cause in us and in God, while some of the other sacraments have their
cause in God alone. Wherefore penance which in a manner has a cause in
us, is assigned certain impediments by the Master (Sent. iv, D, 16), such
as hypocrisy, the public games, and so forth; thirdly, because other
sacraments are objects of command or counsel, as being more perfect
goods, whereas marriage is a matter of indulgence, as being a less
perfect good (1 Cor. 7:6). Wherefore, in order to afford an opportunity
of proficiency towards a greater good, more impediments are assigned to
matrimony than to the other sacraments.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[50] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The more perfect things can be hindered in more ways, in so
far as more conditions are required for them. And if an imperfect thing
requires more conditions, there will be more impediments to it; and thus
it is in matrimony.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[50] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: This argument would hold, were there no other and more
efficacious remedies for the disease of concupiscence; which is false.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[50] A[1] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: Persons are said to be unlawful subjects for marriage
through being contrary to the law whereby marriage is established. Now
marriage as fulfilling an office of nature is established by the natural
law; as a sacrament, by the Divine law; as fulfilling an office of
society, by the civil law. Consequently a person may be rendered an
unlawful subject of marriage by any of the aforesaid laws. Nor does the
comparison with the other sacraments hold, for they are sacraments only.
And since the natural law is particularized in various ways according to
the various states of mankind, and since positive law, too, varies
according to the various conditions of men, the Master (Sent. iv, D, 34)
asserts that at various times various persons have been unlawful subjects
of marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[50] A[1] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: The law may forbid a thing either altogether, or in part
and in certain cases. Hence between that which is altogether according to
the law and that which is altogether against the law (which are opposed
by contrariety and not according to affirmation and negation), that which
is somewhat according to the law and somewhat against the law is a middle
term. For this reason certain persons hold a middle place between those
who are simply lawful subjects and those who are simply unlawful.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[50] A[1] R.O. 6 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 6: Those impediments which do not annul a marriage already
contracted sometimes hinder a marriage from being contracted, by
rendering it not invalid but unlawful. And if it be contracted it is a
true marriage although the contracting parties sin; just as by
consecrating after breaking one's fast one would sin by disobeying the
Church's ordinance, and yet it would be a valid sacrament because it is
not essential to the sacrament that the consecrator be fasting.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[50] A[1] R.O. 7 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 7: When we say that the aforesaid impediments annul marriage
already contracted, we do not mean that they dissolve a marriage
contracted in due form, but that they dissolve a marriage contracted "de
facto" and not "de jure." Wherefore if an impediment supervene after a
marriage has been contracted in due form, it cannot dissolve the marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[50] A[1] R.O. 8 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 8: The impediments that hinder a good accidentally are
infinite in number, like all accidental causes. But the causes which of
their own nature corrupt a certain good are directed to that effect, and
determinate, even as are the causes which produce that good; for the
causes by which a thing is destroyed and those by which it is made are
either contrary to one another, or the same but taken in a contrary way.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[50] A[1] R.O. 9 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 9: The conditions of particular persons taken individually are
infinite in number, but taken in general, they may be reduced to a
certain number; as instanced in medicine and all operative arts, which
consider the conditions of particular persons in whom acts are.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[51] Out. Para. 1/1
OF THE IMPEDIMENT OF ERROR (TWO ARTICLES)
We must now consider the impediments to matrimony in particular, and in
the first place the impediment of error. Under this head there are two
points of inquiry:
(1) Whether error of its very nature is an impediment to matrimony?
(2) What kind of error?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[51] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether it is right to reckon error as an impediment to marriage?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[51] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that error should not be reckoned in itself an
impediment to marriage. For consent, which is the efficient cause of
marriage, is hindered in the same way as the voluntary. Now the
voluntary, according to the Philosopher (Ethic. iii, 1), may be hindered
by ignorance. But ignorance is not the same as error, because ignorance
excludes knowledge altogether, whereas error does not, since "error is to
approve the false as though it were true," according to Augustine (De
Trin. ix, 11). Therefore ignorance rather than error should have been
reckoned here as an impediment to marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[51] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, that which of its very nature can be an impediment to
marriage is in opposition to the good of marriage. But error is not a
thing of this kind. Therefore error is not by its very nature an
impediment to marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[51] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, just as consent is required for marriage, so is
intention required for baptism. Now if one were to baptize John, thinking
to baptize Peter, John would be baptized none the less. Therefore error
does not annul matrimony.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[51] A[1] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, there was true marriage between Lia and Jacob, and yet,
in this case, there was error. Therefore error does not annul a marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[51] A[1] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, It is said in the Digests (Si per errorem, ff. De
jurisdic. omn. judic.): "What is more opposed to consent than error?" Now
consent is required for marriage. Therefore error is an impediment to
matrimony.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[51] A[1] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, consent denotes something voluntary. Now error is an obstacle
to the voluntary, since "the voluntary," according to the Philosopher
(Ethic. iii, 1), Damascene (De Fide Orth. ii, 24), and Gregory of Nyssa
[*Nemesius] (De Nat. Hom. xxxii), "is that which has its principle in one
who has knowledge of singulars which are the matter of actions." But this
does not apply to one who is in error. Therefore error is an impediment
to matrimony.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[51] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Whatever hinders a cause, of its very nature hinders the
effect likewise. Now consent is the cause of matrimony, as stated above
(Q[45], A[1]). Hence whatever voids the consent, voids marriage. Now
consent is an act of the will, presupposing an act of the intellect; and
if the first be lacking, the second must needs be lacking also. Hence,
when error hinders knowledge, there follows a defect in the consent also,
and consequently in the marriage. Therefore it is possible according to
the natural law for error to void marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[51] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Speaking simply, ignorance differs from error, because
ignorance does not of its very nature imply an act of knowledge, while
error supposes a wrong judgment of reason about something. However, as
regards being an impediment to the voluntary, it differs not whether we
call it ignorance or error, since no ignorance can be an impediment to
the voluntary, unless it have error in conjunction with it, because the
will's act presupposes an estimate or judgment about something which is
the object of the will. Wherefore if there be ignorance there must needs
be error; and for this reason error is set down as being the proximate
cause.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[51] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Although error is not of itself contrary to matrimony, it
is contrary thereto as regards the cause of marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[51] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: The character of baptism is not caused directly by the
intention of the baptizer, but by the material element applied outwardly;
and the intention is effective only as directing the material element to
its effect; whereas the marriage tie is caused by the consent directly.
Hence the comparison fails.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[51] A[1] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: According to the Master (Sent. iv, D, 30) the marriage
between Lia and Jacob was effected not by their coming together, which
happened through an error, but by their consent, which followed
afterwards. Yet both are clearly to be excused from sin (Sent. iv, D, 30).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[51] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether every error is an impediment to matrimony?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[51] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that every error is an impediment to matrimony, and
not, as stated in the text (Sent. iv, D, 30), only error about the
condition or the person. For that which applies to a thing as such
applies to it in all its bearings. Now error is of its very nature an
impediment to matrimony, as stated above (A[1]). Therefore every error is
an impediment to matrimony.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[51] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, if error, as such, is an impediment to matrimony, the
greater the error the greater the impediment. Now the error concerning
faith in a heretic who disbelieves in this sacrament is greater than an
error concerning the person. Therefore it should be a greater impediment
than error about the person.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[51] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, error does not void marriage except as removing
voluntariness. Now ignorance about any circumstance takes away
voluntariness (Ethic. iii, 1). Therefore it is not only error about
condition or person that is an impediment to matrimony.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[51] A[2] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, just as the condition of slavery is an accident
affecting the person, so are bodily or mental qualities. But error
regarding the condition is an impediment to matrimony. Therefore error
concerning quality or fortune is equally an impediment.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[51] A[2] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, just as slavery or freedom pertains to the condition of
person, so do high and low rank, or dignity of position and the lack
thereof. Now error regarding the condition of slavery is an impediment to
matrimony. Therefore error about the other matters mentioned is also an
impediment.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[51] A[2] Obj. 6 Para. 1/1
OBJ 6: Further, just as the condition of slavery is an impediment, so
are difference of worship and impotence, as we shall say further on
(Q[52], A[2]; Q[58], A[1]; Q[59], A[1]). Therefore just as error
regarding the condition is an impediment, so also should error about
those other matters be reckoned an impediment.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[51] A[2] Obj. 7 Para. 1/1
OBJ 7: On the other hand, it would seem that not even error about the
person is an impediment to marriage. For marriage is a contract even as a
sale is. Now in buying and selling the sale is not voided if one coin be
given instead of another of equal value. Therefore a marriage is not
voided if one woman be taken instead of another.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[51] A[2] Obj. 8 Para. 1/1
OBJ 8: Further, it is possible for them to remain in this error for many
years and to beget between them sons and daughters. But it would be a
grave assertion to maintain that they ought to be separated then.
Therefore their previous error did not void their marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[51] A[2] Obj. 9 Para. 1/1
OBJ 9: Further, it might happen that the woman is betrothed to the
brother of the man whom she thinks that she is consenting to marry, and
that she has had carnal intercourse with him; in which case, seemingly,
she cannot go back to the man to whom she thought to give her consent,
but should hold on to his brother. Thus error regarding the person is not
an impediment to marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[51] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Just as error, through causing involuntariness, is an
excuse from sin, so on the same count is it an impediment to marriage.
Now error does not excuse from sin unless it refer to a circumstance the
presence or absence of which makes an action lawful or unlawful. For if a
man were to strike his father with an iron rod thinking it to be of wood,
he is not excused from sin wholly, although perhaps in part; but if a man
were to strike his father, thinking to strike his son to correct him, he
is wholly excused provided he take due care. Wherefore error, in order to
void marriage, must needs be about the essentials of marriage. Now
marriage includes two things, namely the two persons who are joined
together, and the mutual power over one another wherein marriage
consists. The first of these is removed by error concerning the person,
the second by error regarding the condition, since a slave cannot freely
give power over his body to another, without his master's consent. For
this reason these two errors, and no others, are an impediment to
matrimony.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[51] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: It is not from its generic nature that error is an
impediment to marriage, but from the nature of the difference added
thereto; namely from its being error about one of the essentials to
marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[51] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: An error of faith about matrimony is about things
consequent upon matrimony, for instance on the question of its being a
sacrament, or of its being lawful. Wherefore such error as these is no
impediment to marriage, as neither does an error about baptism hinder a
man from receiving the character, provided he intend to receive what the
Church gives, although he believe it to be nothing.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[51] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: It is not any ignorance of a circumstance that causes the
involuntariness which is an excuse from sin, as stated above; wherefore
the argument does not prove.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[51] A[2] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: Difference of fortune or of quality does not make a
difference in the essentials to matrimony, as the condition of slavery
does. Hence the argument does not prove.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[51] A[2] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: Error about a person's rank, as such, does not void a
marriage, for the same reason as neither does error about a personal
quality. If, however, the error about a person's rank or position amounts
to an error about the person, it is an impediment to matrimony. Hence, if
the woman consent directly to this particular person, her error about
his rank does not void the marriage; but if she intend directly to
consent to marry the king's son, whoever he may be, then, if another man
than the king's son be brought to her, there is error about the person,
and the marriage will be void.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[51] A[2] R.O. 6 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 6: Error is an impediment to matrimony, although it be about
other impediments to marriage if it concern those things which render a
person an unlawful subject of marriage. But (the Master) does not mention
error about such things, because they are an impediment to marriage
whether there be error about them or not; so that if a woman contract
with a subdeacon, whether she know this or not, there is no marriage;
whereas the condition of slavery is no impediment if the slavery be
known. Hence the comparison fails.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[51] A[2] R.O. 7 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 7: In contracts money is regarded as the measure of other
things (Ethic. v, 5), and not as being sought for its own sake. Hence if
the coin paid is not what it is thought to be but another of equal value,
this does not void the contract. But if there be error about a thing
sought for its own sake, the contract is voided, for instance if one were
to sell a donkey for a horse; and thus it is in the case in point.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[51] A[2] R.O. 8 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 8: No matter how long they have cohabited, unless she be
willing to consent again, there is no marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[51] A[2] R.O. 9 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 9: If she did not consent previously to marry his brother, she
may hold to the one whom she took in error. Nor can she return to his
brother, especially if there has been carnal intercourse between her and
the man she took to husband. If, however, she had previously consented to
take the first one in words of the present, she cannot have the second
while the first lives. But she may either leave the second or return to
the first; and ignorance of the fact excuses her from sin, just as she
would be excused if after the consummation of the marriage a kinsman of
her husband were to know her by fraud since she is not to be blamed for
the other's deceit.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] Out. Para. 1/1
OF THE IMPEDIMENT OF THE CONDITION OF SLAVERY (FOUR ARTICLES)
We must now consider the impediment of the condition of slavery. Under
this head there are four points of inquiry:
(1) Whether the condition of slavery is an impediment to matrimony?
(2) Whether a slave can marry without his master's consent?
(3) Whether a man who is already married can make himself a slave
without his wife's consent?
(4) Whether the children should follow the condition of their father or
of their mother?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the condition of slavery is an impediment to matrimony?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the condition of slavery is no impediment to
matrimony. For nothing is an impediment to marriage except what is in
some way opposed to it. But slavery is in no way opposed to marriage,
else there could be no marriage among slaves. Therefore slavery is no
impediment to marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, that which is contrary to nature cannot be an impediment
to that which is according to nature. Now slavery is contrary to nature,
for as Gregory says (Pastor. ii, 6), "it is contrary to nature for man to
wish to lord it over another man"; and this is also evident from the fact
that it was said of man (Gn. 1:26) that he should "have dominion over the
fishes of the sea," but not that he should have dominion over man.
Therefore it cannot be an impediment to marriage, which is a natural
thing.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, if it is an impediment, this is either of natural law or
of positive law. But it is not of natural law, since according to natural
law all men are equal, as Gregory says (Pastor. ii, 6), while it is
stated at the beginning of the Digests (Manumissiones, ff. de just. et
jure.) that slavery is not of natural law; and positive law springs from
the natural law, as Tully says (De Invent. ii). Therefore, according to
law, slavery is not an impediment to any marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[1] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, that which is an impediment to marriage is equally an
impediment whether it be known or not, as in the case of consanguinity.
Now the slavery of one party, if it be known to the other, is no
impediment to their marriage. Therefore slavery, considered in itself, is
unable to void a marriage; and consequently it should not be reckoned by
itself as a distinct impediment to marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[1] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, just as one may be in error about slavery, so as to deem
a person free who is a slave, so may one be in error about freedom, so as
to deem a person a slave whereas he is free. But freedom is not accounted
an impediment to matrimony. Therefore neither should slavery be so
accounted.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[1] Obj. 7 Para. 1/1
OBJ 7: Further, leprosy is a greater burden to the fellowship of
marriage and is a greater obstacle to the good of the offspring than
slavery is. Yet leprosy is not reckoned an impediment to marriage.
Therefore neither should slavery be so reckoned.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[1] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, A Decretal says (De conjug. servorum, cap. Ad nostram)
that "error regarding the condition hinders a marriage from being
contracted and voids that which is already contracted."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[1] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, marriage is one of the goods that are sought for their own
sake, because it is qualified by honesty; whereas slavery is one of the
things to be avoided for their own sake. Therefore marriage and slavery
are contrary to one another; and consequently slavery is an impediment to
matrimony.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, In the marriage contract one party is bound to the other
in the matter of paying the debt; wherefore if one who thus binds
himself is unable to pay the debt, ignorance of this inability, on the
side of the party to whom he binds himself, voids the contract. Now just
as impotence in respect of coition makes a person unable to pay the debt,
so that he is altogether disabled, so slavery makes him unable to pay it
freely. Therefore, just as ignorance or impotence in respect of coition
is an impediment if not known but not if known, as we shall state further
on (Q[58]), so the condition of slavery is an impediment if not known,
but not if it be known.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Slavery is contrary to marriage as regards the act to which
marriage binds one party in relation to the other, because it prevents
the free execution of that act; and again as regards the good of the
offspring who become subject to the same condition by reason of the
parent's slavery. Since, however, it is free to everyone to suffer
detriment in that which is his due, if one of the parties knows the other
to be a slave, the marriage is none the less valid. Likewise since in
marriage there is an equal obligation on either side to pay the debt,
neither party can exact of the other a greater obligation than that under
which he lies; so that if a slave marry a bondswoman, thinking her to be
free, the marriage is not thereby rendered invalid. It is therefore
evident that slavery is no impediment to marriage except when it is
unknown to the other party, even though the latter be in a condition of
freedom; and so nothing prevents marriage between slaves, or even between
a freeman and a bondswoman.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Nothing prevents a thing being against nature as to the
first intention of nature, and yet not against nature as to its second
intention. Thus, as stated in De Coelo, ii, all corruption, defect, and
old age are contrary to nature, because nature intends being and
perfection, and yet they are not contrary to the second intention of
nature, because nature, through being unable to preserve being in one
thing, preserves it in another which is engendered of the other's
corruption. And when nature is unable to bring a thing to a greater
perfection it brings it to a lesser; thus when it cannot produce a male
it produces a female which is "a misbegotten male" (De Gener. Animal. ii,
3). I say then in like manner that slavery is contrary to the first
intention of nature. Yet it is not contrary to the second, because
natural reason has this inclination, and nature has this desire---that
everyone should be good; but from the fact that a person sins, nature has
an inclination that he should be punished for his sin, and thus slavery
was brought in as a punishment of sin. Nor is it unreasonable for a
natural thing to be hindered by that which is unnatural in this way; for
thus is marriage hindered by impotence of coition, which impotence is
contrary to nature in the way mentioned.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: The natural law requires punishment to be inflicted for
guilt, and that no one should be punished who is not guilty; but the
appointing of the punishment according to the circumstances of person and
guilt belongs to positive law. Hence slavery which is a definite
punishment is of positive law, and arises out of natural law, as the
determinate from that which is indeterminate. And it arises from the
determination of the same positive law that slavery if unknown is an
impediment to matrimony, lest one who is not guilty be punished; for it
is a punishment to the wife to have a slave for husband, and "vice versa."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[1] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: Certain impediments render a marriage unlawful; and since
it is not our will that makes a thing lawful or unlawful, but the law to
which our will ought to be subject, it follows that the validity or
invalidity of a marriage is not affected either by ignorance (such as
destroys voluntariness) of the impediment or by knowledge thereof; and
such an impediment is affinity or a vow, and others of the same kind.
other impediments, however, render a marriage ineffectual as to the
payment of the debt; and since it is within the competency of our will to
remit a debt that is due to us, it follows that such impediments, if
known, do not invalidate a marriage, but only when ignorance of them
destroys voluntariness. Such impediments are slavery and impotence of
coition. And, because they have of themselves the nature of an
impediment, they are reckoned as special impediments besides error;
whereas a change of person is not reckoned a special impediment besides
error, because the substitution of another person has not the nature of
an impediment except by reason of the intention of one of the contracting
parties.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[1] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: Freedom does not hinder the marriage act, wherefore
ignorance of freedom is no impediment to matrimony.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[1] R.O. 6 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 6: Leprosy does not hinder marriage as to its first act, since
lepers can pay the debt freely; although they lay a burden upon marriage
as to its secondary effects; wherefore it is not an impediment to
marriage as slavery is.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether a slave can marry without his master's consent?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that a slave cannot marry without his master's
consent. For no one can give a person that which is another's without the
latter's consent. Now a slave is his master's chattel. Therefore he
cannot give his wife power over his body by marrying without his master's
consent.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, a slave is bound to obey his master. But his master may
command him not to consent to marry. Therefore he cannot marry without
his consent.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, after marriage, a slave is bound even by a precept of
the Divine law to pay the debt to his wife. But at the time that his wife
asks for the debt his master may demand of him a service which he will be
unable to perform if he wish to occupy himself in carnal intercourse.
Therefore if a slave can marry without his master's consent, the latter
would be deprived of a service due to him without any fault of his; and
this ought not to be.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[2] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, a master may sell his slave into a foreign country,
where the latter's wife is unable to follow him, through either bodily
weakness, or imminent danger to her faith; for instance if he be sold to
unbelievers, or if her master be unwilling, supposing her to be a
bondswoman; and thus the marriage will be dissolved, which is unfitting.
Therefore a slave cannot marry without his master's consent.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[2] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, the burden under which a man binds himself to the Divine
service is more advantageous than that whereby a man subjects himself to
his wife. But a slave cannot enter religion or receive orders without his
master's consent. Much less therefore can he be married without his
consent.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[2] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, "In Christ Jesus . . . there is neither bond nor free"
(Gal. 3:26,28). Therefore both freeman and bondsman enjoy the same
liberty to marry in the faith of Christ Jesus.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[2] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, slavery is of positive law; whereas marriage is of natural and
Divine law. Since then positive law is not prejudicial to the natural or
the Divine law, it would seem that a slave can marry without his master's
consent.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, As stated above (A[1], ad 3), the positive law arises out
of the natural law, and consequently slavery, which is of positive law,
cannot be prejudicious to those things that are of natural law. Now just
as nature seeks the preservation of the individual, so does it seek the
preservation of the species by means of procreation; wherefore even as a
slave is not so subject to his master as not to be at liberty to eat,
sleep, and do such things as pertain to the needs of his body, and
without which nature cannot be preserved, so he is not subject to him to
the extent of being unable to marry freely, even without his master's
knowledge or consent.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: A slave is his master's chattel in matters superadded to
nature, but in natural things all are equal. Wherefore, in things
pertaining to natural acts, a slave can by marrying give another person
power over his body without his master's consent.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: A slave is bound to obey his master in those things which
his master can command lawfully; and just as his master cannot lawfully
command him not to eat or sleep, so neither can he lawfully command him
to refrain from marrying. For it is the concern of the lawgiver how each
one uses his own, and consequently if the master command his slave not to
marry, the slave is not bound to obey his master.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: If a slave has married with his master's consent, he should
omit the service commanded by his master and pay the debt to his wife;
because the master, by consenting to his slave's marriage, implicitly
consented to all that marriage requires. If, however, the marriage was
contracted without the master's knowledge or consent, he is not bound to
pay the debt, but in preference to obey his master, if the two things are
incompatible. Nevertheless in such matters there are many particulars to
be considered, as in all human acts, namely the danger to which his
wife's chastity is exposed, and the obstacle which the payment of the
debt places in the way of the service commanded, and other like
considerations, all of which being duly weighed it will be possible to
judge which of the two in preference the slave is bound to obey, his
master or his wife.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[2] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: In such a case it is said that the master should be
compelled not to sell the slave in such a way as to increase the weight
of the marriage burden, especially since he is able to obtain anywhere a
just price for his slave.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[2] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: By entering religion or receiving orders a man is bound to
the Divine service for all time; whereas a husband is bound to pay the
debt to his wife not always, but at a fitting time; hence the comparison
fails. Moreover, he who enters religion or receives orders binds himself
to works that are superadded to natural works, and in which his master
has power over him, but not in natural works to which a man binds himself
by marriage. Hence he cannot vow continence without his master's consent.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether slavery can supervene to marriage?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that slavery cannot supervene to marriage, by the
husband selling himself to another as slave. Because what is done by
fraud and to another's detriment should not hold. But a husband who sells
himself for a slave, does so sometimes to cheat marriage, and at least to
the detriment of his wife. Therefore such a sale should not hold as to
the effect of slavery.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, two favorable things outweigh one that is not favorable.
Now marriage and freedom are favorable things and are contrary to
slavery, which in law is not a favorable thing. Therefore such a slavery
ought to be entirely annulled in marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, in marriage husband and wife are on a par with one
another. Now the wife cannot surrender herself to be a slave without her
husband's consent. Therefore neither can the husband without his wife's
consent.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[3] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, in natural things that which hinders a thing being
generated destroys it after it has been generated. Now bondage of the
husband, if unknown to the wife, is an impediment to the act of marriage
before it is performed. Therefore if it could supervene to marriage it
would dissolve it; which is unreasonable.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[3] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, Everyone can give another that which is his own. Now
the husband is his own master since he is free. Therefore he can
surrender his right to another.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[3] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, a slave can marry without his master's consent, as stated above
(A[2]). Therefore a husband can in like manner subject himself to a
master, without his wife's consent.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[3] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, A husband is subject to his wife in those things which
pertain to the act of nature; in these things they are equal, and the
subjection of slavery does not extend thereto. Wherefore the husband,
without his wife's knowledge, can surrender himself to be another's
slave. Nor does this result in a dissolution of the marriage, since no
impediment supervening to marriage can dissolve it, as stated above
(Q[50], A[1], ad 7).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The fraud can indeed hurt the person who has acted
fraudulently, but it cannot be prejudicial to another person: wherefore
if the husband, to cheat his wife, surrender himself to be another's
slave, It will be to his own prejudice, through his losing the
inestimable good of freedom; whereas this can nowise be prejudicial to
the wife, and he is bound to pay her the debt when she asks, and to do
all that marriage requires of him for he cannot be taken away from these
obligations by his master's command.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: In so far as slavery is opposed to marriage, marriage is
prejudicial to slavery, since the slave is bound then to pay the debt to
his wife, though his master be unwilling.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Although husband and wife are considered to be on a par in
the marriage act and in things relating to nature, to which the condition
of slavery does not extend, nevertheless as regards the management of the
household, and other such additional matters the husband is the head of
the wife and should correct her, and not "vice versa." Hence the wife
cannot surrender herself to be a slave without her husband's consent.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[3] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: This argument considers corruptible things; and yet even in
these there are many obstacles to generation that are not capable of
destroying what is already generated. But in things which have stability
it is possible to have an impediment which prevents a certain thing from
beginning to be, yet does not cause it to cease to be; as instanced by
the rational soul. It is the same with marriage, which is a lasting tie
so long as this life lasts.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether children should follow the condition of their father?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that children should follow the condition of their
father. Because dominion belongs to those of higher rank. Now in
generating the father ranks above the mother. Therefore, etc.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the being of a thing depends on the form more than on
the matter. Now in generation the father gives the form, and the mother
the matter (De Gener. Animal. ii, 4). Therefore the child should follow
the condition of the father rather than of the mother.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[4] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, a thing should follow that chiefly to which it is most
like. Now the son is more like the father than the mother, even as the
daughter is more like the mother. Therefore at least the son should
follow the father in preference, and the daughter the mother.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[4] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, in Holy Writ genealogies are not traced through the
women but through the men. Therefore the children follow the father
rather than the mother.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[4] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, If a man sows on another's land, the produce belongs to
the owner of the land. Now the woman's womb in relation to the seed of
man is like the land in relation to the sower. Therefore, etc.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[4] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, we observe that in animals born from different species the
offspring follows the mother rather that the father, wherefore mules born
of a mare and an ass are more like mares than those born of a she-ass and
a horse. Therefore it should be the same with men.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[4] Body Para. 1/2
I answer that, According to civil law (XIX, ff. De statu hom. vii, cap.
De rei vendit.) the offspring follows the womb: and this is reasonable
since the offspring derives its formal complement from the father, but
the substance of the body from the mother. Now slavery is a condition of
the body, since a slave is to the master a kind of instrument in working;
wherefore children follow the mother in freedom and bondage; whereas in
matters pertaining to dignity as proceeding from a thing's form, they
follow the father, for instance in honors, franchise, inheritance and so
forth. The canons are in agreement with this (cap. Liberi, 32, qu. iv, in
gloss.: cap. Inducens, De natis ex libero ventre) as also the law of
Moses (Ex. 21).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[4] Body Para. 2/2
In some countries, however, where the civil law does not hold, the
offspring follows the inferior condition, so that if the father be a
slave the children will be slaves although the mother be free; but not if
the father gave himself up as a slave after his marriage and without his
wife's consent; and the same applies if the case be reversed. And if both
be of servile condition and belong to different masters, the children, if
several, are divided among the latter, or if one only, the one master
will compensate the other in value and will take the child thus born for
his slave. However it is incredible that this custom have as much reason
in its favor as the decision of the time-honored deliberations of many
wise men. Moreover in natural things it is the rule that what is received
is in the recipient according to the mode of the recipient and not
according to the mode of the giver; wherefore it is reasonable that the
seed received by the mother should be drawn to her condition.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Although the father is a more noble principle than the
mother, nevertheless the mother provides the substance of the body, and
it is to this that the condition of slavery attaches.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: As regards things pertaining to the specific nature the son
is like the father rather than the mother, but in material conditions
should be like the mother rather than the father, since a thing has its
specific being from its form, but material conditions from matter.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[4] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: The son is like the father in respect of the form which is
his, and also the father's, complement. Hence the argument is not to the
point.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[52] A[4] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: It is because the son derives honor from his father rather
than from his mother that in the genealogies of Scripture, and according
to common custom, children are named after their father rather than from
their mother. But in matters relating to slavery they follow the mother
by preference.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] Out. Para. 1/1
OF THE IMPEDIMENT OF VOWS AND ORDERS (FOUR ARTICLES)
We must now consider the impediment of vows and orders. Under this head
there are four points of inquiry:
(1) Whether a simple vow is a diriment impediment to matrimony?
(2) Whether a solemn vow is a diriment impediment?
(3) Whether order is an impediment to matrimony?
(4) Whether a man can receive a sacred order after being married?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether marriage already contracted should be annulled by the obligation
of a simple vow?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that a marriage already contracted ought to be
annulled by the obligation of a simple vow. For the stronger tie takes
precedence of the weaker. Now a vow is a stronger tie than marriage,
since the latter binds man to man, but the former binds man to God.
Therefore the obligation of a vow takes precedence of the marriage tie.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, God's commandment is no less binding than the
commandment of the Church. Now the commandment of the Church is so
binding that a marriage is void if contracted in despite thereof; as
instanced in the case of those who marry within the degrees of kindred
forbidden by the Church. Therefore, since it is a Divine commandment to
keep a vow, it would seem that if a person marry in despite of a vow his
marriage should be annulled for that reason.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, in marriage a man may have carnal intercourse without
sin. Yet he who has taken a simple vow of chastity can never have carnal
intercourse with his wife without sin. Therefore a simple vow annuls
marriage. The minor is proved as follows. It is clear that it is a
mortal sin to marry after taking a simple vow of continence, since
according to Jerome [*Cf. St. Augustine, De Bono Viduit, ix] "for those
who vow virginity it is damnable not only to marry, but even to wish to
marry." Now the marriage contract is not contrary to the vow of
continence, except by reason of carnal intercourse: and therefore he sins
mortally the first time he has intercourse with his wife, and for the
same reason every other time, because a sin committed in the first
instance cannot be an excuse for a subsequent sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[1] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, husband and wife should be equal in marriage, especially
as regards carnal intercourse. But he who has taken a simple vow of
continence can never ask for the debt without a sin, for this is clearly
against his vow of continence, since he is bound to continence by vow.
Therefore neither can he pay the debt without sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[1] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, Pope Clement [*Alexander III] says (cap. Consuluit, De
his qui cler. vel vovent.) that a "simple vow is an impediment to the
contract of marriage, but does not annul it after it is contracted."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, A thing ceases to be in one man's power from the fact
that it passes into the power of another. Now the promise of a thing does
not transfer it into the power of the person to whom it is promised,
wherefore a thing does not cease to be in a person's power for the reason
that he has promised it. Since then a simple vow contains merely a simple
promise of one's body to the effect of keeping continence for God's sake,
a man still retains power over his own body after a simple vow, and
consequently can surrender it to another, namely his wife; and in this
surrender consists the sacrament of matrimony, which is indissoluble.
Therefore although a simple vow is an impediment to the contracting of a
marriage, since it is a sin to marry after taking a simple vow of
continence, yet since the contract is valid, the marriage cannot be
annulled on that account.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: A vow is a stronger tie than matrimony, as regards that to
which man is tied, and the obligation under which he lies. because by
marriage a man is tied to his wife, with the obligation of paying the
debt, whereas by a vow a man is tied to God, with the obligation of
remaining continent. But as to the manner in which he is tied marriage is
a stronger tie than a simple vow, since by marriage a man surrenders
himself actually to the power of his wife, but not by a simple vow as
explained above: and the possessor is always in the stronger position. In
this respect a simple vow binds in the same way as a betrothal; wherefore
a betrothal must be annulled on account of a simple vow.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The contracting of a marriage between blood relations is
annulled by the commandment forbidding such marriages, not precisely
because it is a commandment of God or of the Church, but because it makes
it impossible for the body of a kinswoman to be transferred into the
power of her kinsman: whereas the commandment forbidding marriage after
a simple vow has not this effect, as already stated. Hence the argument
is void for it assigns as a cause that which is not cause.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: If after taking a simple vow a man contract marriage by
words of the present, he cannot know his wife without mortal sin, because
until the marriage is consummated he is still in a position to fulfill
the vow of continence. But after the marriage has been consummated,
thenceforth through his fault it is unlawful for him not to pay the debt
when his wife asks: wherefore this is not covered by his obligation to
his vow, as explained above (ad 1). Nevertheless he should atone for not
keeping continence, by his tears of repentance.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[1] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: After contracting marriage he is still bound to keep his
vow of continence in those matters wherein he is not rendered unable to
do so. Hence if his wife die he is bound to continence altogether. And
since the marriage tie does not bind him to ask for the debt, he cannot
ask for it without sin, although he can pay the debt without sin on being
asked, when once he has incurred this obligation through the carnal
intercourse that has already occurred. And this holds whether the wife
ask expressly or interpretively, as when she is ashamed and her husband
feels that she desires him to pay the debt, for then he may pay it
without sin. This is especially the case if he fears to endanger her
chastity: nor does it matter that they are equal in the marriage act,
since everyone may renounce what is his own. Some say, however, that he
may both ask and pay lest the marriage become too burdensome to the wife
who has always to ask; but if this be looked into aright, it is the same
as asking interpretively.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether a solemn vow dissolves a marriage already contracted?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that not even a solemn vow dissolves a marriage
already contracted. For according to a Decretal (cap. Rursus, De his qui
cler. vel vovent.) "in God's sight a simple vow is no less binding than a
solemn one." Now marriage stands or falls by virtue of the Divine
acceptance. Therefore since a simple vow does not dissolve marriage,
neither will a solemn vow dissolve it.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, a solemn vow does not add the same force to a simple vow
as an oath does. Now a simple vow, even though an oath be added thereto,
does not dissolve a marriage already contracted. Neither therefore does a
solemn vow.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, a solemn vow has nothing that a simple vow cannot have.
For a simple vow may give rise to scandal since it may be public, even as
a solemn vow. Again the Church could and should ordain that a simple vow
dissolves a marriage already contracted, so that many sins may be
avoided. Therefore for the same reason that a simple vow does not
dissolve a marriage already contracted, neither should a solemn vow
dissolve it.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[2] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, He who takes a solemn vow contracts a spiritual
marriage with God, which is much more excellent than a material marriage.
Now a material marriage already contracted annuls a marriage contracted
afterwards. Therefore a solemn vow does also.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[2] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, the same conclusion may be proved by many authorities quoted in
the text (Sent. iv, D, 28).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, All agree that as a solemn vow is an impediment to the
contracting of marriage, so it invalidates the contract. Some assign
scandal as the reason. But this is futile, because even a simple vow
sometimes leads to scandal since it is at times somewhat public. Moreover
the indissolubility of marriage belongs to the truth of life [*Cf. FP,
Q[16], A[4], ad 3; FP, Q[21], A[2], ad 2; SS, Q[109], A[3], ad 3], which
truth is not to be set aside on account of scandal. Wherefore others say
that it is on account of the ordinance of the Church. But this again is
insufficient, since in that case the Church might decide the contrary,
which is seemingly untrue. Wherefore we must say with others that a
solemn vow of its very nature dissolves the marriage contract, inasmuch
namely as thereby a man has lost the power over his own body, through
surrendering it to God for the purpose of perpetual continence. Wherefore
he is unable to surrender it to the power of a wife by contracting
marriage. And since the marriage that follows such a vow is void, a vow
of this kind is said to annul the marriage contracted.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: A simple vow is said to be no less binding in God's sight
than a solemn vow, in matters pertaining to God, for instance the
separation from God by mortal sin, because he who breaks a simple vow
commits a mortal sin just as one who breaks a solemn vow, although it is
more grievous to break a solemn vow, so that the comparison be understood
as to the genus and not as to the definite degree of guilt. But as
regards marriage, whereby one man is under an obligation to another,
there is no need for it to be of equal obligation even in general, since
a solemn vow binds to certain things to which a simple vow does not bind.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: An oath is more binding than a vow on the part of the cause
of the obligation: but a solemn vow is more binding as to the manner in
which it binds, in so far as it is an actual surrender of that which is
promised; while an oath does not do this actually. Hence the conclusion
does not follow.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: A solemn vow implies the actual surrender of one's body,
whereas a simple vow does not, as stated above (A[1]). Hence the argument
does not suffice to prove the conclusion.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether order is an impediment to matrimony?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that order is not an impediment to matrimony. For
nothing is an impediment to a thing except its contrary. But order is not
contrary to matrimony. Therefore it is not an impediment thereto.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, orders are the same with us as with the Eastern Church.
But they are not an impediment to matrimony in the Eastern Church.
Therefore, etc.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, matrimony signifies the union of Christ with the Church.
Now this is most fittingly signified in those who are Christ's ministers,
those namely who are ordained. Therefore order is not an impediment to
matrimony.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[3] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, all the orders are directed to spiritual things. Now
order cannot be an impediment to matrimony except by reason of its
spirituality. Therefore if order is an impediment to matrimony, every
order will be an impediment, and this is untrue.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[3] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, every ordained person can have ecclesiastical benefices,
and can enjoy equally the privilege of clergy. If, therefore, orders are
an impediment to marriage, because married persons cannot have an
ecclesiastical benefice, nor enjoy the privilege of clergy, as jurists
assert (cap. Joannes et seqq., De cler. conjug.), then every order ought
to be an impediment. Yet this is false, as shown by the Decretal of
Alexander III (De cler. conjug., cap. Si Quis): and consequently it would
seem that no order is an impediment to marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[3] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, the Decretal says (De cler. conjug., cap. Si Quis):
"any person whom you shall find to have taken a wife after receiving the
subdiaconate or the higher orders, you shall compel to put his wife
away." But this would not be so if the marriage were valid.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[3] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, no person who has vowed continence can contract marriage. Now
some orders have a vow of continence connected with them, as appears from
the text (Sent. iv, D, 37). Therefore in that case order is an impediment
to matrimony.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[3] Body Para. 1/2
I answer that, By a certain fittingness the very nature of holy order
requires that it should be an impediment to marriage: because those who
are in holy orders handle the sacred vessels and the sacraments:
wherefore it is becoming that they keep their bodies clean by continence
[*Cf. Is. 52:11]. But it is owing to the Church's ordinance that it is
actually an impediment to marriage. However it is not the same with the
Latins as with the Greeks; since with the Greeks it is an impediment to
the contracting of marriage, solely by virtue of order; whereas with the
Latins it is an impediment by virtue of order, and besides by virtue of
the vow of continence which is annexed to the sacred orders; for although
this vow is not expressed in words, nevertheless a person is understood
to have taken it by the very fact of his being ordained. Hence among the
Greeks and other Eastern peoples a sacred order is an impediment to the
contracting of matrimony but it does not forbid the use of marriage
already contracted: for they can use marriage contracted previously,
although they cannot be married again. But in the Western Church it is
an impediment both to marriage and to the use of marriage, unless perhaps
the husband should receive a sacred order without the knowledge or
consent of his wife, because this cannot be prejudicial to her.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[3] Body Para. 2/2
Of the distinction between sacred and non-sacred orders now and in the
early Church we have spoken above (Q[37], A[3]).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Although a sacred order is not contrary to matrimony as a
sacrament, it has a certain incompatibility with marriage in respect of
the latter's act which is an obstacle to spiritual acts.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The objection is based on a false statement: since order is
everywhere an impediment to the contracting of marriage, although it has
not everywhere a vow annexed to it.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Those who are in sacred orders signify Christ by more
sublime actions, as appears from what has been said in the treatise on
orders (Q[37], AA[2],4), than those who are married. Consequently the
conclusion does not follow.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[3] R.O. 4 Para. 1/2
Reply OBJ 4: Those who are in minor orders are not forbidden to marry by
virtue of their order; for although those orders are entrusted with
certain spiritualities, they are not admitted to the immediate handling
of sacred things, as those are who are in sacred orders. But according to
the laws of the Western Church, the use of marriage is an impediment to
the exercise of a non-sacred order, for the sake of maintaining a greater
honesty in the offices of the Church. And since the holding of an
ecclesiastical benefice binds a man to the exercise of his order, and
since for this very reason he enjoys the privilege of clergy, it follows
that in the Latin Church this privilege is forfeit to a married cleric.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[3] R.O. 4 Para. 2/2
This suffices for the Reply to the last Objection.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether a sacred order cannot supervene to matrimony?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that a sacred order cannot supervene to matrimony.
For the stronger prejudices the weaker. Now a spiritual obligation is
stronger than a bodily tie. Therefore if a married man be ordained, this
will prejudice the wife, so that she will be unable to demand the debt,
since order is a spiritual, and marriage a bodily bond. Hence it would
seem that a man cannot receive a sacred order after consummating marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, after consummating the marriage, one of the parties
cannot vow continence without the other's consent [*Cf. Q[61], A[1]]. Now
a sacred order has a vow of continence annexed to it. Therefore if the
husband be ordained without his wife's consent, she will be bound to
remain continent against her will, since she cannot marry another man
during her husband's lifetime.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[4] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, a husband may not even for a time devote himself to
prayer without his wife's consent (1 Cor. 7:5). But in the Eastern Church
those who are in sacred orders are bound to continence for the time when
they exercise their office. Therefore neither may they be ordained
without their wife's consent, and much less may the Latins.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[4] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, husband and wife are on a par with one another. Now a
Greek priest cannot marry again after his wife's death. Therefore neither
can his wife after her husband's death. But she cannot be deprived by her
husband's act of the right to marry after his death. Therefore her
husband cannot receive orders after marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[4] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, order is as much opposed to marriage as marriage to
order. Now a previous order is an impediment to a subsequent marriage.
Therefore, etc.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[4] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, Religious are bound to continence like those who are in
sacred orders. But a man may enter religion after marriage, if his wife
die, or if she consent. Therefore he can also receive orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[4] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, a man may become a man's bondsman after marriage. Therefore he
can become a bondsman of God by receiving orders.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[4] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Marriage is not an impediment to the receiving of sacred
orders, since if a married man receive sacred orders, even though his
wife be unwilling, he receives the character of order: but he lacks the
exercise of his order. If, however, his wife consent, or if she be dead,
he receives both the order and the exercise.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The bond of orders dissolves the bond of marriage as
regards the payment of the debt, in respect of which it is incompatible
with marriage, on the part of the person ordained, since he cannot demand
the debt, nor is the wife bound to pay it. But it does not dissolve the
bond in respect of the other party, since the husband is bound to pay the
debt to the wife if he cannot persuade her to observe continence.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: If the husband receive sacred orders with the knowledge and
consent of his wife, she is bound to vow perpetual continence, but she is
not bound to enter religion, if she has no fear of her chastity being
endangered through her husband having taken a solemn vow: it would have
been different, however, if he had taken a simple vow. On the other hand,
if he be ordained without her consent, she is not bound in this way,
because the result is not prejudicial to her in any way.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[4] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: It would seem more probable, although some say the
contrary, that even a Greek ought not to receive sacred orders without
his wife's consent, since at least at the time of his ministry she would
be deprived of the payment of the debt, of which she cannot be deprived
according to law if the husband should have been ordained without her
consent or knowledge.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[4] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: As stated, among the Greeks the wife, by the very fact of
consenting to her husband's receiving a sacred order, binds herself never
to marry another man, because the signification of marriage would not be
safeguarded, and this is especially required in the marriage of a priest.
If, however, he be ordained without her consent, seemingly she would not
be under that obligation.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[53] A[4] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: Marriage has for its cause our consent: not so order, which
has a sacramental cause appointed by God. Hence matrimony may be impeded
by a previous order; so as not to be true marriage: whereas order cannot
be impeded by marriage, so as not to be true order, because the power of
the sacraments is unchangeable, whereas human acts can be impeded.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] Out. Para. 1/1
OF THE IMPEDIMENT OF CONSANGUINITY (FOUR ARTICLES)
We must next consider the impediment of consanguinity. Under this head
there are four points of inquiry:
(1) Whether consanguinity is rightly defined by some?
(2) Whether it is fittingly distinguished by degrees and lines?
(3) Whether certain degrees are by natural law an impediment to marriage?
(4) Whether the impediment degrees can be fixed by the ordinance of the
Church?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether consanguinity is rightly defined?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that consanguinity is unsuitably defined by some as
follows: "Consanguinity is the tie contracted between persons descending
from the same common ancestor by carnal procreation." For all men descend
from the same common ancestor, namely Adam, by carnal procreation.
Therefore if the above definition of consanguinity is right, all men
would be related by consanguinity: which is false.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, a tie is only between things in accord with one another,
since a tie unites. Now there is not greater accordance between persons
descended from a common ancestor than there is between other men, since
they accord in species but differ in number, just as other men do.
Therefore consanguinity is not a tie.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, carnal procreation, according to the Philosopher (De
Gener. Anim. ii, 19), is effected from the surplus food [*Cf. FP, Q[119],
A[2]]. Now this surplus has more in common with that which is eaten,
since it agrees with it in substance, than with him who eats. Since then
no tie of consanguinity arises between the person born of semen and that
which he eats, neither will there be any tie of kindred between him and
the person of whom he is born by carnal procreation.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[1] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, Laban said to Jacob (Gn. 29:14): "Thou art my bone and
my flesh," on account of the relationship between them. Therefore such a
kinship should be called flesh-relationship rather than
blood-relationship [consanguinitas].
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[1] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, carnal procreation is common to men and animals. But no
tie of consanguinity is contracted among animals from carnal procreation.
Therefore neither is there among men.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, According to the Philosopher (Ethic. iii, 11, 12) "all
friendship is based on some kind of fellowship." And since friendship is
a knot or union, it follows that the fellowship which is the cause of
friendship is called "a tie." Wherefore in respect of any kind of a
fellowship certain persons are denominated as though they were tied
together: thus we speak of fellow-citizens who are connected by a common
political life, of fellow-soldiers who are connected by the common
business of soldiering, and in the same way those who are connected by
the fellowship of nature are said to be tied by blood [consanguinei].
Hence in the above definition "tie" is included as being the genus of
consanguinity; the "persons descending from the same common ancestor,"
who are thus tied together are the subject of this tie. while "carnal
procreation" is mentioned as being its origin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: An active force is not received into an instrument in the
same degree of perfection as it has in the principal agent. And since
every moved mover is an instrument, it follows that the power of the
first mover in a particular genus when drawn out through many mediate
movers fails at length, and reaches something that is moved and not a
mover. But the power of a begetter moves not only as to that which
belongs to the species, but also as to that which belongs to the
individual, by reason of which the child is like the parent even in
accidentals and not only in the specific nature. And yet this individual
power of the father is not so perfect in the son as it was in the father,
and still less so in the grandson, and thus it goes on failing: so that
at length it ceases and can go no further. Since then consanguinity
results from this power being communicated to many through being conveyed
to them from one person by procreation, it destroys itself by little and
little, as Isidore says (Etym. ix). Consequently in defining
consanguinity we must not take a remote common ancestor but the nearest,
whose power still remains in those who are descended from him.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: It is clear from what has been said that blood relations
agree not only in the specific nature but also in that power peculiar to
the individual which is conveyed from one to many: the result being that
sometimes the child is not only like his father, but also his grandfather
or his remote ancestors (De Gener. Anim. iv, 3).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Likeness depends more on form whereby a thing is actually,
than on matter whereby a thing is potentially: for instance, charcoal has
more in common with fire than with the tree from which the wood was cut.
In like manner food already transformed by the nutritive power into the
substance of the person fed has more in common with the subject nourished
than with that from which the nourishment was taken. The argument however
would hold according to the opinion of those who asserted that the whole
nature of a thing is from its matter and that all forms are accidents:
which is false.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[1] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: It is the blood that is proximately changed into the semen,
as proved in De Gener. Anim. i, 18. Hence the tie contracted by carnal
procreation is more fittingly called blood-relationship than
flesh-relationship. That sometimes one relation is called the flesh of
another, is because the blood which is transformed into the man's seed or
into the menstrual fluid is potentially flesh and bone.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[1] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: Some say that the reason why the tie of consanguinity is
contracted among men through carnal procreation, and not among other
animals, is because whatever belongs to the truth of human nature in all
men was in our first parent: which does not apply to other animals. But
according to this, matrimonial consanguinity would never come to an end.
However the above theory was disproved in the Second Book (Sent. ii, D,
30: FP, Q[119], A[1]). Wherefore we must reply that the reason for this
is that animals are not united together in the union of friendship
through the begetting of many from one proximate parent, as is the case
with men, as stated above.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether consanguinity is fittingly distinguished by degrees and lines?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that consanguinity is unfittingly distinguished by
degrees and lines. For a line of consanguinity is described as "the
ordered series of persons related by blood, and descending from a common
ancestor in various degrees." Now consanguinity is nothing else but a
series of such persons. Therefore a line of consanguinity is the same as
consanguinity. Now a thing ought not to be distinguished by itself.
Therefore consanguinity is not fittingly distinguished into lines.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, that by which a common thing is divided should not be
placed in the definition of that common thing. Now descent is placed in
the above definition of consanguinity. Therefore consanguinity cannot be
divided into ascending, descending and collateral lines.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, a line is defined as being between two points. But two
points make but one degree. Therefore one line has but one degree, and
for this reason it would seem that consanguinity should not be divided
into lines and degrees.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[2] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, a degree is defined as "the relation between distant
persons, whereby is known the distance between them." Now since
consanguinity is a kind of propinquity, distance between persons is
opposed to consanguinity rather than a part thereof.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[2] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, if consanguinity is distinguished and known by its
degrees, those who are in the same degree ought to be equally related.
But this is false since a man's great-uncle and great-nephew are in the
same degree, and yet they are not equally related according to a Decretal
(cap. Porro; cap. Parenteloe, 35, qu. v). Therefore consanguinity is not
rightly divided into degrees.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[2] Obj. 6 Para. 1/1
OBJ 6: Further, in ordinary things a different degree results from the
addition of one thing to another, even as every additional unity makes a
different species of number. Yet the addition of one person to another
does not always make a different degree of consanguinity, since father
and uncle are in the same degree of consanguinity, for they are side by
side. Therefore consanguinity is not rightly divided into degrees.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[2] Obj. 7 Para. 1/1
OBJ 7: Further, if two persons be akin to one another there is always
the same measure of kinship between them, since the distance from one
extreme to the other is the same either way. Yet the degrees of
consanguinity are not always the same on either side, since sometimes one
relative is in the third and the other in the fourth degree. Therefore
the measure of consanguinity cannot be sufficiently known by its degrees.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[2] Body Para. 1/2
I answer that, Consanguinity as stated (A[1]) is a certain propinquity
based on the natural communication by the act of procreation whereby
nature is propagated. Wherefore according to the Philosopher (Ethic.
viii, 12) this communication is threefold. one corresponds to the
relationship between cause and effect, and this is the consanguinity of
father to son, wherefore he says that "parents love their children as
being a part of themselves." Another corresponds to the relation of
effect to cause, and this is the consanguinity of son to father,
wherefore he says that "children love their parents as being themselves
something which owes its existence to them." The third corresponds to the
mutual relation between things that come from the same cause, as
brothers, "who are born of the same parents," as he again says (Ethic.
viii, 12). And since the movement of a point makes a line, and since a
father by procreation may be said to descend to his son, hence it is that
corresponding to these three relationships there are three lines of
consanguinity, namely the "descending" line corresponding to the first
relationship, the "ascending" line corresponding to the second, and the
"collateral" line corresponding to the third. Since however the movement
of propagation does not rest in one term but continues beyond, the result
is that one can point to the father's father and to the son's son, and so
on, and according to the various steps we take we find various degrees in
one line. And seeing that the degrees of a thing are parts of that thing,
there cannot be degrees of propinquity where there is no propinquity.
Consequently identity and too great a distance do away with degrees of
consanguinity; since no man is kin to himself any more than he is like
himself: for which reason there is no degree of consanguinity where there
is but one person, but only when one person is compared to another.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[2] Body Para. 2/2
Nevertheless there are different ways of counting the degrees in various
lines. For the degree of consanguinity in the ascending and descending
line is contracted from the fact that one of the parties whose
consanguinity is in question, is descended from the other. Wherefore
according to the canonical as well as the legal reckoning, the person who
occupies the first place, whether in the ascending or in the descending
line, is distant from a certain one, say Peter, in the first degree---for
instance father and son; while the one who occupies the second place in
either direction is distant in the second degree, for instance
grandfather, grandson and so on. But the consanguinity that exists
between persons who are in collateral lines is contracted not through one
being descended from the other, but through both being descended from
one: wherefore the degrees of consanguinity in this line must be reckoned
in relation to the one principle whence it arises. Here, however, the
canonical and legal reckonings differ: for the legal reckoning takes into
account the descent from the common stock on both sides, whereas the
canonical reckoning takes into account only one, that namely on which the
greater number of degrees are found. Hence according to the legal
reckoning brother and sister, or two brothers, are related in the second
degree, because each is separated from the common stock by one degree;
and in like manner the children of two brothers are distant from one
another in the fourth degree. But according to the canonical reckoning,
two brothers are related in the first degree, since neither is distant
more than one degree from the common stock: but the children of one
brother are distant in the second degree from the other brother, because
they are at that distance from the common stock. Hence, according to the
canonical reckoning, by whatever degree a person is distant from some
higher degree, by so much and never by less is he distant from each
person descending from that degree, because "the cause of a thing being
so is yet more so." Wherefore although the other descendants from the
common stock be related to some person on account of his being descended
from the common stock, these descendants of the other branch cannot be
more nearly related to him than he is to the common stock. Sometimes,
however, a person is more distantly related to a descendant from the
common stock, than he himself is to the common stock, because this other
person may be more distantly related to the common stock than he is: and
consanguinity must be reckoned according to the more distant degree.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: This objection is based on a false premise: for
consanguinity is not the series but a mutual relationship existing
between certain persons, the series of whom forms a line of consanguinity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Descent taken in a general sense attaches to every line of
consanguinity, because carnal procreation whence the tie of consanguinity
arises is a kind of descent: but it is a particular kind of descent,
namely from the person whose consanguinity is in question, that makes the
descending line.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: A line may be taken in two ways. Sometimes it is taken
properly for the dimension itself that is the first species of continuous
quantity: and thus a straight line contains actually but two points which
terminate it, but infinite points potentially, any one of which being
actually designated, the line is divided, and becomes two lines. But
sometimes a line designates things which are arranged in a line, and thus
we have line and figure in numbers, in so far as unity added to unity
involves number. Thus every unity added makes a degree in a particular
line: and it is the same with the line of consanguinity: wherefore one
line contains several degrees.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[2] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: Even as there cannot be likeness without a difference, so
there is no propinquity without distance. Hence not every distance is
opposed to consanguinity, but such as excludes the propinquity of
blood-relationship.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[2] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: Even as whiteness is said to be greater in two ways, in one
way through intensity of the quality itself, in another way through the
quantity of the surface, so consanguinity is said to be greater or lesser
in two ways. First, intensively by reason of the very nature of
consanguinity: secondly, extensively as it were, and thus the degree of
consanguinity is measured by the persons between whom there is the
propagation of a common blood, and in this way the degrees of
consanguinity are distinguished. Wherefore it happens that of two persons
related to one person in the same degree of consanguinity, one is more
akin to him than the other, if we consider the quantity of consanguinity
in the first way: thus a man's father and brother are related to him in
the first degree of consanguinity, because in neither case does any
person come in between; and yet from the point of view of intensity a
man's father is more closely related to him than his brother, since his
brother is related to him only because he is of the same father. Hence
the nearer a person is to the common ancestor from whom the consanguinity
descends, the greater is his consanguinity although he be not in a nearer
degree. In this way a man's great-uncle is more closely related to him
than his great-nephew, although they are in the same degree.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[2] R.O. 6 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 6: Although a man's father and uncle are in the same degree in
respect of the root of consanguinity, since both are separated by one
degree from the grandfather, nevertheless in respect of the person whose
consanguinity is in question, they are not in the same degree, since the
father is in the first degree, whereas the uncle cannot be nearer than
the second degree, wherein the grandfather stands.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[2] R.O. 7 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 7: Two persons are always related in the same degree to one
another, although they are not always distant in the same number of
degrees from the common ancestor, as explained above.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether consanguinity is an impediment to marriage by virtue of the
natural law?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that consanguinity is not by natural law an
impediment to marriage. For no woman can be more akin to a man than Eve
was to Adam, since of her did he say (Gn. 2:23): "This now is bone of my
bones and flesh of my flesh." Yet Eve was joined in marriage to Adam.
Therefore as regards the natural law no consanguinity is an impediment to
marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the natural law is the same for all. Now among the
uncivilized nations no person is debarred from marriage by reason of
consanguinity. Therefore, as regards the law of nature, consanguinity is
no impediment to marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, the natural law is what "nature has taught all animals,"
as stated at the beginning of the Digests (i, ff. De just. et jure). Now
brute animals copulate even with their mother. Therefore it is not of
natural law that certain persons are debarred from marriage on account of
consanguinity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[3] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, nothing that is not contrary to one of the goods of
matrimony is an impediment to marriage. But consanguinity is not contrary
to any of the goods of marriage. Therefore it is not an impediment
thereto.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[3] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, things which are more akin and more similar to one
another are better and more firmly united together. Now matrimony is a
kind of union. Since then consanguinity is a kind of kinship, it does not
hinder marriage but rather strengthens the union.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[3] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, According to the natural law whatever is an obstacle to
the good of the offspring is an impediment to marriage. Now consanguinity
hinders the good of the offspring, because in the words of Gregory
(Regist., epis. xxxi) quoted in the text (Sent. iv, D, 40): "We have
learnt by experience that the children of such a union cannot thrive."
Therefore according to the law of nature consanguinity is an impediment
to matrimony.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[3] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, that which belongs to human nature when it was first created is
of natural law. Now it belonged to human nature from when it was first
created that one should be debarred from marrying one's father or mother:
in proof of which it was said (Gn. 2:24): "Wherefore a man shall leave
father and mother": which cannot be understood of cohabitation, and
consequently must refer to the union of marriage. Therefore consanguinity
is an impediment to marriage according to the natural law.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[3] Body Para. 1/3
I answer that, In relation to marriage a thing is said to be contrary to
the natural law if it prevents marriage from reaching the end for which
it was instituted. Now the essential and primary end of marriage is the
good of the offspring. and this is hindered by a certain consanguinity,
namely that which is between father and daughter, or son and mother. It
is not that the good of the offspring is utterly destroyed, since a
daughter can have a child of her father's semen and with the father rear
and teach that child in which things the good of the offspring consists,
but that it is not effected in a becoming way. For it is out of order
that a daughter be mated to her father in marriage for the purpose of
begetting and rearing children, since in all things she ought to be
subject to her father as proceeding from him. Hence by natural law a
father and mother are debarred from marrying their children; and the
mother still more than the father, since it is more derogatory to the
reverence due to parents if the son marry his mother than if the father
marry his daughter; since the wife should be to a certain extent subject
to her husband. The secondary essential end of marriage is the curbing of
concupiscence; and this end would be forfeit if a man could marry any
blood-relation, since a wide scope would be afforded to concupiscence if
those who have to live together in the same house were not forbidden to
be mated in the flesh. Wherefore the Divine law debars from marriage not
only father and mother, but also other kinsfolk who have to live in close
intimacy with one another and ought to safeguard one another's modesty.
The Divine law assigns this reason (Lev. 18:10): "Thou shalt not uncover
the nakedness" of such and such a one, "because it is thy own nakedness."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[3] Body Para. 2/3
But the accidental end of marriage is the binding together of mankind
and the extension of friendship: for a husband regards his wife's kindred
as his own. Hence it would be prejudicial to this extension of friendship
if a man could take a woman of his kindred to wife since no new
friendship would accrue to anyone from such a marriage. Wherefore,
according to human law and the ordinances of the Church, several degrees
of consanguinity are debarred from marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[3] Body Para. 3/3
Accordingly it is clear from what has been said that consanguinity is by
natural law an impediment to marriage in regard to certain persons, by
Divine law in respect of some, and by human law in respect of others.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Although Eve was formed from Adam she was not Adam's
daughter, because she was not formed from him after the manner in which
it is natural for a man to beget his like in species, but by the Divine
operation, since from Adam's rib a horse might have been formed in the
same way as Eve was. Hence the natural connection between Eve and Adam
was not so great as between daughter and father, nor was Adam the natural
principle of Eve as a father is of his daughter.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: That certain barbarians are united carnally to their
parents does not come from the natural law but from the passion of
concupiscence which has clouded the natural law in them.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/2
Reply OBJ 3: Union of male and female is said to be of natural law,
because nature has taught this to animals: yet she has taught this union
to various animals in various ways according to their various conditions.
But carnal copulation with parents is derogatory to the reverence due to
them. For just as nature has instilled into parents solicitude in
providing for their offspring, so has it instilled into the offspring
reverence towards their parents: yet to no kind of animal save man has
she instilled a lasting solicitude for his children or reverence for
parents; but to other animals more or less, according as the offspring is
more or less necessary to its parents, or the parents to their offspring.
Hence as the Philosopher attests (De Animal. ix, 47) concerning the camel
and the horse, among certain animals the son abhors copulation with its
mother as long as he retains knowledge of her and a certain reverence for
her. And since all honest customs of animals are united together in man
naturally, and more perfectly than in other animals, it follows that man
naturally abhors carnal knowledge not only of his mother, but also of his
daughter, which is, however, less against nature, as stated above.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 2/2
Moreover consanguinity does not result from carnal procreation in other
animals as in man, as stated above (A[1], ad 5). Hence the comparison
fails.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[3] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: It has been shown how consanguinity between married persons
is contrary to the goods of marriage. Hence the Objection proceeds from
false premises.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[3] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: It is not unreasonable for one of two unions to be hindered
by the other, even as where there is identity there is not likeness. In
like manner the tie of consanguinity may hinder the union of marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the degrees of consanguinity that are an impediment to marriage
could be fixed by the Church?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the degrees of consanguinity that are an
impediment to marriage could not be fixed by the Church so as to reach to
the fourth degree. For it is written (Mt. 19:6): "What God hath joined
together let no man put asunder." But God joined those together who are
married within the fourth degree of consanguinity, since their union is
not forbidden by the Divine law. Therefore they should not be put asunder
by a human law.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, matrimony is a sacrament as also is baptism. Now no
ordinance of the Church could prevent one who is baptized from receiving
the baptismal character, if he be capable of receiving it according to
the Divine law. Therefore neither can an ordinance of the Church forbid
marriage between those who are not forbidden to marry by the Divine law.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[4] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, positive law can neither void nor extend those things
which are natural. Now consanguinity is a natural tie which is in itself
of a nature to impede marriage. Therefore the Church cannot by its
ordinance permit or forbid certain people to marry, any more than she can
make them to be kin or not kin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[4] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, an ordinance of positive law should have some reasonable
cause, since it is for this reasonable cause that it proceeds from the
natural law. But the causes that are assigned for the number of degrees
seem altogether unreasonable, since they bear no relation to their
effect; for instance, that consanguinity be an impediment as far as the
fourth degree on account of the four elements as far as the sixth degree
on account of the six ages of the world, as far as the seventh degree on
account of the seven days of which all time is comprised. Therefore
seemingly this prohibition is of no force.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[4] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, where the cause is the same there should be the same
effect. Now the causes for which consanguinity is an impediment to
marriage are the good of the offspring, the curbing of concupiscence, and
the extension of friendship, as stated above (A[3]), which are equally
necessary for all time. Therefore the degrees of consanguinity should
have equally impeded marriage at all times: yet this is not true since
consanguinity is now an impediment to marriage as far as the fourth
degree, whereas formerly it was an impediment as far as the seventh.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[4] Obj. 6 Para. 1/1
OBJ 6: Further, one and the same union cannot be a kind of sacrament and
a kind of incest. But this would be the case if the Church had the power
of fixing a different number in the degrees which are an impediment to
marriage. Thus if certain parties related in the fifth degree were
married when that degree was an impediment, their union would be
incestuous, and yet this same union would be a marriage afterwards when
the Church withdrew her prohibition. And the reverse might happen if
certain degrees which were not an impediment were subsequently to be
forbidden by the Church. Therefore seemingly the power of the Church does
not extend to this.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[4] Obj. 7 Para. 1/1
OBJ 7: Further, human law should copy the Divine law. Now according to
the Divine law which is contained in the Old Law, the prohibition of
degrees does not apply equally in the ascending and descending lines:
since in the Old Law a man was forbidden to marry his father's sister but
not his brother's daughter. Therefore neither should there remain now a
prohibition in respect of nephews and uncles.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[4] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, Our Lord said to His disciples (Lk. 10:16): "He that
heareth you heareth Me." Therefore a commandment of the Church has the
same force as a commandment of God. Now the Church sometimes has
forbidden and sometimes allowed certain degrees which the Old Law did not
forbid. Therefore those degrees are an impediment to marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[4] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, even as of old the marriages of pagans were controlled by the
civil law, so now is marriage controlled by the laws of the Church. Now
formerly the civil law decided which degrees of consanguinity impede
marriage, and which do not. Therefore this can be done now by a
commandment of the Church.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[4] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, The degrees within which consanguinity has been an
impediment to marriage have varied according to various times. For at the
beginning of the human race father and mother alone were debarred from
marrying their children, because then mankind were few in number, and
then it was necessary for the propagation of the human race to be ensured
with very great care, and consequently only such persons were to be
debarred as were unfitted for marriage even in respect of its principal
end which is the good of the offspring, as stated above (A[3]).
Afterwards however, the human race having multiplied, more persons were
excluded by the law of Moses, for they already began to curb
concupiscence. Wherefore as Rabbi Moses says (Doc. Perp. iii, 49) all
those persons were debarred from marrying one another who are wont to
live together in one household, because if a lawful carnal intercourse
were possible between them, this would prove a very great incentive to
lust. Yet the Old Law permitted other degrees of consanguinity, in fact
to a certain extent it commanded them; to wit that each man should take a
wife from his kindred, in order to avoid confusion of inheritances:
because at that time the Divine worship was handed down as the
inheritance of the race. But afterwards more degrees were forbidden by
the New Law which is the law of the spirit and of love, because the
worship of God is no longer handed down and spread abroad by a carnal
birth but by a spiritual grace: wherefore it was necessary that men
should be yet more withdrawn from carnal things by devoting themselves to
things spiritual, and that love should have a yet wider play. Hence in
olden times marriage was forbidden even within the more remote degrees of
consanguinity, in order that consanguinity and affinity might be the
sources of a wider natural friendship; and this was reasonably extended
to the seventh degree, both because beyond this it was difficult to have
any recollection of the common stock, and because this was in keeping
with the sevenfold grace of the Holy Ghost. Afterwards, however, towards
these latter times the prohibition of the Church has been restricted to
the fourth degree, because it became useless and dangerous to extend the
prohibition to more remote degrees of consanguinity. Useless, because
charity waxed cold in many hearts so that they had scarcely a greater
bond of friendship with their more remote kindred than with strangers:
and it was dangerous because through the prevalence of concupiscence and
neglect men took no account of so numerous a kindred, and thus the
prohibition of the more remote degrees became for many a snare leading to
damnation. Moreover there is a certain fittingness in the restriction of
the above prohibition to the fourth degree. First because men are wont to
live until the fourth generation, so that consanguinity cannot lapse into
oblivion, wherefore God threatened (Ex. 20:5) to visit the parent's sins
on their children to the third and fourth generation. Secondly, because
in each generation the blood, the identity of which causes consanguinity,
receives a further addition of new blood, and the more another blood is
added the less there is of the old. And because there are four elements,
each of which is the more easily mixed with another, according as it is
more rarefied it follows that at the first admixture the identity of
blood disappears as regards the first element which is most subtle; at
the second admixture, as regards the second element; at the third, as to
the third element; at the fourth, as to the fourth element. Thus after
the fourth generation it is fitting for the carnal union to be repeated.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Even as God does not join together those who are joined
together against the Divine command, so does He not join together those
who are joined together against the commandment of the Church, which has
the same binding force as a commandment of God.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Matrimony is not only a sacrament but also fulfills an
office; wherefore it is more subject to the control of the Church's
ministers than baptism which is a sacrament only: because just as human
contracts and offices are controlled by human laws, so are spiritual
contracts and offices controlled by the law of the Church.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[4] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Although the tie of consanguinity is natural, it is not
natural that consanguinity forbid carnal intercourse, except as regards
certain degrees, as stated above (A[3]). Wherefore the Church's
commandment does not cause certain people to be kin or not kin, because
they remain equally kin at all times: but it makes carnal intercourse to
be lawful or unlawful at different times for different degrees of
consanguinity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[4] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: The reasons assigned are given as indicating aptness and
congruousness rather than causality and necessity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[4] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: The reason for the impediment of consanguinity is not the
same at different times: wherefore that which it was useful to allow at
one time, it was beneficial to forbid at another.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[4] R.O. 6 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 6: A commandment does not affect the past but the future.
Wherefore if the fifth degree which is now allowed were to be forbidden
at any time, those in the fifth degree who are married would not have to
separate, because no impediment supervening to marriage can annul it; and
consequently a union which was a marriage from the first would not be
made incestuous by a commandment of the Church. In like manner, if a
degree which is now forbidden were to be allowed, such a union would not
become a marriage on account of the Church's commandment by reason of the
former contract, because they could separate if they wished.
Nevertheless, they could contract anew, and this would be a new union.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[54] A[4] R.O. 7 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 7: In prohibiting the degrees of consanguinity the Church
considers chiefly the point of view of affection. And since the reason
for affection towards one's brother's son is not less but even greater
than the reasons for affection towards one's father's brother, inasmuch
as the son is more akin to the father than the father to the son (Ethic.
viii, 12), therefore did the Church equally prohibit the degrees of
consanguinity in uncles and nephews. On the other hand the Old Law in
debarring certain persons looked chiefly to the danger of concupiscence
arising from cohabitation; and debarred those persons who were in closer
intimacy with one another on account of their living together. Now it is
more usual for a niece to live with her uncle than an aunt with her
nephew: because a daughter is more identified with her father, being part
of him, whereas a sister is not in this way identified with her brother,
for she is not part of him but is born of the same parent. Hence there
was not the same reason for debarring a niece and an aunt.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] Out. Para. 1/1
OF THE IMPEDIMENT OF AFFINITY (ELEVEN ARTICLES)
We must consider next the impediment of affinity. Under this head there
are eleven points of inquiry:
(1) Whether affinity results from matrimony?
(2) Whether it remains after the death of husband or wife?
(3) Whether it is caused through unlawful intercourse?
(4) Whether it arises from a betrothal?
(5) Whether affinity is caused through affinity?
(6) Whether affinity is an impediment to marriage?
(7) Whether affinity in itself admits of degrees?
(8) Whether its degrees extend as far as the degrees of consanguinity?
(9) Whether marriages of persons related to one another by consanguinity
or affinity should always be dissolved by divorce?
(10) Whether the process for the dissolution of like marriages should
always be by way of accusation?
(11) Whether witnesses should be called in such a case?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether a person contracts affinity through the marriage of a
blood-relation?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that a person does not contract affinity through
the marriage of a blood-relation. For "the cause of a thing being so is
yet more so." Now the wife is not connected with her husband's kindred
except by reason of the husband. Since then she does not contract
affinity with her husband, neither does she contract it with her
husband's kindred.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, if certain things be separate from one another and
something be connected with one of them, it does not follow that it is
connected with the other. Now a person's blood relations are separate
from one another. Therefore it does not follow, if a certain woman be
married to a certain man, that she is therefore connected with all his
kindred.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, relations result from certain things being united
together. Now the kindred of the husband do not become united together by
the fact of his taking a wife. Therefore they do not acquire any
relationship of affinity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[1] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, Husband and wife are made one flesh. Therefore if the
husband is related in the flesh to all his kindred, for the same reason
his wife will be related to them all.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[1] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, this is proved by the authorities quoted in the text (Sent. iv,
D, 41).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, A certain natural friendship is founded on natural
fellowship. Now natural fellowship, according to the Philosopher (Ethic.
viii, 12), arises in two ways; first, from carnal procreation; secondly,
from connection with orderly carnal procreation, wherefore he says
(Ethic. viii, 12) that the friendship of a husband towards his wife is
natural. Consequently even as a person through being connected with
another by carnal procreation is bound to him by a tie of natural
friendship, so does one person become connected with another through
carnal intercourse. But there is a difference in this, that one who is
connected with another through carnal procreation, as a son with his
father, shares in the same common stock and blood, so that a son is
connected with his father's kindred by the same kind of tie as the father
was, the tie, namely of consanguinity, albeit in a different degree on
account of his being more distant from the stock: whereas one who is
connected with another through carnal intercourse does not share in the
same stock, but is as it were an extraneous addition thereto: whence
arises another kind of tie known by the name of "affinity." This is
expressed in the verse:
Marriage makes a new kind of connection,
While birth makes a new degree,
because, to wit, the person begotten is in the same kind of relationship,
but in a different degree, whereas through carnal intercourse he enters
into a new kind of relationship.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Although a cause is more potent than its effect, it does
not always follow that the same name is applicable to the cause as to the
effect, because sometimes that which is in the effect, is found in the
cause not in the same but in a higher way; wherefore it is not applicable
to both cause and effect under the same name or under the same aspect, as
is the case with all equivocal effective causes. Thus, then, the union of
husband and wife is stronger than the union of the wife with her
husband's kindred, and yet it ought not to be named affinity, but
matrimony which is a kind of unity; even as a man is identical with
himself, but not with his kinsman.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Blood-relations are in a way separate, and in a way
connected: and it happens in respect of their connection that a person
who is connected with one of them is in some way connected with all of
them. But on account of their separation and distance from one another it
happens that a person who is connected with one of them in one way is
connected with another in another way, either as to the kind of
connection or as to the degree.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Further, a relation results sometimes from a movement in
each extreme, for instance fatherhood and sonship, and a relation of this
kind is really in both extremes. Sometimes it results from the movement
of one only, and this happens in two ways. In one way when a relation
results from the movement of one extreme without any movement previous or
concomitant of the other extreme; as in the Creator and the creature, the
sensible and the sense, knowledge and the knowable object: and then the
relation is in one extreme really and in the other logically only. In
another way when the relation results from the movement of one extreme
without any concomitant movement, but not without a previous movement of
the other; thus there results equality between two men by the increase of
one, without the other either increasing or decreasing then, although
previously he reached his actual quantity by some movement or change, so
that this relation is founded really in both extremes. It is the same
with consanguinity and affinity, because the relation of brotherhood
which results in a grown child on the birth of a boy, is caused without
any movement of the former's at the time, but by virtue of that previous
movement of his wherein he was begotten; wherefore at the time it happens
that there results in him the aforesaid relation through the movement of
another. Likewise because this man descends through his own birth from
the same stock as the husband, there results in him affinity with the
latter's wife, without any new change in him.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether affinity remains after the death of husband or wife?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that affinity does not remain after the death of
husband or wife, between the blood-relations of husband and wife or "vice
versa." Because if the cause cease the effect ceases. Now the cause of
affinity was the marriage, which ceases after the husband's death, since
then "the woman . . . is loosed from the law of the husband" (Rm. 7:2).
Therefore the aforesaid affinity ceases also.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, consanguinity is the cause of affinity. Now the
consanguinity of the husband with his blood-relations ceases at his
death. Therefore, the wife's affinity with them ceases also.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, Affinity is caused by consanguinity. Now consanguinity
binds persons together for all time as long as they live. Therefore
affinity does so also: and consequently affinity (between two persons) is
not dissolved through the dissolution of the marriage by the death of a
third person.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, A relation ceases in two ways: in one way through the
corruption of its subject, in another way by the removal of its cause;
thus likeness ceases when one of the like subjects dies, or when the
quality that caused the likeness is removed. Now there are certain
relations which have for their cause an action, or a passion or movement
(Metaph. v, 20): and some of these are caused by movement, through
something being moved actually; such is the relation between mover and
moved: some of them are caused through something being adapted to
movement, for instance the relations between the motive power and the
movable, or between master and servant; and some of them result from
something, having been moved previously, such as the relation between
father and son, for the relation between them is caused not by (the con)
being begotten now, but by his having been begotten. Now aptitude for
movement and for being moved is transitory; whereas the fact of having
been moved is everlasting, since what has been never ceases having been.
Consequently fatherhood and sonship are never dissolved through the
removal of the cause, but only through the corruption of the subject,
that is of one of the subjects. The same applies to affinity, for this is
caused by certain persons having been joined together not by their being
actually joined. Wherefore it is not done away, as long as the persons
between whom affinity has been contracted survive, although the person
die through whom it was contracted.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The marriage tie causes affinity not only by reason of
actual union, but also by reason of the union having been effected in the
past.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Consanguinity is not the chief cause of affinity, but union
with a blood-relation, not only because that union is now, but because it
has been. Hence the argument does not prove.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether unlawful intercourse causes affinity?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that unlawful intercourse does not cause affinity.
For affinity is an honorable thing. Now honorable things do not result
from that which is dishonorable. Therefore affinity cannot be caused by a
dishonorable intercourse.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, where there is consanguinity there cannot be affinity;
since affinity is a relationship between persons that results from carnal
intercourse and is altogether void of blood-relationship. Now if unlawful
intercourse were a cause of affinity, it would sometimes happen that a
man would contract affinity with his blood-relations and with himself:
for instance when a man is guilty of incest with a blood-relation.
Therefore affinity is not caused by unlawful intercourse.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, unlawful intercourse is according to nature or against
nature. Now affinity is not caused by unnatural unlawful intercourse as
decided by law (can. Extraordinaria, xxxv, qu. 2,3). Therefore it is not
caused only by unlawful intercourse according to nature.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[3] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, He who is joined to a harlot is made one body (1 Cor.
6:16). Now this is the reason why marriage caused affinity. Therefore
unlawful intercourse does so for the same reason.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[3] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, carnal intercourse is the cause of affinity, as shown by the
definition of affinity, which definition is as follows: Affinity is the
relationship of persons which results from carnal intercourse and is
altogether void of blood-relationship. But there is carnal copulation
even in unlawful intercourse. Therefore unlawful intercourse causes
affinity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[3] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, According to the Philosopher (Ethic. viii, 12) the union
of husband and wife is said to be natural chiefly on account of the
procreation of offspring, and secondly on account of the community of
works: the former of which belongs to marriage by reason of carnal
copulation, and the latter, in so far as marriage is a partnership
directed to a common life. Now the former is to be found in every carnal
union where there is a mingling of seeds, since such a union may be
productive of offspring, but the latter may be wanting. Consequently
since marriage caused affinity, in so far as it was a carnal mingling, it
follows that also an unlawful intercourse causes affinity in so far as it
has something of natural copulation.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: In an unlawful intercourse there is something natural which
is common to fornication and marriage, and in this respect it causes
affinity. There is also something which is inordinate whereby it differs
from marriage, and in this respect it does not cause affinity. Hence
affinity remains honorable, although its cause is in a way dishonorable.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: There is no reason why diverse relations should not be in
the same subject by reason of different things. Consequently there can be
affinity and consanguinity between two persons, not only on account of
unlawful but also on account of lawful intercourse: for instance if a
blood-relation of mine on my father's side marries a blood-relation of
mine on my mother's side. Hence in the above definition the words "which
is altogether void of blood-relationship" apply to affinity as such. Nor
does it follow that a man by having intercourse with his blood-relation
contracts affinity with himself, since affinity, like consanguinity,
requires diversity of subjects, as likeness does.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: In unnatural copulation there is no mingling of seeds that
makes generation possible: wherefore a like intercourse does not cause
affinity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether affinity is caused by betrothal?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that affinity cannot be caused by betrothal. For
affinity is a lasting tie: whereas a betrothal is sometimes broken off.
Therefore it cannot cause affinity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further if the hymen be penetrated without the deed being
consummated, affinity is not contracted. Yet this is much more akin to
carnal intercourse than a betrothal. Therefore betrothal does not cause
affinity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[4] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, betrothal is nothing but a promise of future marriage.
Now sometimes there is a promise of future marriage without affinity
being contracted, for instance if it take place before the age of seven
years; or if a man having a perpetual impediment of impotence promise a
woman future marriage; or if a like promise be made between persons to
whom marriage is rendered unlawful by a vow; or in any other way
whatever. Therefore betrothal cannot cause affinity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[4] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, Pope Alexander (cap. Ad audiendem, De spons. et
matrim.) forbade a certain woman to marry a certain man, because she had
been betrothed to his brother. Now this would not be the case unless
affinity were contracted by betrothal. Therefore, etc.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[4] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Just as a betrothal has not the conditions of a perfect
marriage, but is a preparation for marriage, so betrothal causes not
affinity as marriage does, but something like affinity. This is called
"the justice of public honesty," which is an impediment to marriage even
as affinity and consanguinity are, and according to the same degrees, and
is defined thus: "The justice of public honesty is a relationship arising
out of betrothal, and derives its force from ecclesiastical institution
by reason of its honesty." This indicates the reason of its name as well
as its cause, namely that this relationship was instituted by the Church
on account of its honesty.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Betrothal, by reason not of itself but of the end to which
it is directed, causes this kind of affinity known as "the justice of
public honesty": wherefore just as marriage is a lasting tie, so is the
aforesaid kind of affinity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: In carnal intercourse man and woman become one flesh by the
mingling of seeds. Wherefore it is not every invasion or penetration of
the hymen that causes affinity to be contracted, but only such as is
followed by a mingling of seeds. But marriage causes affinity not only on
account of carnal intercourse, but also by reason of the conjugal
fellowship, in respect of which also marriage is according to nature.
Consequently affinity results from the marriage contract itself expressed
in words of the present and before its consummation, and in like manner
there results from betrothal, which is a promise of conjugal fellowship,
something akin to affinity, namely the justice of public honesty.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[4] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: All those impediments which void a betrothal prevent
affinity being contracted through a promise of marriage. Hence whether he
who actually promises marriage be lacking in age, or be under a solemn
vow of continence or any like impediment, no affinity nor anything akin
to it results because the betrothal is void. If however, a minor,
laboring under insensibility or malefice, having a perpetual impediment,
is betrothed before the age of puberty and after the age of seven years,
with a woman who is of age, from such a contract there results the
impediment called "justice of public honesty," because at the time the
impediment was not actual, since at that age the boy who is insensible is
equally impotent in respect of the act in question.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[5] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether affinity is a cause of affinity?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[5] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that affinity also is a cause of affinity. For Pope
Julius I says (cap. Contradicimus 35, qu. iii): "No man may marry his
wife's surviving blood-relation": and it is said in the next chapter
(cap. Porro duorum) that "the wives of two cousins are forbidden to
marry, one after the other, the same husband." But this is only on
account of affinity being contracted through union with a person related
by affinity. Therefore affinity is a cause of affinity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[5] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, carnal intercourse makes persons akin even as carnal
procreation, since the degrees of affinity and consanguinity are reckoned
equally. But consanguinity causes affinity. Therefore affinity does also.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[5] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, things that are the same with one and the same are the
same with one another. But the wife contracts the same relations with all
her husband's kindred. Therefore all her husband's kindred are made one
with all who are related by affinity to the wife, and thus affinity is
the cause of affinity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[5] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: On the contrary, If affinity is caused by affinity a man who has
connection with two women can marry neither of them, because then the one
would be related to the other by affinity. But this is false. Therefore
affinity does not cause affinity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[5] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, if affinity arose out of affinity a man by marrying
another man's widow would contract affinity with all her first husband's
kindred, since she is related to them by affinity. But this cannot be the
case because he would become especially related by affinity to her
deceased husband. Therefore, etc.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[5] Obj. 6 Para. 1/1
OBJ 6: Further, consanguinity is a stronger tie than affinity. But the
blood-relations of the wife do not become blood-relations of the husband.
Much less, therefore, does affinity to the wife cause affinity to her
blood-relations, and thus the same conclusion follows.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[5] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, There are two ways in which one thing proceeds from
another: in one way a thing proceeds from another in likeness of species,
as a man is begotten of a man: in another way one thing proceeds from
another, not in likeness of species; and this process is always towards a
lower species, as instanced in all equivocal agents. The first kind of
procession, however often it be repeated, the same species always
remains: thus if one man be begotten of another by an act of the
generative power, of this man also another man will be begotten, and so
on. But the second kind of procession, just as in the first instance it
produces another species, so it makes another species as often as it is
repeated. Thus by movement from a point there proceeds a line and not a
point, because a point by being moved makes a line; and from a line
moved lineally, there proceeds not a line but a surface, and from a
surface a body, and in this way the procession can go no further. Now in
the procession of kinship we find two kinds whereby this tie is caused:
one is by carnal procreation, and this always produces the same species
of relationship; the other is by the marriage union, and this produces a
different kind of relationship from the beginning: thus it is clear that
a married woman is related to her husband's blood-relations not by blood
but by affinity. Wherefore if this kind of process be repeated, the
result will be not affinity but another kind of relationship; and
consequently a married party contracts with the affines of the other
party a relation not of affinity but of some other kind which is called
affinity of the second kind. And again if a person through marriage
contracts relationship with an affine of the second kind, it will not be
affinity of the second kind, but of a third kind, as indicated in the
verse quoted above (A[1]). Formerly these two kinds were included in the
prohibition, under the head of the justice of public honesty rather than
under the head of affinity, because they fall short of true affinity, in
the same way as the relationship arising out of betrothal. Now however
they have ceased to be included in the prohibition, which now refers only
to the first kind of affinity in which true affinity consists.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[5] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: A husband contracts affinity of the first kind with his
wife's male blood-relation, and affinity of the second kind with the
latter's wife: wherefore if the latter man dies the former cannot marry
his widow on account of the second kind of affinity. Again if a man A
marry a widow B, C, a relation of her former husband being connected with
B by the first kind of affinity, contracts affinity of the second kind
with her husband A; and D, the wife of this relation C being connected,
by affinity of the second kind, with B, this man's wife contracts
affinity of the third kind with her husband A. And since the third kind
of affinity was included in the prohibition on account of a certain
honesty more than by reason of affinity, the canon (cap. Porro duorum 35,
qu. iii) says: "The justice of public honesty forbids the wives of two
cousins to be married to the same man, the one after the other." But this
prohibition is done away with.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[5] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Although carnal intercourse is a cause of people being
connected with one another, it is not the same kind of connection.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[5] R.O. 3 Para. 1/2
Reply OBJ 3: The wife contracts the same connection with her husband's
relatives as to the degree but not as to the kind of connection.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[5] R.O. 3 Para. 2/2
Since however the arguments in the contrary sense would seem to show
that no tie is caused by affinity, we must reply to them lest the
time-honored prohibition of the Church seem unreasonable.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[5] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: As stated above, a woman does not contract affinity of the
first kind with the man to whom she is united in the flesh, wherefore
she does not contract affinity of the second kind with a woman known by
the same man; and consequently if a man marry one of these women, the
other does not contract affinity of the third kind with him. And so the
laws of bygone times did not forbid the same man to marry successively
two women known by one man.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[5] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: As a man is not connected with his wife by affinity of the
first kind, so he does not contract affinity of the second kind with the
second husband of the same wife. Wherefore the argument does not prove.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[5] R.O. 6 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 6: One person is not connected with me through another, except
they be connected together. Hence through a woman who is affine to me, no
person becomes connected with me, except such as is connected with her.
Now this cannot be except through carnal procreation from her, or through
connection with her by marriage: and according to the olden legislation,
I contracted some kind of connection through her in both ways: because
her son even by another husband becomes affine to me in the same kind and
in a different degree of affinity, as appears from the rule given above:
and again her second husband becomes affine to me in the second kind of
affinity. But her other blood-relations are not connected with him, but
she is connected with them, either as with father or mother, inasmuch as
she descends from them, or, as with her brothers, as proceeding from the
same principle; wherefore the brother or father of my affine does not
become affine to me in any kind of affinity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[6] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether affinity is an impediment to marriage?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[6] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that affinity is not an impediment to marriage. For
nothing is an impediment to marriage except what is contrary thereto. But
affinity is not contrary to marriage since it is caused by it. Therefore
it is not an impediment to marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[6] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, by marriage the wife becomes a possession of the
husband. Now the husband's kindred inherit his possessions after his
death. Therefore they can succeed to his wife, although she is affine to
them, as shown above (A[5]). Therefore affinity is not an impediment to
marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[6] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, It is written (Lev. 18:8): "Thou shalt not uncover the
nakedness of thy father's wife." Now she is only affine. Therefore
affinity is an impediment to marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[6] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Affinity that precedes marriage hinders marriage being
contracted and voids the contract, for the same reason as consanguinity.
For just as there is a certain need for blood-relations to live together,
so is there for those who are connected by affinity: and just as there is
a tie of friendship between blood-relations, so is there between those
who are affine to one another. If, however, affinity supervene to
matrimony, it cannot void the marriage, as stated above (Q[50], A[7]).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[6] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Affinity is not contrary to the marriage which causes it,
but to a marriage being contracted with an affine, in so far as the
latter would hinder the extension of friendship and the curbing of
concupiscence, which are sought in marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[6] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The husband's possessions do not become one with him as the
wife is made one flesh with him. Wherefore just as consanguinity is an
impediment to marriage or union with the husband according to the flesh,
so is one forbidden to marry the husband's wife.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[7] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether affinity in itself admits of degrees?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[7] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that affinity in itself admits of degrees. For any
kind of propinquity can itself be the subject of degrees. Now affinity is
a kind of propinquity. Therefore it has degrees in itself apart from the
degrees of consanguinity by which it is caused.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[7] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, it is stated in the text (Sent. iv, D, 41) that the
child of a second marriage could not take a consort from within the
degrees of affinity of the first husband. But this would not be the case
unless the son of an affine were also affine. Therefore affinity like
consanguinity admits itself of degrees.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[7] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, Affinity is caused by consanguinity. Therefore all the
degrees of affinity are caused by the degrees of consanguinity: and so it
has no degrees of itself.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[7] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, A thing does not of itself admit of being divided except
in reference to something belonging to it by reason of its genus: thus
animal is divided into rational and irrational and not into white and
black. Now carnal procreation has a direct relation to consanguinity,
because the tie of consanguinity is immediately contracted through it;
whereas it has no relation to affinity except through consanguinity which
is the latter's cause. Wherefore since the degrees of relationship are
distinguished in reference to carnal procreation, the distinction of
degrees is directly and immediately referable to consanguinity, and to
affinity through consanguinity. Hence the general rule in seeking the
degrees of affinity is that in whatever degree of consanguinity I am
related to the husband, in that same degree of affinity I am related to
the wife.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[7] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The degrees in propinquity of relationship can only be
taken in reference to ascent and descent of propagation, to which
affinity is compared only through consanguinity. Wherefore affinity has
no direct degrees, but derives them according to the degrees of
consanguinity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[7] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Formerly it used to be said that the son of my affine by a
second marriage was affine to me, not directly but accidentally as it
were: wherefore he was forbidden to marry on account of the justice of
public honesty rather than affinity. And for this reason this prohibition
is now revoked.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[8] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the degrees of affinity extend in the same way as the degrees of
consanguinity?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[8] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the degrees of affinity do not extend in the
same way as the degrees of consanguinity. For the tie of affinity is less
strong than the tie of consanguinity, since affinity arises from
consanguinity in diversity of species, as from an equivocal cause. Now
the stronger the tie the longer it lasts. Therefore the tie of affinity
does not last to the same number of degrees as consanguinity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[8] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, human law should imitate Divine law. Now according to
the Divine law certain degrees of consanguinity were forbidden, in which
degrees affinity was not an impediment to marriage: as instanced in a
brother's wife whom a man could marry although he could not marry her
sister. Therefore now too the prohibition of affinity and consanguinity
should not extend to the same degrees.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[8] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, A woman is connected with me by affinity from the very
fact that she is married to a blood-relation of mine. Therefore in
whatever degree her husband is related to me by blood she is related to
me in that same degree by affinity: and so the degrees of affinity should
be reckoned in the same number as the degrees of consanguinity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[8] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Since the degrees of affinity are reckoned according to
the degrees of consanguinity, the degrees of affinity must needs be the
same in number as those of consanguinity. Nevertheless, affinity being a
lesser tie than consanguinity, both formerly and now, a dispensation is
more easily granted in the more remote degrees of affinity than in the
remote degrees of consanguinity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[8] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The fact that the tie of affinity is less than the tie of
consanguinity causes a difference in the kind of relationship but not in
the degrees. Hence this argument is not to the point.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[8] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: A man could not take his deceased brother's wife except, in
the case when the latter died without issue, in order to raise up seed to
his brother. This was requisite at a time when religious worship was
propagated by means of the propagation of the flesh, which is not the
case now. Hence it is clear that he did not marry her in his own person
as it were, but as supplying the place of his brother.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[9] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether a marriage contracted by persons with the degrees of affinity or
consanguinity should always be annulled?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[9] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that a marriage contracted by persons within the
degrees of affinity or consanguinity ought not always to be annulled by
divorce. For "what God hath joined together let no man put asunder" (Mt.
19:6). Since then it is understood that what the Church does God does,
and since the Church sometimes through ignorance joins such persons
together, it would seem that if subsequently this came to knowledge they
ought not to be separated.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[9] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the tie of marriage is less onerous than the tie of
ownership. Now after a long time a man may acquire by prescription the
ownership of a thing of which he was not the owner. Therefore by length
of time a marriage becomes good in law, although it was not so before.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[9] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, of like things we judge alike. Now if a marriage ought
to be annulled on account of consanguinity, in the case when two brothers
marry two sisters, if one be separated on account of consanguinity, the
other ought to be separated for the same reason. and yet this is not
seemly. Therefore a marriage ought not to be annulled on account of
affinity or consanguinity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[9] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, Consanguinity and affinity forbid the contracting of a
marriage and void the contract. Therefore if affinity or consanguinity be
proved, the parties should be separated even though they have actually
contracted marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[9] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Since all copulation apart from lawful marriage is a
mortal sin, which the Church uses all her endeavors to prevent, it
belongs to her to separate those between whom there cannot be valid
marriage, especially those related by blood or by affinity, who cannot
without incest be united in the flesh.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[9] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Although the Church is upheld by God's gift and authority,
yet in so far as she is an assembly of men there results in her acts
something of human frailty which is not Divine. Therefore a union
effected in the presence of the Church who is ignorant of an impediment
is not indissoluble by Divine authority, but is brought about contrary to
Divine authority through man's error, which being an error of fact
excuses from sin, as long as it remains. Hence when the impediment comes
to the knowledge of the Church, she ought to sever the aforesaid union.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[9] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: That which cannot be done without sin is not ratified by
any prescription, for as Innocent III says (Conc. Later. iv, can. 50:
cap. Non debent, De consang. et affinit.), "length of time does not
diminish sin but increases it": nor can it in any way legitimize a
marriage which could not take place between unlawful persons.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[9] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: In contentious suits between two persons the verdict does
not prejudice a third party, wherefore although the one brother's
marriage with the one sister is annulled on account of consanguinity, the
Church does not therefore annul the other marriage against which no
action is taken. Yet in the tribunal of the conscience the other brother
ought not on this account always to be bound to put away his wife,
because such accusations frequently proceed from ill-will, and are proved
by false witnesses. Hence he is not bound to form his conscience on what
has been done about the other marriage: but seemingly one ought to draw a
distinction, because either he has certain knowledge of the impediment of
his marriage, or he has an opinion about it, or he has neither. In the
first case, he can neither seek nor pay the debt, in the second, he must
pay, but not ask, in the third he can both pay and ask.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[10] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether it is necessary to proceed by way of accusation for the annulment
of a marriage contracted by persons related to each other by affinity or
consanguinity?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[10] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that one ought not to proceed by way of accusation
in order to sever a marriage contracted between persons related by
affinity or consanguinity. Because accusation is preceded by inscription*
whereby a man binds himself to suffer the punishment of retaliation, if
he fail to prove his accusation. [*The accuser was bound by Roman Law to
endorse (se inscribere) the writ of accusation; Cf. SS, Q[33], A[7]]. But
this is not required when a matrimonial separation is at issue. Therefore
accusation has no place then.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[10] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, in a matrimonial lawsuit only the relatives are heard,
as stated in the text (Sent. iv, D, 41). But in accusations even
strangers are heard. Therefore in a suit for matrimonial separation the
process is not by way of accusation.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[10] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, if a marriage ought to be denounced this should be done
especially where it is least difficult to sever the tie. Now this is when
only the betrothal has been contracted, and then it is not the marriage
that is denounced. Therefore accusation should never take place at any
other time.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[10] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, a man is not prevented from accusing by the fact that he
does not accuse at once. But this happens in marriage, for if he was
silent at first when the marriage was being contracted, he cannot
denounce the marriage afterwards without laying himself open to
suspicion. Therefore, etc.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[10] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, Whatever is unlawful can be denounced. But the marriage
of relatives by affinity and consanguinity is unlawful. Therefore it can
be denounced.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[10] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Accusation is instituted lest the guilty be tolerated as
though they were innocent. Now just as it happens through ignorance of
fact that a guilty man is reputed innocent, so it happens through
ignorance of a circumstance that a certain fact is deemed lawful whereas
it is unlawful. Wherefore just as a man is sometimes accused, so is a
fact sometimes an object of accusation. It is in this way that a marriage
is denounced, when through ignorance of an impediment it is deemed
lawful, whereas it is unlawful.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[10] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The punishment of retaliation takes place when a person is
accused of a crime, because then action is taken that he may be punished.
But when it is a deed that is accused, action is taken not for the
punishment of the doer, but in order to prevent what is unlawful. Hence
in a matrimonial suit the accuser does not bind himself to a punishment.
Moreover, the accusation may be made either in words or in writing,
provided the person who denounces the marriage denounced, and the
impediment for which it is denounced, be expressed.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[10] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Strangers cannot know of the consanguinity except from the
relatives, since these know with greater probability. Hence when these
are silent, a stranger is liable to be suspected of acting from ill-will
unless he wish the relatives to prove his assertion. Wherefore a stranger
is debarred from accusing when there are relatives who are silent, and by
whom he cannot prove his accusation. On the other hand the relatives,
however nearly related they be, are not debarred from accusing, when the
marriage is denounced on account of a perpetual impediment, which
prevents the contracting of the marriage and voids the contract. When,
however, the accusation is based on a denial of the contract having taken
place, the parents should be debarred from witnessing as being liable to
suspicion, except those of the party that is inferior in rank and wealth,
for they, one is inclined to think, would be willing for the marriage to
stand.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[10] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: If the marriage is not yet contracted and there is only a
betrothal, there can be no accusation, for what is not, cannot be
accused. But the impediment can be denounced lest the marriage be
contracted.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[10] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: He who is silent at first is sometimes heard afterwards if
he wish to denounce the marriage, and sometimes he is repulsed. This is
made clear by the Decretal (cap. Cum in tua, De his qui matrim. accus.
possunt.) which runs as follows: "If an accuser present himself after the
marriage has been contracted, since he did not declare himself when
according to custom, the banns were published in church, we may rightly
ask whether he should be allowed to voice his accusation. In this matter
we deem that a distinction should be made, so that if he who lodges
information against persons already married was absent from the diocese
at the time of the aforesaid publication, or if for some other reason
this could not come to his knowledge, for instance if through exceeding
stress of weakness and fever he was not in possession of his faculties,
or was of so tender years as to be too young to understand such matters,
or if he were hindered by some other lawful cause, his accusation should
be heard. otherwise without doubt he should be repulsed as open to
suspicion, unless he swear that the information lodged by him came to
his knowledge subsequently and that he is not moved by ill-will to make
his accusation."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[11] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether in a suit of this kind one should proceed by hearing witnesses in
the same way as in other suits?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[11] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that in such a suit one ought not to proceed by
hearing witnesses, in the same way as in other suits where any witnesses
may be called provided they be unexceptionable. But here strangers are
not admitted, although they be unexceptionable. Therefore, etc.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[11] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, witnesses who are suspected of private hatred or love
are debarred from giving evidence. Now relatives are especially open to
suspicion of love for one party, and hatred for the other. Therefore
their evidence should not be taken.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[11] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, marriage is a more favorable suit than those others in
which purely corporeal questions are at stake. Now in these the same
person cannot be both accuser and witness. Neither therefore can this be
in a matrimonial suit; and so it would appear that it is not right to
proceed by hearing witnesses in a suit of this kind.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[11] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, Witnesses are called in a suit in order to give the
judge evidence concerning matters of doubt. Now evidence should be
afforded the judge in this suit as in other suits, since he must not
pronounce a hasty judgment on what is not proven. Therefore here as in
other lawsuits witnesses should be called.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[11] Body Para. 1/2
I answer that, In this kind of lawsuit as in others, truth must be
unveiled by witnesses: yet, as the lawyers say, there are many things
peculiar to this suit; namely that "the same person can be accuser and
witness; that evidence is not taken 'on oath of calumny,' since it is a
quasi-spiritual lawsuit; that relatives are allowed as witnesses; that
the juridical order is not perfectly observed, since if the denunciation
has been made, and the suit is uncontested, the defendant may be
excommunicated if contumacious; that hearsay evidence is admitted; and
that witnesses may be called after the publication of the names of the
witnesses." All this is in order to prevent the sin that may occur in
such a union (cap. Quoties aliqui; cap. Super eo, De test. et attest.;
cap. Literas, De juram. calumn.).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[55] A[11] Body Para. 2/2
This suffices for the Replies to the Objections.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] Out. Para. 1/1
OF THE IMPEDIMENT OF SPIRITUAL RELATIONSHIP (FIVE ARTICLES)
We must now consider the impediment of spiritual relationship: under
which head there are five points of inquiry:
(1) Whether spiritual relationship is an impediment to marriage?
(2) From what cause is it contracted?
(3) Between whom?
(4) Whether it passes from husband to wife?
(5) Whether it passes to the father's carnal children?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether spiritual relationship is an impediment to marriage?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that spiritual relationship is not an impediment to
marriage. For nothing is an impediment to marriage save what is contrary
to a marriage good. Now spiritual relationship is not contrary to a
marriage good. Therefore it is not an impediment to marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, a perpetual impediment to marriage cannot stand together
with marriage. But spiritual relationship sometimes stands together with
marriage, as stated in the text (Sent. iv, D, 42), as when a man in a
case of necessity baptizes his own child, for then he contracts a
spiritual relationship with his wife, and yet the marriage is not
dissolved. Therefore spiritual relationship is not an impediment to
marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, union of the spirit does not pass to the flesh. But
marriage is a union of the flesh. Therefore since spiritual relationship
is a union of the spirit, it cannot become an impediment to marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[1] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, contraries have not the same effects. Now spiritual
relationship is apparently contrary to disparity of worship, since
spiritual relationship is a kinship resulting from the giving of a
sacrament or the intention of so doing [*See next Article, ad 3]: whereas
disparity of worship consists in the lack of a sacrament, as stated above
(Q[50], A[1]). Since then disparity of worship is an impediment to
matrimony, it would seem that spiritual relationship has not this effect.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[1] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, The holier the bond, the more is it to be safeguarded.
Now a spiritual bond is holier than a bodily tie: and since the tie of
bodily kinship is an impediment to marriage, it follows that spiritual
relationship should also be an impediment.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[1] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, in marriage the union of souls ranks higher than union of
bodies, for it precedes it. Therefore with much more reason can a
spiritual relationship hinder marriage than bodily relationship does.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Just as by carnal procreation man receives natural being,
so by the sacraments he receives the spiritual being of grace. Wherefore
just as the tie that is contracted by carnal procreation is natural to
man, inasmuch as he is a natural being, so the tie that is contracted
from the reception of the sacraments is after a fashion natural to man,
inasmuch as he is a member of the Church. Therefore as carnal
relationship hinders marriage, even so does spiritual relationship by
command of the Church. We must however draw a distinction in reference
to spiritual relationship, since either it precedes or follows marriage.
If it precedes, it hinders the contracting of marriage and voids the
contract. If it follows, it does not dissolve the marriage bond: but we
must draw a further distinction in reference to the marriage act. For
either the spiritual relationship is contracted in a case of necessity,
as when a father baptizes his child who is at the point of death---and
then it is not an obstacle to the marriage act on either side---or it is
contracted without any necessity and through ignorance, in which case if
the person whose action has occasioned the relationship acted with due
caution, it is the same with him as in the former case---or it is
contracted purposely and without any necessity, and then the person whose
action has occasioned the relationship, loses the right to ask for the
debt; but is bound to pay if asked, because the fault of the one party
should not be prejudicial to the other.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Although spiritual relationship does not hinder any of the
chief marriage goods, it hinders one of the secondary goods, namely the
extension of friendship, because spiritual relationship is by itself a
sufficient reason for friendship: wherefore intimacy and friendship with
other persons need to be sought by means of marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Marriage is a lasting bond, wherefore no supervening
impediment can sever it. Hence it happens sometimes that marriage and an
impediment to marriage stand together, but not if the impediment precedes.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: In marriage there is not only a bodily but also a spiritual
union: and consequently kinship of spirit proves an impediment thereto,
without spiritual kinship having to pass into a bodily relationship.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[1] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: There is nothing unreasonable in two things that are
contrary to one another being contrary to the same thing, as great and
small are contrary to equal. Thus disparity of worship and spiritual
relationship are opposed to marriage, because in one the distance is
greater, and in the other less, than required by marriage. Hence there is
an impediment to marriage in either case.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether spiritual relationship is contracted by baptism only?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that spiritual relationship is contracted by
Baptism only. For as bodily kinship is to bodily birth, so is spiritual
kinship to spiritual birth. Now Baptism alone is called spiritual birth.
Therefore spiritual kinship is contracted by Baptism only, even as only
by carnal birth is carnal kinship contracted.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, a character is imprinted in order as in Confirmation.
But spiritual relationship does not result from receiving orders.
Therefore it does not result from Confirmation but only from Baptism.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, sacraments are more excellent than sacramentals. Now
spiritual relationship does not result from certain sacraments, for
instance from Extreme Unction. Much less therefore does it result from
catechizing, as some maintain.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[2] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, many other sacramentals are attached to Baptism besides
catechizing. Therefore spiritual relationship is not contracted from
catechism any more than from the others.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[2] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, prayer is no less efficacious than instruction of
catechism for advancement in good. But spiritual relationship does not
result from prayer. Therefore it does not result from catechism.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[2] Obj. 6 Para. 1/1
OBJ 6: Further, the instruction given to the baptized by preaching to
them avails no less than preaching to those who are not yet baptized. But
no spiritual relationship results from preaching. Neither therefore does
it result from catechism.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[2] Obj. 7 Para. 1/1
OBJ 7: On the other hand, It is written (1 Cor. 4:15): "In Christ Jesus
by the gospel I have begotten you." Now spiritual birth causes spiritual
relationship. Therefore spiritual relationship results from the preaching
of the gospel and instruction, and not only from Baptism.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[2] Obj. 8 Para. 1/1
OBJ 8: Further, as original sin is taken away by Baptism, so is actual
sin taken away by Penance. Therefore just as Baptism causes spiritual
relationship, so also does Penance.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[2] Obj. 9 Para. 1/1
OBJ 9: Further, "father" denotes relationship. Now a man is called
another's spiritual father in respect of Penance, teaching, pastoral care
and many other like things. Therefore spiritual relationship is
contracted from many other sources besides Baptism and Confirmation.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, There are three opinions on this question. Some say that
as spiritual regeneration is bestowed by the sevenfold grace of the Holy
Ghost, it is caused by means of seven things, beginning with the first
taste of blessed salt and ending with Confirmation given by the bishop:
and they say that spiritual relationship is contracted by each of these
seven things. But this does not seem reasonable, for carnal relationship
is not contracted except by a perfect act of generation. Wherefore
affinity is not contracted except there be mingling of seeds, from which
it is possible for carnal generation to follow. Now spiritual generation
is not perfected except by a sacrament: wherefore it does not seem
fitting for spiritual relationship to be contracted otherwise than
through a sacrament. Hence others say that spiritual relationship is only
contracted through three sacraments, namely catechism, Baptism and
Confirmation, but these do not apparently know the meaning of what they
say, since catechism is not a sacrament but a sacramental. Wherefore
others say that it is contracted through two sacraments only, namely
Confirmation and Baptism, and this is the more common opinion. Some
however of these say that catechism is a weak impediment, since it
hinders the contracting of marriage but does not void the contract.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Carnal birth is twofold. The first is in the womb, wherein
that which is born is a weakling and cannot come forth without danger:
and to this birth regeneration by Baptism is likened; wherein a man is
regenerated as though yet needing to be fostered in the womb of the
Church. The second is birth from out of the womb, when that which was
born in the womb is so far strengthened that it can without danger face
the outer world which has a natural corruptive tendency. To this is
likened Confirmation, whereby man being strengthened goes forth abroad to
confess the name of Christ. Hence spiritual relationship is fittingly
contracted through both these sacraments.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The effect of the sacrament of order is not regeneration
but the bestowal of power, for which reason it is not conferred on women,
and consequently no impediment to marriage can arise therefrom. Hence
this kind of relationship does not count.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: In catechism one makes a profession of future Baptism, just
as in betrothal one enters an engagement of future marriage. Wherefore
just as in betrothal a certain kind of propinquity is contracted, so is
there in catechism, whereby marriage is rendered at least unlawful, as
some say; but not in the other sacraments.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[2] R.O. 4 Para. 1/2
Reply OBJ 4: There is not made a profession of faith in the other
sacramentals of Baptism, as in catechism: wherefore the comparison fails.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[2] R.O. 4 Para. 2/2
The same answer applies to the Fifth and Sixth Objections.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[2] R.O. 7 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 7: The Apostle had instructed them in the faith by a kind of
catechism; and consequently his instruction was directed to their
spiritual birth.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[2] R.O. 8 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 8: Properly speaking a spiritual relationship is not
contracted through the sacrament of Penance. Wherefore a priest's son can
marry a woman whose confession the priest has heard, else in the whole
parish he could not find a woman whom he could marry. Nor does it matter
that by Penance actual sin is taken away, for this is not a kind of
birth, but a kind of healing. Nevertheless Penance occasions a kind of
bond between the woman penitent and the priest, that has a resemblance to
spiritual relationship, so that if he have carnal intercourse with her,
he sins as grievously as if she were his spiritual daughter. The reason
of this is that the relations between priest and penitent are most
intimate, and consequently in order to remove the occasion of sin this
prohibition [*Can. Omnes quos, and seqq., Caus. xxx] was made.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[2] R.O. 9 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 9: A spiritual father is so called from his likeness to a
carnal father. Now as the Philosopher says (Ethic. viii, 2) a carnal
father gives his child three things, being nourishment and instruction:
and consequently a person's spiritual father is so called from one of
these three things. Nevertheless he has not, through being his spiritual
father, a spiritual relationship with him, unless he is like a (carnal)
father as to generation which is the way to being. This solution may also
be applied to the foregoing Eighth Objection.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether spiritual relationship is contracted between the person baptized
and the person who raises him from the sacred font?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that spiritual relationship is not contracted
between the person baptized and the person who raises him from the sacred
font. For in carnal generation carnal relationship is contracted only on
the part of the person of whose seed the child is born; and not on the
part of the person who receives the child after birth. Therefore neither
is spiritual relationship contracted between the receiver and the
received at the sacred font.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, he who raises a person from the sacred font is called
{anadochos} by Dionysius (Eccl. Hier. ii): and it is part of his office
to instruct the child. But instruction is not a sufficient cause of
spiritual relationship, as stated above (A[2]). Therefore no relationship
is contracted between him and the person whom he raises from the sacred
font.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, it may happen that someone raises a person from the
sacred font before he himself is baptized. Now spiritual relationship is
not contracted in such a case, since one who is not baptized is not
capable of spirituality. Therefore raising a person from the sacred font
is not sufficient to contract a spiritual relationship.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[3] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, There is the definition of spiritual relationship
quoted above (A[1]), as also the authorities mentioned in the text (Sent.
iv, D, 42).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[3] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Just as in carnal generation a person is born of a father
and mother, so in spiritual generation a person is born again a son of
God as Father, and of the Church as Mother. Now while he who confers the
sacrament stands in the place of God, whose instrument and minister he
is, he who raises a baptized person from the sacred font, or holds the
candidate for Confirmation, stands in the place of the Church. Therefore
spiritual relationship is contracted with both.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Not only the father, of whose seed the child is born, is
related carnally to the child, but also the mother who provides the
matter, and in whose womb the child is begotten. So too the godparent who
in place of the Church offers and raises the candidate for Baptism and
holds the candidate for Confirmation contracts spiritual relationship.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: He contracts spiritual relationship not by reason of the
instruction it is his duty to give, but on account of the spiritual birth
in which he co-operates.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: A person who is not baptized cannot raise anyone from the
sacred font, since he is not a member of the Church whom the godparent in
Baptism represents: although he can baptize, because he is a creature of
God Whom the baptizer represents. And yet he cannot contract a spiritual
relationship, since he is void of spiritual life to which man is first
born by receiving Baptism.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether spiritual relationship passes from husband to wife?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that spiritual relationship does not pass from
husband to wife. For spiritual and bodily union are disparate and differ
generically. Therefore carnal union which is between husband and wife
cannot be the means of contracting a spiritual relationship.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the godfather and godmother have more in common in the
spiritual birth that is the cause of spiritual relationship, than a
husband, who is godfather, has with his wife. Now godfather and godmother
do not hereby contract spiritual relationship. Therefore neither does a
wife contract a spiritual relationship through her husband being
godfather to someone.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[4] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, it may happen that the husband is baptized, and his wife
not, for instance when he is converted from unbelief without his wife
being converted. Now spiritual relationship cannot be contracted by one
who is not baptized. Therefore it does not always pass from husband to
wife.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[4] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, husband and wife together can raise a person from the
sacred font, since no law forbids it. If therefore spiritual relationship
passed from husband to wife, it would follow that each of them is twice
godfather or godmother of the same individual: which is absurd.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[4] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, Spiritual goods are more communicable than bodily
goods. But the bodily consanguinity of the husband passes to his wife by
affinity. Much more therefore does spiritual relationship.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[4] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, A may become co-parent with B in two ways. First, by the
act of another (B), who baptizes A's child, or raises him in Baptism. In
this way spiritual relationship does not pass from husband to wife,
unless perchance it be his wife's child, for then she contracts spiritual
relationship directly, even as her husband. Secondly, by his own act, for
instance when he raises B's child from the sacred font, and thus
spiritual relationship passes to the wife if he has already had carnal
knowledge of her, but not if the marriage be not yet consummated, since
they are not as yet made one flesh: and this is by way of a kind of
affinity; wherefore it would seem on the same grounds to pass to a woman
of whom he has carnal knowledge, though she be not his wife. Hence the
verse: "I may not marry my own child's godmother, nor the mother of my
godchild: but I may marry the godmother of my wife's child."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: From the fact that corporal and spiritual union differ
generically we may conclude that the one is not the other, but not that
the one cannot cause the other, since things of different genera
sometimes cause one another either directly or indirectly.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/2
Reply OBJ 2: The godfather and godmother of the same person are not
united in that person's spiritual birth save accidentally, since one of
them would be self-sufficient for the purpose. Hence it does not follow
from this that any spiritual relationship results between them whereby
they are hindered from marrying one another. Hence the verse:
"Of two co-parents one is always spiritual, the other carnal: this rule
is infallible."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 2/2
On the other hand, marriage by itself makes husband and wife one flesh:
wherefore the comparison fails.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[4] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: If the wife be not baptized, the spiritual relationship
will not reach her, because she is not a fit subject, and not because
spiritual relationship cannot pass from husband to wife through marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[4] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: Since no spiritual relationship results between godfather
and godmother, nothing prevents husband and wife from raising together
someone from the sacred font. Nor is it absurd that the wife become twice
godmother of the same person from different causes, just as it is
possible for her to be connected in carnal relationship both by affinity
and consanguinity to the same person.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[5] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether spiritual relationship passes to the godfather's carnal children?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[5] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that spiritual relationship does not pass to the
godfather's carnal children. For no degrees are assigned to spiritual
relationship. Yet there would be degrees if it passed from father to son,
since the person begotten involves a change of degree, as stated above
(Q[55], A[5]). Therefore it does not pass to the godfather's carnal sons.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[5] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, father and son are related in the same degree as brother
and brother. If therefore spiritual relationship passes from father to
son, it will equally pass from brother to brother: and this is false.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[5] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, This is proved by authority quoted in the text (Sent.
iv, D, 42).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[5] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, A son is something of his father and not conversely
(Ethic. viii, 12): wherefore spiritual relationship passes from father to
his carnal son and not conversely. Thus it is clear that there are three
spiritual relationships: one called spiritual fatherhood between
godfather and godchild; another called co-paternity between the godparent
and carnal parent of the same person; and the third is called spiritual
brotherhood, between godchild and the carnal children of the same parent.
Each of these hinders the contracting of marriage and voids the contract.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[5] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The addition of a person by carnal generation entails a
degree with regard to a person connected by the same kind of
relationship, but not with regard to one connected by another kind of
relationship. Thus a son is connected with his father's wife in the same
degree as his father, but by another kind of relationship. Now spiritual
relationship differs in kind from carnal. Wherefore a godson is not
related to his godfather's carnal son in the same degree as the latter's
father is related to him, through whom the spiritual relationship is
contracted. Consequently it does not follow that spiritual relationship
admits of degrees.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[56] A[5] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: A man is not part of his brother as a son is of his father.
But a wife is part of her husband, since she is made one with him in
body. Consequently the relationship does not pass from brother to
brother, whether the brother be born before or after spiritual
brotherhood.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[57] Out. Para. 1/1
OF LEGAL RELATIONSHIP, WHICH IS BY ADOPTION (THREE ARTICLES)
We must now consider legal relationship which is by adoption. Under this
head there are three points of inquiry:
(1) What is adoption?
(2) Whether one contracts through it a tie that is an impediment to
marriage?
(3) Between which persons is this tie contracted.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[57] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether adoption is rightly defined?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[57] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that adoption is not rightly defined: "Adoption is
the act by which a person lawfully takes for his child or grandchild and
so on one who does not belong to him." For the child should be subject to
its father. Now, sometimes the person adopted does not come under the
power of the adopter. Therefore adoption is not always the taking of
someone as a child.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[57] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, "Parents should lay up for their children" (2 Cor.
12:14). But the adoptive father does not always necessarily lay up for
his adopted child, since sometimes the adopted does not inherit the
goods of the adopter. Therefore adoption is not the taking of someone as
a child.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[57] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, adoption, whereby someone is taken as a child, is
likened to natural procreation whereby a child is begotten naturally.
Therefore whoever is competent to beget a child naturally is competent to
adopt. But this is untrue, since neither one who is not his own master,
nor one who is not twenty-five years of age, nor a woman can adopt, and
yet they can beget a child naturally. Therefore, properly speaking,
adoption is not the taking of someone as a child.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[57] A[1] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, to take as one's child one who is not one's own seems
necessary in order to supply the lack of children begotten naturally. Now
one who is unable to beget, through being a eunuch or impotent, suffers
especially from the absence of children of his own begetting. Therefore
he is especially competent to adopt someone as his child. But he is not
competent to adopt. Therefore adoption is not the taking of someone as
one's child.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[57] A[1] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, in spiritual relationship, where someone is taken as a
child without carnal procreation, it is of no consequence whether an
older person become the father of a younger, or "vice versa," since a
youth can baptize an old man and "vice versa." Therefore, if by adoption
a person is taken as a child without being carnally begotten, it would
make no difference whether an older person adopted a younger, or a
younger an older person; which is not true. Therefore the same conclusion
follows.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[57] A[1] Obj. 6 Para. 1/1
OBJ 6: Further, there is no difference of degree between adopted and
adopter. Therefore whoever is adopted, is adopted as a child; and
consequently it is not right to say that one may be adopted as a
grandchild.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[57] A[1] Obj. 7 Para. 1/1
OBJ 7: Further, adoption is a result of love, wherefore God is said to
have adopted us as children through charity. Now we should have greater
charity towards those who are connected with us than towards strangers.
Therefore adoption should be not of a stranger but of someone connected
with us.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[57] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Art imitates nature and supplies the defect of nature
where nature is deficient. Hence just as a man begets by natural
procreation, so by positive law which is the art of what is good and
just, one person can take to himself another as a child in likeness to
one that is his child by nature, in order to take the place of the
children he has lost, this being the chief reason why adoption was
introduced. And since taking implies a term "wherefrom," for which reason
the taker is not the thing taken, it follows that the person taken as a
child must be a stranger. Accordingly, just as natural procreation has a
term "whereto," namely the form which is the end of generation, and a
term "wherefrom," namely the contrary form, so legal generation has a
term "whereto," namely a child or grandchild, and a term "wherefrom,"
namely, a stranger. Consequently the above definition includes the genus
of adoption, for it is described as a "lawful taking," and the term
"wherefrom," since it is said to be the taking of "a stranger," and the
term "whereto," because it says, "as a child or grandchild ."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[57] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/2
Reply OBJ 1: The sonship of adoption is an imitation of natural sonship.
Wherefore there are two species of adoption, one which imitates natural
sonship perfectly, and this is called "arrogatio," whereby the person
adopted is placed under the power of the adopter; and one who is thus
adopted inherits from his adopted father if the latter die intestate, nor
can his father legally deprive him of a fourth part of his inheritance.
But no one can adopt in this way except one who is his own master, one
namely who has no father or, if he has, is of age. There can be no
adoption of this kind without the authority of the sovereign. The other
kind of adoption imitates natural sonship imperfectly, and is called
"simple adoption," and by this the adopted does not come under the power
of the adopter: so that it is a disposition to perfect adoption, rather
than perfect adoption itself. In this way even one who is not his own
master can adopt, without the consent of the sovereign and with the
authority of a magistrate: and one who is thus adopted does not inherit
the estate of the adopter, nor is the latter bound to bequeath to him any
of his goods in his will, unless he will.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[57] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 2/2
This suffices for the Reply to the Second Objection.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[57] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Natural procreation is directed to the production of the
species; wherefore anyone in whom the specific nature is not hindered is
competent to be able to beget naturally. But adoption is directed to
hereditary succession, wherefore those alone are competent to adopt who
have the power to dispose of their estate. Consequently one who is not
his own master, or who is less than twenty-five years of age, or a woman,
cannot adopt anyone, except by special permission of the sovereign.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[57] A[1] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: An inheritance cannot pass to posterity through one who has
a perpetual impediment from begetting: hence for this very reason it
ought to pass to those who ought to succeed to him by right of
relationship; and consequently he cannot adopt, as neither can he beget.
Moreover greater is sorrow for children lost than for children one has
never had. Wherefore those who are impeded from begetting need no solace
for their lack of children as those who have had and have lost them, or
could have had them but have them not by reason of some accidental
impediment.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[57] A[1] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: Spiritual relationship is contracted through a sacrament
whereby the faithful are born again in Christ, in Whom there is no
difference between male and female, bondman and free, youth and old age
(Gal. 3:28; Col. 3:11). Wherefore anyone can indifferently become
another's godfather. But adoption aims at hereditary succession and a
certain subjection of the adopted to the adopter: and it is not fitting
that older persons should be subjected to younger in the care of the
household. Consequently a younger person cannot adopt an older; but
according to law the adopted person must be so much younger than the
adopter, that he might have been the child of his natural begetting.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[57] A[1] R.O. 6 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 6: One may lose one's grandchildren and so forth even as one
may lose one's children. Wherefore since adoption was introduced as a
solace for children lost, just as someone may be adopted in place of a
child, so may someone be adopted in place of a grandchild and so on.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[57] A[1] R.O. 7 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 7: A relative ought to succeed by right of relationship; and
therefore such a person is not competent to be chosen to succeed by
adoption. And if a relative, who is not competent to inherit the estate,
be adopted, he is adopted not as a relative, but as a stranger lacking
the right of succeeding to the adopter's goods.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[57] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether a tie that is an impediment to marriage is contracted through
adoption?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[57] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that there is not contracted through adoption a tie
that is an impediment to marriage. For spiritual care is more excellent
than corporeal care. But no tie of relationship is contracted through
one's being subjected to another's spiritual care: else all those who
dwell in the parish would be related to the parish priest and would be
unable to marry his son. Neither therefore can this result from adoption
which places the adopted under the care of the adopter.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[57] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, no tie of relationship results from persons conferring a
benefit on another. But adoption is nothing but the conferring of a
benefit. Therefore no tie of relationship results from adoption.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[57] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, a natural father provides for his child chiefly in three
things, as the Philosopher states (Ethic. viii, 11,12), namely by giving
him being, nourishment and education; and hereditary succession is
subsequent to these. Now no tie of relationship is contracted by one's
providing for a person's nourishment and education, else a person would
be related to his nourishers, tutors and masters, which is false.
Therefore neither is any relationship contracted through adoption by
which one inherits another's estate.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[57] A[2] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, the sacraments of the Church are not subject to human
laws. Now marriage is a sacrament of the Church. Since then adoption was
introduced by human law, it would seem that a tie contracted from
adoption cannot be an impediment to marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[57] A[2] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, Relationship is an impediment to marriage. Now a kind
of relationship results from adoption, namely legal relationship, as
evidenced by its definition, for "legal relationship is a connection
arising out of adoption." Therefore adoption results in a tie which is
an impediment to marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[57] A[2] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, the same is proved by the authorities quoted in the text (Sent.
iv, D, 42).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[57] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, The Divine law especially forbids marriage between those
persons who have to live together lest, as Rabbi Moses observes (Doc.
Perp. iii, 49), if it were lawful for them to have carnal intercourse,
there should be more room for concupiscence to the repression of which
marriage is directed. And since the adopted child dwells in the house of
his adopted father like one that is begotten naturally human laws forbid
the contracting of marriage between the like, and this prohibition is
approved by the Church. Hence it is that legal adoption is an impediment
to marriage. This suffices for the Replies to the first three Objections,
because none of those things entails such a cohabitation as might be an
incentive to concupiscence. Therefore they do not cause a relationship
that is an impediment to marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[57] A[2] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: The prohibition of a human law would not suffice to make an
impediment to marriage, unless the authority of the Church intervenes by
issuing the same prohibition.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[57] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether legal relationship is contracted only between the adopting father
and the adopted child?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[57] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that a relationship of this kind is contracted only
between the adopting father and the adopted child. For it would seem that
it ought above all to be contracted between the adopting father and the
natural mother of the adopted, as happens in spiritual relationship. Yet
there is no legal relationship between them. Therefore it is not
contracted between any other persons besides the adopter and adopted.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[57] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the relationship that impedes marriage is a perpetual
impediment. But there is not a perpetual impediment between the adopted
son and the naturally begotten daughter of the adopted; because when the
adoption terminates at the death of the adopter, or when the adopted
comes of age, the latter can marry her. Therefore he was not related to
her in such a way as to prevent him from marrying her.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[57] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, spiritual relationship passes to no person incapable of
being a god-parent; wherefore it does not pass to one who is not
baptized. Now a woman cannot adopt, as stated above (A[1], ad 2).
Therefore legal relationship does not pass from husband to wife.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[57] A[3] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, spiritual relationship is stronger than legal. But
spiritual relationship does not pass to a grandchild. Neither, therefore,
does legal relationship.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[57] A[3] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, Legal relationship is more in agreement with carnal
union or procreation than spiritual relationship is. But spiritual
relationship passes to another person. Therefore legal relationship does
so also.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[57] A[3] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, the same is proved by the authorities quoted in the text (Sent.
iv, D, 42).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[57] A[3] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Legal relationship is of three kinds. The first is in the
descending order as it were, and is contracted between the adoptive
father and the adopted child, the latter's child grandchild and so on;
the second is between the adopted child and the naturally begotten child;
the third is like a kind of affinity, and is between the adoptive father
and the wife of the adopted son, or contrariwise between the adopted son
and the wife of the adoptive father. Accordingly the first and third
relationships are perpetual impediments to marriage: but the second is
not, but only so long as the adopted person remains under the power of
the adoptive father, wherefore when the father dies or when the child
comes of age, they can be married.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[57] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: By spiritual generation the son is not withdrawn from the
father's power, as in the case of adoption, so that the godson remains
the son of both at the same time, whereas the adopted son does not. Hence
no relationship is contracted between the adoptive father and the natural
mother or father, as was the case in spiritual relationship.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[57] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Legal relationship is an impediment to marriage on account
of the parties dwelling together: hence when the need for dwelling
together ceases, it is not unreasonable that the aforesaid tie cease, for
instance when he ceases to be under the power of the same father. But the
adoptive father and his wife always retain a certain authority over their
adopted son and his wife, wherefore the tie between them remains.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[57] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Even a woman can adopt by permission of the sovereign,
wherefore legal relationship passes also to her. Moreover the reason why
spiritual relationship does not pass to a non-baptized person is not
because such a person cannot be a god-parent but because he is not a fit
subject of spirituality.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[57] A[3] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: By spiritual relationship the son is not placed under the
power and care of the godfather, as in legal relationship: because it is
necessary that whatever is in the son's power pass under the power of the
adoptive father. Wherefore if a father be adopted the children and
grandchildren who are in the power of the person adopted are adopted also.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] Out. Para. 1/1
OF THE IMPEDIMENTS OF IMPOTENCE, SPELL, FRENZY OR MADNESS, INCEST AND
DEFECTIVE AGE (FIVE ARTICLES)
We must now consider five impediments to marriage, namely the
impediments of impotence, spell, frenzy or madness, incest, and defective
age. Under this head there are five points of inquiry:
(1) Whether impotence is an impediment to marriage?
(2) Whether a spell is?
(3) Whether frenzy or madness is?
(4) Whether incest is?
(5) Whether defective age is?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether impotence is an impediment to marriage?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that impotence is not an impediment to marriage.
For carnal copulation is not essential to marriage, since marriage is
more perfect when both parties observe continency by vow. But impotence
deprives marriage of nothing save carnal copulation. Therefore it is not
a diriment impediment to the marriage contract.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, just as impotence prevents carnal copulation so does
frigidity. But frigidity is not reckoned an impediment to marriage.
Therefore neither should impotence be reckoned as such.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, all old people are frigid. Yet old people can marry.
Therefore, etc.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[1] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, if the woman knows the man to be frigid when she marries
him, the marriage is valid. Therefore frigidity, considered in itself, is
not an impediment to marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[1] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, calidity may prove a sufficient incentive to carnal
copulation with one who is not a virgin, but not with one who is, because
it happens to be so weak as to pass away quickly, and is therefore
insufficient for the deflowering of a virgin. Or again it may move a man
sufficiently in regard to a beautiful woman, but insufficiently in regard
to an uncomely one. Therefore it would seem that frigidity, although it
be an impediment in regard to one, is not an impediment absolutely.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[1] Obj. 6 Para. 1/1
OBJ 6: Further, generally speaking woman is more frigid than man. But
women are not debarred from marriage. Neither therefore should men be
debarred on account of frigidity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[1] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, It is stated (Extra, De Frigidis et Malefic., cap. Quod
Sedem): "Just as a boy who is incapable of marital intercourse is unfit
to marry, so also those who are impotent are deemed most unfit for the
marriage contract." Now persons affected with frigidity are the like.
Therefore, etc.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[1] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, no one can bind himself to the impossible. Now in marriage man
binds himself to carnal copulation; because it is for this purpose that
he gives the other party power over his body. Therefore a frigid person,
being incapable of carnal copulation, cannot marry.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, In marriage there is a contract whereby one is bound to
pay the other the marital debt: wherefore just as in other contracts,
the bond is unfitting if a person bind himself to what he cannot give or
do, so the marriage contract is unfitting, if it be made by one who
cannot pay the marital debt. This impediment is called by the general
name of impotence as regards coition, and can arise either from an
intrinsic and natural cause, or from an extrinsic and accidental cause,
for instance spell, of which we shall speak later (A[2]). If it be due to
a natural cause, this may happen in two ways. For either it is temporary,
and can be remedied by medicine, or by the course of time, and then it
does not void a marriage: or it is perpetual and then it voids marriage,
so that the party who labors under this impediment remains for ever
without hope of marriage, while the other may "marry to whom she will . .
in the Lord" (1 Cor. 7:39). In order to ascertain whether the
impediment be perpetual or not, the Church has appointed a fixed time,
namely three years, for putting the matter to a practical proof: and if
after three years, during which both parties have honestly endeavored to
fulfil their marital intercourse, the marriage remain unconsummated, the
Church adjudges the marriage to be dissolved. And yet the Church is
sometimes mistaken in this, because three years are sometimes
insufficient to prove impotence to be perpetual. Wherefore if the Church
find that she has been mistaken, seeing that the subject of the
impediment has completed carnal copulation with another or with the same
person, she reinstates the former marriage and dissolves the subsequent
one, although the latter has been contracted with her permission.
[*"Nowadays it is seldom necessary to examine too closely into this
matter, as all cases arising from it are treated as far as possible under
the form of dispensations of non-consummated marriages." Cf. Catholic
Encyclopedia, article Canonical Impediments.]
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Although the act of carnal copulation is not essential to
marriage, ability to fulfill the act is essential, because marriage gives
each of the married parties power over the other's body in relation to
marital intercourse.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Excessive calidity can scarcely be a perpetual impediment.
If, however, it were to prove an impediment to marital intercourse for
three years it would be adjudged to be perpetual. Nevertheless, since
frigidity is a greater and more frequent impediment (for it not only
hinders the mingling of seeds but also weakens the members which
co-operate in the union of bodies), it is accounted an impediment rather
than calidity, since all natural defects are reduced to frigidity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Although old people have not sufficient calidity to
procreate, they have sufficient to copulate. Wherefore they are allowed
to marry, in so far as marriage is intended as a remedy, although it does
not befit them as fulfilling an office of nature.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[1] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: In all contracts it is agreed on all hands that anyone who
is unable to satisfy an obligation is unfit to make a contract which
requires the fulfilling of that obligation. Now this inability is of two
kinds. First, because a person is unable to fulfill the obligation "de
jure," and such inability renders the contract altogether void, whether
the party with whom he contracts knows of this or not. Secondly, because
he is unable to fulfill "de facto"; and then if the party with whom he
contracts knows of this and, notwithstanding, enters the contract, this
shows that the latter seeks some other end from the contract, and the
contract stands. But if he does not know of it the contract is void.
Consequently frigidity which causes such an impotence that a man cannot
"de facto" pay the marriage debt, as also the condition of slavery,
whereby a man cannot "de facto" give his service freely, are impediments
to marriage, when the one married party does not know that the other is
unable to pay the marriage debt. But an impediment whereby a person
cannot pay the marriage debt "de jure," for instance consanguinity, voids
the marriage contract, whether the other party knows of it or not. For
this reason the Master holds (Sent. iv, D, 34) that these two
impediments, frigidity and slavery, make it not altogether unlawful for
their subjects to marry.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[1] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: A man cannot have a perpetual natural impediment in regard
to one person and not in regard to another. But if he cannot fulfill the
carnal act with a virgin, while he can with one who is not a virgin, the
hymeneal membrane may be broken by a medical instrument, and thus he may
have connection with her. Nor would this be contrary to nature, for it
would be done not for pleasure but for a remedy. Dislike for a woman is
not a natural cause, but an accidental extrinsic cause: and therefore we
must form the same judgment in its regard as about spells, of which we
shall speak further on (A[2]).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[1] R.O. 6 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 6: The male is the agent in procreation, and the female is the
patient, wherefore greater calidity is required in the male than in the
female for the act of procreation. Hence the frigidity which renders the
man impotent would not disable the woman. Yet there may be a natural
impediment from another cause, namely stricture, and then we must judge
of stricture in the woman in the same way as of frigidity in the man.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether a spell can be an impediment to marriage?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that a spell cannot be an impediment to marriage.
For the spells in question are caused by the operation of demons. But the
demons have no more power to prevent the marriage act than other bodily
actions; and these they cannot prevent, for thus they would upset the
whole world if they hindered eating and walking and the like. Therefore
they cannot hinder marriage by spells.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, God's work is stronger than the devil's. But a spell is
the work of the devil. Therefore it cannot hinder marriage which is the
work of God.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, no impediment, unless it be perpetual, voids the
marriage contract. But a spell cannot be a perpetual impediment, for
since the devil has no power over others than sinners, the spell will be
removed if the sin be cast out, or by another spell, or by the exorcisms
of the Church which are employed for the repression of the demon's power.
Therefore a spell cannot be an impediment to marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[2] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, carnal copulation cannot be hindered, unless there be an
impediment to the generative power which is its principle. But the
generative power of one man is equally related to all women. Therefore a
spell cannot be an impediment in respect of one woman without being so
also in respect of all.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[2] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, It is stated in the Decretals (XXXIII, qu. 1, cap. iv):
"If by sorcerers or witches . . . ," and further on, "if they be
incurable, they must be separated."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[2] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, the demons' power is greater than man's: "There is no power
upon earth that can be compared with him who was made to fear no one"
(Job 41:24). Now through the action of man, a person may be rendered
incapable of carnal copulation by some power or by castration; and this
is an impediment to marriage. Therefore much more can this be done by the
power of a demon.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[2] Body Para. 1/3
I answer that, Some have asserted that witchcraft is nothing in the
world but an imagining of men who ascribed to spells those natural
effects the causes of which are hidden. But this is contrary to the
authority of holy men who state that the demons have power over men's
bodies and imaginations, when God allows them: wherefore by their means
wizards can work certain signs. Now this opinion grows from the root of
unbelief or incredulity, because they do not believe that demons exist
save only in the imagination of the common people, who ascribe to the
demon the terrors which a man conjures from his thoughts, and because,
owing to a vivid imagination, certain shapes such as he has in his
thoughts become apparent to the senses, and then he believes that he sees
the demons. But such assertions are rejected by the true faith whereby we
believe that angels fell from heaven, and that the demons exist, and that
by reason of their subtle nature they are able to do many things which we
cannot; and those who induce them to do such things are called wizards.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[2] Body Para. 2/3
Wherefore others have maintained that witchcraft can set up an
impediment to carnal copulation, but that no such impediment is
perpetual: hence it does not void the marriage contract, and they say
that the laws asserting this have been revoked. But this is contrary to
actual facts and to the new legislation which agrees with the old.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[2] Body Para. 3/3
We must therefore draw a distinction: for the inability to copulate
caused by witchcraft is either perpetual and then it voids marriage, or
it is not perpetual and then it does not void marriage. And in order to
put this to practical proof the Church has fixed the space of three years
in the same way as we have stated with regard to frigidity (A[1]). There
is, however this difference between a spell and frigidity, that a person
who is impotent through frigidity is equally impotent in relation to one
as to another, and consequently when the marriage is dissolved, he is not
permitted to marry another woman. whereas through witchcraft a man may be
rendered impotent in relation to one woman and not to another, and
consequently when the Church adjudges the marriage to be dissolved, each
party is permitted to seek another partner in marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The first corruption of sin whereby man became the slave of
the devil was transmitted to us by the act of the generative power, and
for this reason God allows the devil to exercise his power of witchcraft
in this act more than in others. Even so the power of witchcraft is made
manifest in serpents more than in other animals according to Gn. 3, since
the devil tempted the woman through a serpent.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: God's work may be hindered by the devil's work with God's
permission; not that the devil is stronger than God so as to destroy His
works by violence.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Some spells are so perpetual that they can have no human
remedy, although God might afford a remedy by coercing the demon, or the
demon by desisting. For, as wizards themselves admit, it does not always
follow that what was done by one kind of witchcraft can be destroyed by
another kind, and even though it were possible to use witchcraft as a
remedy, it would nevertheless be reckoned to be perpetual, since nowise
ought one to invoke the demon's help by witchcraft. Again, if the devil
has been given power over a person on account of sin, it does not follow
that his power ceases with the sin, because the punishment sometimes
continues after the fault has been removed. And again, the exorcisms of
the Church do not always avail to repress the demons in all their
molestations of the body, if God will it so, but they always avail
against those assaults of the demons against which they are chiefly
instituted.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[2] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: Witchcraft sometimes causes an impediment in relation to
all, sometimes in relation to one only: because the devil is a voluntary
cause not acting from natural necessity. Moreover, the impediment
resulting from witchcraft may result from an impression made by the demon
on a man's imagination, whereby he is deprived of the concupiscence that
moves him in regard to a particular woman and not to another.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether madness is an impediment to marriage?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that madness is not an impediment to marriage. For
spiritual marriage which is contracted in Baptism is more excellent than
carnal marriage. But mad persons can be baptized. Therefore they can also
marry.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, frigidity is an impediment to marriage because it
impedes carnal copulation, which is not impeded by madness. Therefore
neither is marriage impeded thereby.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, marriage is not voided save by a perpetual impediment.
But one cannot tell whether madness is a perpetual impediment. Therefore
it does not void marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[3] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, the impediments that hinder marriage are sufficiently
contained in the verses given above (Q[50]). But they contain no mention
of madness. Therefore, etc.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[3] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, Madness removes the use of reason more than error does.
But error is an impediment to marriage. Therefore madness is also.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[3] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, mad persons are not fit for making contracts. But marriage is a
contract. Therefore, etc.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[3] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, The madness is either previous or subsequent to marriage.
If subsequent, it nowise voids the marriage, but if it be previous, then
the mad person either has lucid intervals, or not. If he has, then
although it is not safe for him to marry during that interval, since he
would not know how to educate his children, yet if he marries, the
marriage is valid. But if he has no lucid intervals, or marries outside a
lucid interval, then, since there can be no consent without use of
reason, the marriage will be invalid.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The use of reason is not necessary for Baptism as its
cause, in which way it is necessary for matrimony. Hence the comparison
fails. We have, however, spoken of the Baptism of mad persons (TP, Q[68],
A[12]).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Madness impedes marriage on the part of the latter's cause
which is the consent, although not on the part of the act as frigidity
does. Yet the Master treats of it together with frigidity, because both
are defects of nature (Sent. iv, D, 34).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: A passing impediment which hinders the cause of marriage,
namely the consent, voids marriage altogether. But an impediment that
hinders the act must needs be perpetual in order to void the marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[3] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: This impediment is reducible to error, since in either case
there is lack of consent on the part of the reason.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether marriage is annulled by the husband committing incest with his
wife's sister?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that marriage is not annulled by the husband
committing incest with his wife's sister. For the wife should not be
punished for her husband's sin. Yet she would be punished if the
marriage were annulled. Therefore, etc.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, it is a greater sin to know one's own relative, than to
know the relative of one's wife. But the former sin is not an impediment
to marriage. Therefore neither is the second.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[4] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, if this is inflicted as a punishment of the sin, it
would seem, if the incestuous husband marry even after his wife's death,
that they ought to be separated: which is not true.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[4] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, this impediment is not mentioned among those enumerated
above (Q[50]). Therefore it does not void the marriage contract.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[4] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, By knowing his wife's sister he contracts affinity,
with his wife. But affinity voids the marriage contract. Therefore the
aforesaid incest does also.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[4] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, by whatsoever a man sinneth, by the same also is he punished.
Now such a man sins against marriage. Therefore he ought to be punished
by being deprived of marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[4] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, If a man has connection with the sister or other relative
of his wife before contracting marriage, even after his betrothal, the
marriage should be broken off on account of the resultant affinity. If,
however, the connection take place after the marriage has been contracted
and consummated, the marriage must not be altogether dissolved: but the
husband loses his right to marital intercourse, nor can he demand it
without sin. And yet he must grant it if asked, because the wife should
not be punished for her husband's sin. But after the death of his wife he
ought to remain without any hope of marriage, unless he receive a
dispensation on account of his frailty, through fear of unlawful
intercourse. If, however, he marry without a dispensation, he sins by
contravening the law of the Church, but his marriage is not for this
reason to be annulled. This suffices for the Replies to the Objections,
for incest is accounted an impediment to marriage not so much for its
being a sin as on account of the affinity which it causes. For this
reason it is not mentioned with the other impediments, but is included in
the impediment of affinity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[5] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether defective age is an impediment to marriage?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[5] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that deficient age is not an impediment to
marriage. For according to the laws children are under the care of a
guardian until their twenty-fifth year. Therefore it would seem that
before that age their reason is not sufficiently mature to give consent,
and consequently that ought seemingly to be the age fixed for marrying.
Yet marriage can be contracted before that age. Therefore lack of the
appointed age is not an impediment to marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[5] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, just as the tie of religion is perpetual so is the
marriage tie. Now according to the new legislation (cap. Non Solum, De
regular. et transeunt.) no one can be professed before the fourteenth
year of age. Therefore neither could a person marry if defective age were
an impediment.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[5] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, just as consent is necessary for marriage on the part of
the man, so is it on the part of the woman. Now a woman can marry before
the age of fourteen. Therefore a man can also.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[5] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, inability to copulate, unless it be perpetual and not
known, is not an impediment to marriage. But lack of age is neither
perpetual nor unknown. Therefore it is not an impediment to marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[5] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, it is not included under any of the aforesaid
impediments (Q[50]), and consequently would seem not to be an impediment
to marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[5] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, A Decretal (cap. Quod Sedem, De frigid et malefic.)
says that "a boy who is incapable of marriage intercourse is unfit to
marry." But in the majority of cases he cannot pay the marriage debt
before the age of fourteen (De Animal. vii). Therefore, etc.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[5] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, "There is a fixed limit of size and growth for all things in
nature" according to the Philosopher (De Anima ii, 4): and consequently
it would seem that, since marriage is natural, it must have a fixed age
by defect of which it is impeded.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[5] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Since marriage is effected by way of a contract, it comes
under the ordinance of positive law like other contracts. Consequently
according to law (cap. Tua, De sponsal. impub.) it is determined that
marriage may not be contracted before the age of discretion when each
party is capable of sufficient deliberation about marriage, and of mutual
fulfilment of the marriage debt, and that marriages otherwise contracted
are void. Now for the most part this age is the fourteenth year in males
and the twelfth year in women: but since the ordinances of positive law
are consequent upon what happens in the majority of cases, if anyone
reach the required perfection before the aforesaid age, so that nature
and reason are sufficiently developed to supply the lack of age, the
marriage is not annulled. Wherefore if the parties who marry before the
age of puberty have marital intercourse before the aforesaid age, their
marriage is none the less perpetually indissoluble.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[5] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: In matters to which nature inclines there is not required
such a development of reason in order to deliberate, as in other matters:
and therefore it is possible after deliberation to consent to marriage
before one is able to manage one's own affairs in other matters without a
guardian.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[5] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The same answer applies, since the religious vow is about
matters outside the inclination of nature, and which offer greater
difficulty than marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[5] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: It is said that woman comes to the age of puberty sooner
than man does (De Animal. ix); hence there is no parallel between the two.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[5] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: In this case there is an impediment not only as to
inability to copulate, but also on account of the defect of the reason,
which is not yet qualified to give rightly that consent which is to
endure in perpetuity.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[58] A[5] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: The impediment arising from defective age, like that which
arises from madness, is reducible to the impediment of error; because a
man has not yet the full use of his free-will.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] Out. Para. 1/1
OF DISPARITY OF WORSHIP AS AN IMPEDIMENT TO MARRIAGE (SIX ARTICLES)
We must now consider disparity of worship as an impediment to marriage.
Under this head there are six points of inquiry:
(1) Whether a believer can marry an unbeliever?
(2) Whether there is marriage between unbelievers?
(3) Whether a husband being converted to the faith can remain with his
wife if she be unwilling to be converted?
(4) Whether he may leave his unbelieving wife?
(5) Whether after putting her away he may take another wife?
(6) Whether a husband may put aside his wife on account of other sins as
he may for unbelief?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether a believer can marry an unbeliever?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that a believer can marry an unbeliever. For Joseph
married an Egyptian woman, and Esther married Assuerus: and in both
marriages there was disparity of worship, since one was an unbeliever and
the other a believer. Therefore disparity of worship previous to marriage
is not an impediment thereto.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the Old Law teaches the same faith as the New. But
according to the Old Law there could be marriage between a believer and
an unbeliever, as evidenced by Dt. 21:10 seqq.: "If thou go out to the
fight . . . and seest in the number of the captives a beautiful woman and
lovest her, and wilt have her to wife . . . thou shalt go in unto her,
and shalt sleep with her, and she shall be thy wife." Therefore it is
lawful also under the New Law.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, betrothal is directed to marriage. Now there can be a
betrothal between a believer and an unbeliever in the case where a
condition is made of the latter's future conversion. Therefore under the
same condition there can be marriage between them.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[1] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, every impediment to marriage is in some way contrary to
marriage. But unbelief is not contrary to marriage, since marriage
fulfills an office of nature whose dictate faith surpasses. Therefore
disparity of worship is not an impediment to marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[1] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, there is sometime disparity of worship even between two
persons who are baptized, for instance when, after Baptism, a person
falls into heresy. Yet if such a person marry a believer, it is
nevertheless a valid marriage. Therefore disparity of worship is not an
impediment to marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[1] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, It is written (2 Cor. 6:14): "What concord hath light
with darkness? [*Vulg.: 'What fellowship hath light with darkness? And
what concord hath Christ with Belial?']" Now there is the greatest
concord between husband and wife. Therefore one who is in the light of
faith cannot marry one who is in the darkness of unbelief.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[1] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, it is written (Malachi 2:11): "Juda hath profaned the holiness
of the Lord, which he loved, and hath married the daughter of a strange
god." But such had not been the case if they could have married validly.
Therefore disparity of worship is an impediment to marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, The chief good of marriage is the offspring to be brought
up to the worship of God. Now since education is the work of father and
mother in common, each of them intends to bring up the child to the
worship of God according to their own faith. Consequently if they be of
different faith, the intention of the one will be contrary to the
intention of the other, and therefore there cannot be a fitting marriage
between them. For this reason disparity of faith previous to marriage is
an impediment to the marriage contract.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: In the Old Law it was allowable to marry with certain
unbelievers, and forbidden with others. It was however especially
forbidden with regard to inhabitants of the land of Canaan, both because
the Lord had commanded them to be slain on account of their obstinacy,
and because it was fraught with a greater danger, lest to wit they should
pervert to idolatry those whom they married or their children, since the
Israelites were more liable to adopt their rites and customs through
dwelling among them. But it was permitted in regard to other unbelievers,
especially when there could be no fear of their being drawn into
idolatry. And thus Joseph, Moses, and Esther married unbelievers. But
under the New Law which is spread throughout the whole world the
prohibition extends with equal reason to all unbelievers. Hence disparity
of worship previous to marriage is an impediment to its being contracted
and voids the contract.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: This law either refers to other nations with whom they
could lawfully marry, or to the case when the captive woman was willing
to be converted to the faith and worship of God.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Present is related to present in the same way as future to
future. Wherefore just as when marriage is contracted in the present,
unity of worship is required in both contracting parties, so in the case
of a betrothal, which is a promise of future marriage, it suffices to add
the condition of future unity of worship.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[1] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: It has been made clear that disparity of worship is
contrary to marriage in respect of its chief good, which is the good of
the offspring.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[1] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: Matrimony is a sacrament: and therefore so far as the
sacramental essentials are concerned, it requires purity with regard to
the sacrament of faith, namely Baptism, rather than with regard to
interior faith. For which reason also this impediment is not called
disparity of faith, but disparity of worship which concerns outward
service, as stated above (Sent. iii, D, 9, Q[1], A[1], qu. 1).
Consequently if a believer marry a baptized heretic, the marriage is
valid, although he sins by marrying her if he knows her to be a heretic:
even so he would sin were he to marry an excommunicate woman, and yet the
marriage would not be void: whereas on the other hand if a catechumen
having right faith but not having been baptized were to marry a baptized
believer, the marriage would not be valid.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether there can be marriage between unbelievers?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that there can be no marriage between unbelievers.
For matrimony is a sacrament of the Church. Now Baptism is the door of
the sacraments. Therefore unbelievers, since they are not baptized,
cannot marry any more than they can receive other sacraments.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, two evils are a greater impediment to good than one. But
the unbelief of only one party is an impediment to marriage. Much more,
therefore, is the unbelief of both, and consequently there can be no
marriage between unbelievers.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, just as there is disparity of worship between believer
and unbeliever, so can there be between two unbelievers, for instance if
one be a heathen and the other a Jew. Now disparity of worship is an
impediment to marriage, as stated above (A[1]). Therefore there can be no
valid marriage at least between unbelievers of different worship.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[2] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, in marriage there is real chastity. But according to
Augustine (De Adult. Conjug. i, 18) there is no real chastity between an
unbeliever and his wife, and these words are quoted in the Decretals
(XXVIII, qu. i, can. Sic enim.). Neither therefore is there a true
marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[2] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, true marriage excuses carnal intercourse from sin. But
marriage contracted between unbelievers cannot do this, since "the whole
life of unbelievers is a sin," as a gloss observes on Rm. 14:23, "All
that is not of faith is sin." Therefore there is no true marriage between
unbelievers.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[2] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, It is written (1 Cor. 7:12): "If any brother hath a
wife that believeth not, and she consent to dwell with him, let him not
put her away." But she is not called his wife except by reason of
marriage. Therefore marriage between unbelievers is a true marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[2] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, the removal of what comes after does not imply the removal of
what comes first. Now marriage belongs to an office of nature, which
precedes the state of grace, the principle of which is faith. Therefore
unbelief does not prevent the existence of marriage between unbelievers.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Marriage was instituted chiefly for the good of the
offspring, not only as to its begetting---since this can be effected even
without marriage---but also as to its advancement to a perfect state,
because everything intends naturally to bring its effect to perfection.
Now a twofold perfection is to be considered in the offspring. one is the
perfection of nature, not only as regards the body but also as regards
the soul, by those means which are of the natural law. The other is the
perfection of grace: and the former perfection is material and imperfect
in relation to the latter. Consequently, since those things which are for
the sake of the end are proportionate to the end, the marriage that tends
to the first perfection is imperfect and material in comparison with that
which tends to the second perfection. And since the first perfection can
be common to unbelievers and believers, while the second belongs only to
believers, it follows that between unbelievers there is marriage indeed,
but not perfected by its ultimate perfection as there is between
believers.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Marriage was instituted not only as a sacrament, but also
as an office of nature. And therefore, although marriage is not competent
to unbelievers, as a sacrament dependent on the dispensation of the
Church's ministers, it is nevertheless competent to them as fulfilling an
office of nature. And yet even a marriage of this kind is a sacrament
after the manner of a habit, although it is not actually since they do
not marry actually in the faith of the Church.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Disparity of worship is an impediment to marriage, not by
reason of unbelief, but on account of the difference of faith. For
disparity of worship hinders not only the second perfection of the
offspring, but also the first, since the parents endeavor to draw their
children in different directions, which is not the case when both are
unbelievers.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: As already stated (ad 1) there is marriage between
unbelievers, in so far as marriage fulfills an office of nature. Now
those things that pertain to the natural law are determinable by positive
law: and therefore if any law among unbelievers forbid the contracting
of marriage with unbelievers of a different rite, the disparity of
worship will be an impediment to their intermarrying. They are not,
however, forbidden by Divine law, because before God, however much one
may stray from the faith, this makes no difference to one's being removed
from grace: nor is it forbidden by any law of the Church who has not to
judge of those who are without.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[2] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: The chastity and other virtues of unbelievers are said not
to be real, because they cannot attain the end of real virtue, which is
real happiness. Thus we say it is not a real wine if it has not the
effect of wine.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[2] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: An unbeliever does not sin in having intercourse with his
wife, if he pays her the marriage debt, for the good of the offspring, or
for the troth whereby he is bound to her: since this is an act of justice
and of temperance which observes the due circumstance in pleasure of
touch; even as neither does he sin in performing acts of other civic
virtues. Again, the reason why the whole life of unbelievers is said to
be a sin is not that they sin in every act, but because they cannot be
delivered from the bondage of sin by that which they do.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the husband, being converted to the faith, may remain with his
wife is she be unwilling to be converted?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that when a husband is converted to the faith he
cannot remain with his wife who is an unbeliever and is unwilling to be
converted, and whom he had married while he was yet an unbeliever. For
where the danger is the same one should take the same precautions. Now a
believer is forbidden to marry an unbeliever for fear of being turned
away from the faith. Since then if the believer remain with the
unbeliever whom he had married previously, the danger is the same, in
fact greater, for neophytes are more easily perverted than those who have
been brought up in the faith, it would seem that a believer, after being
converted, cannot remain with an unbeliever.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, "An unbeliever cannot remain united to her who has been
received into the Christian faith" (Decretals, XXVIII, qu. 1, can.
Judaei). Therefore a believer is bound to put away a wife who does not
believe.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, a marriage contracted between believers is more perfect
than one contracted between unbelievers. Now, if believers marry within
the degrees forbidden by the Church, their marriage is void. Therefore
the same applies to unbelievers, and thus a believing husband cannot
remain with an unbelieving wife, at any rate, if as an unbeliever he
married her within the forbidden degrees.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[3] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, sometimes an unbeliever has several wives recognized by
his law. If, then, he can remain with those whom he married while yet an
unbeliever, it would seem that even after his conversion he can retain
several wives.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[3] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, it may happen that after divorcing his first wife he has
married a second, and that he is converted during this latter marriage.
It would seem therefore that at least in this case he cannot remain with
this second wife.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[3] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, The Apostle counsels him to remain (1 Cor. 7:12).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[3] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, no impediment that supervenes upon a true marriage dissolves
it. Now it was a true marriage when they were both unbelievers. Therefore
when one of them is converted, the marriage is not annulled on that
account; and thus it would seem that they may lawfully remain together.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[3] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, The faith of a married person does not dissolve but
perfects the marriage. Wherefore, since there is true marriage between
unbelievers, as stated above (A[2], ad 1), the marriage tie is not broken
by the fact that one of them is converted to the faith, but sometimes
while the marriage tie remains, the marriage is dissolved as to
cohabitation and marital intercourse, wherein unbelief and adultery are
on a par, since both are against the good of the offspring. Consequently,
the husband has the same power to put away an unbelieving wife or to
remain with her, as he has to put away an adulterous wife or to remain
with her. For an innocent husband is free to remain with an adulterous
wife in the hope of her amendment, but not if she be obstinate in her sin
of adultery, lest he seem to approve of her disgrace; although even if
there be hope of her amendment he is free to put her away. In like manner
the believer after his conversion may remain with the unbeliever in the
hope of her conversion, if he see that she is not obstinate in her
unbelief, and he does well in remaining with her, though not bound to do
so: and this is what the Apostle counsels (1 Cor. 7:12).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: It is easier to prevent a thing being done than to undo
what is rightly done. Hence there are many things that impede the
contracting of marriage if they precede it, which nevertheless cannot
dissolve it if they follow it. Such is the case with affinity (Q[55],
A[6]): and it is the same with disparity of worship.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: In the early Church at the time of the apostles, both Jews
and Gentiles were everywhere converted to the faith: and consequently the
believing husband could then have a reasonable hope for his wife's
conversion, even though she did not promise to be converted. Afterwards,
however, as time went on the Jews became more obstinate than the
Gentiles, because the Gentiles still continued to come to the faith, for
instance, at the time of the martyrs, and at the time of Constantine and
thereabouts. Wherefore it was not safe then for a believer to cohabit
with an unbelieving Jewish wife, nor was there hope for her conversion as
for that of a Gentile wife. Consequently, then, the believer could, after
his conversion, cohabit with his wife if she were a Gentile, but not if
she were a Jewess, unless she promised to be converted. This is the sense
of that decree. Now, however, they are on a par, namely Gentiles and
Jews, because both are obstinate; and therefore unless the unbelieving
wife be willing to be converted, he is not allowed to cohabit with her,
be she Gentile or Jew.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Non-baptized unbelievers are not bound by the laws of the
Church, but they are bound by the ordinances of the Divine law. Hence
unbelievers who have married within the degrees forbidden by the Divine
law, whether both or one of them be converted to the faith, cannot
continue in a like marriage. But if they have married within the degrees
forbidden by a commandment of the Church, they can remain together if
both be converted, or if one be converted and there be hope of the
other's conversion.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[3] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: To have several wives is contrary to the natural law by
which even unbelievers are bound. Wherefore an unbeliever is not truly
married save to her whom he married first. Consequently if he be
converted with all his wives, he may remain with the first, and must put
the others away. If, however, the first refuse to be converted, and one
of the others be converted, he has the same right to marry her again as
he would have to marry another. We shall treat of this matter further on
(A[5]).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[3] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: To divorce a wife is contrary to the law of nature,
wherefore it is not lawful for an unbeliever to divorce his wife. Hence
if he be converted after divorcing one and marrying another, the same
judgment is to be pronounced in this case as in the case of a man who had
several wives, because if he wish to be converted he is bound to take the
first whom he had divorced and to put the other away.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether a believer can, after his conversion, put away his unbelieving
wife if she be willing to cohabit with him without insult to the Creator?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that a believer, after his conversion, cannot put
away his unbelieving wife if she be willing to cohabit with him without
insult to the Creator. For the husband is more bound to his wife than a
slave to his master. But a converted slave is not freed from the bond of
slavery, as appears from 1 Cor. 7:21; 1 Tim. 6:1. Therefore neither can a
believing husband put away his unbelieving wife.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, no one may act to another's prejudice without the
latter's consent. Now the unbelieving wife had a right in the body of her
unbelieving husband. If, then, her husband's conversion to the faith
could be prejudicial to the wife, so that he would be free to put her
away, the husband could not be converted to the faith without his wife's
consent, even as he cannot receive orders or vow continence without her
consent.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[4] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, if a man, whether slave or free, knowingly marry a
bondwoman, he cannot put her away on account of her different condition.
Since, then, the husband, when he married an unbeliever, knew that she
was an unbeliever, it would seem that in like manner he cannot put her
away on account of her unbelief.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[4] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, a father is in duty bound to work for the salvation of
his children. But if he were to leave his unbelieving wife, the children
of their union would remain with the mother, because "the offspring
follows the womb," and thus their salvation would be imperiled. Therefore
he cannot lawfully put away his unbelieving wife.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[4] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, an adulterous husband cannot put away an adulterous
wife, even after he has done penance for his adultery. Therefore if an
adulterous and an unbelieving husband are to be judged alike, neither can
the believer put aside the unbeliever, even after his conversion to the
faith.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[4] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, are the words of the Apostle (1 Cor. 7:15,16).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[4] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, spiritual adultery is more grievous than carnal. But a man can
put his wife away, as to cohabitation, on account of carnal adultery.
Much more, therefore, can he do so on account of unbelief, which is
spiritual adultery.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[4] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Different things are competent and expedient to man
according as his life is of one kind or of another. Wherefore he who dies
to his former life is not bound to those things to which he was bound in
his former life. Hence it is that he who vowed certain things while
living in the world is not bound to fulfill them when he dies to the
world by adopting the religious life. Now he who is baptized is
regenerated in Christ and dies to his former life, since the generation
of one thing is the corruption of another, and consequently he is freed
from the obligation whereby he was bound to pay his wife the marriage
debt, and is not bound to cohabit with her when she is unwilling to be
converted, although in a certain case he is free to do so, as stated
above (A[3]), just as a religious is free to fulfill the vows he took in
the world, if they be not contrary to his religious profession, although
he is not bound to do so.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Bondage is not inconsistent with the perfection of the
Christian religion, which makes a very special profession of humility.
But the obligation to a wife, or the conjugal bond, is somewhat
derogatory to the perfection of Christian life, the highest state of
which is in the possession of the continent: hence the comparison fails.
Moreover one married party is not bound to the other as the latter's
possession, as a slave to his master, but by way of a kind of
partnership, which is unfitting between unbeliever and believer as
appears from 2 Cor. 6:15; hence there is no comparison between a slave
and a married person.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/2
Reply OBJ 2: The wife had a right in the body of her husband only as
long as he remained in the life wherein he had married, since also when
the husband dies the wife "is delivered from the law of her husband" (Rm.
7:3). Wherefore if the husband leave her after he has changed his life by
dying to his former life, this is nowise prejudicial to her. Now he who
goes over to the religious life dies but a spiritual death and not a
bodily death. Wherefore if the marriage be consummated, the husband
cannot enter religion without his wife's consent, whereas he can before
carnal connection when there is only a spiritual connection. On the other
hand, he who is baptized is even corporeally buried together with Christ
unto death; and therefore he is freed from paying the marriage debt even
after the marriage has been consummated.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 2/2
We may also reply that it is through her own fault in refusing to be
converted that the wife suffers prejudice.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[4] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Disparity of worship makes a person simply unfit for lawful
marriage, whereas the condition of bondage does not, but only where it is
unknown. Hence there is no comparison between an unbeliever and a
bondswoman.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[4] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: Either the child has reached a perfect age, and then it is
free to follow either the believing father or the unbelieving mother, or
else it is under age, and then it should be given to the believer
notwithstanding that it needs the mother's care for its education.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[4] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: By doing penance the adulterer does not enter another life
as an unbeliever by being baptized. Hence the comparison fails.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[5] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the believer who leaves his unbelieving wife can take another
wife?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[5] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the believer who leaves his unbelieving wife
cannot take another wife. For indissolubility is of the nature of
marriage, since it is contrary to the natural law to divorce one's wife.
Now there was true marriage between them as unbelievers. Therefore their
marriage can nowise be dissolved. But as long as a man is bound by
marriage to one woman he cannot marry another. Therefore a believer who
leaves his unbelieving wife cannot take another wife.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[5] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, a crime subsequent to marriage does not dissolve the
marriage. Now, if the wife be willing to cohabit without insult to the
Creator, the marriage tie is not dissolved, since the husband cannot
marry another. Therefore the sin of the wife who refuses to cohabit
without insult to the Creator does not dissolve the marriage so that her
husband be free to take another wife.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[5] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, husband and wife are equal in the marriage tie. Since,
then, it is unlawful for the unbelieving wife to marry again while her
husband lives, it would seem that neither can the believing husband do so.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[5] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, the vow of continence is more favorable than the
marriage contract. Now seemingly it is not lawful for the believing
husband to take a vow of continence without the consent of his
unbelieving wife, since then the latter would be deprived of marriage if
she were afterwards converted. Much less therefore is it lawful for him
to take another wife.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[5] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, the son who persists in unbelief after his father's
conversion loses the right to inherit from his father: and yet if he be
afterwards converted, the inheritance is restored to him even though
another should have entered into possession thereof. Therefore it would
seem that in like manner, if the unbelieving wife be converted, her
husband ought to be restored to her even though he should have married
another wife: yet this would be impossible if the second marriage were
valid. Therefore he cannot take another wife.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[5] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, Matrimony is not ratified without the sacrament of
Baptism. Now what is not ratified can be annulled. Therefore marriage
contracted in unbelief can be annulled, and consequently, the marriage
tie being dissolved, it is lawful for the husband to take another wife.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[5] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, a husband ought not to cohabit with an unbelieving wife who
refuses to cohabit without insult to the Creator. If therefore it were
unlawful for him to take another wife he would be forced to remain
continent, which would seem unreasonable, since then he would be at a
disadvantage through his conversion.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[5] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, When either husband or wife is converted to the faith the
other remaining in unbelief, a distinction must be made. For if the
unbeliever be willing to cohabit without insult to the Creator---that is
without drawing the other to unbelief---the believer is free to part from
the other, but by parting is not permitted to marry again. But if the
unbeliever refuse to cohabit without insult to the Creator, by making use
of blasphemous words and refusing to hear Christ's name, then if she
strive to draw him to unbelief, the believing husband after parting from
her may be united to another in marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[5] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: As stated above (A[2]), the marriage of unbelievers is
imperfect, whereas the marriage of believers is perfect and consequently
binds more firmly. Now the firmer tie always looses the weaker if it is
contrary to it, and therefore the subsequent marriage contracted in the
faith of Christ dissolves the marriage previously contracted in unbelief.
Therefore the marriage of unbelievers is not altogether firm and
ratified, but is ratified afterwards by Christ's faith.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[5] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The sin of the wife who refuses to cohabit without insult
to the Creator frees the husband from the tie whereby he was bound to
his wife so as to be unable to marry again during her lifetime. It does
not however dissolve the marriage at once, since if she were converted
from her blasphemy before he married again, her husband would be restored
to her. But the marriage is dissolved by the second marriage which the
believing husband would be unable to accomplish unless he were freed from
his obligation to his wife by her own fault.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[5] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: After the believer has married, the marriage tie is
dissolved on either side, because the marriage is not imperfect as to the
bond, although it is sometimes imperfect as to its effect. Hence it is in
punishment of the unbelieving wife rather than by virtue of the previous
marriage that she is forbidden to marry again. If however she be
afterwards converted, she may be allowed by dispensation to take another
husband, should her husband have taken another wife.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[5] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: The husband ought not to take a vow of continence nor enter
into a second marriage, if after his conversion there be a reasonable
hope of the conversion of his wife, because the wife's conversion would
be more difficult if she knew she was deprived of her husband. If however
there be no hope of her conversion, he can take Holy orders or enter
religion, having first besought his wife to be converted. And then if the
wife be converted after her husband has received Holy orders, her husband
must not be restored to her, but she must take it as a punishment of her
tardy conversion that she is deprived of her husband.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[5] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: The bond of fatherhood is not dissolved by disparity of
worship, as the marriage bond is: wherefore there is no comparison
between an inheritance and a wife.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[6] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether other sins dissolve marriage?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[6] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that other sins besides unbelief dissolve marriage.
For adultery is seemingly more directly opposed to marriage than unbelief
is. But unbelief dissolves marriage in a certain case so that it is
lawful to marry again. Therefore adultery has the same effect.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[6] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, just as unbelief is spiritual fornication, so is any
kind of sin. If, then unbelief dissolves marriage because it is spiritual
fornication, for the same reason any kind of sin will dissolve marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[6] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, it is said (Mt. 5:30): "If thy right hand scandalize
thee, pluck it off and cast it from thee," and a gloss of Jerome says
that "by the hand and the right eye we may understand our brother, wife,
relatives and children." Now these become obstacles to us by any kind of
sin. Therefore marriage can be dissolved on account of any kind of sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[6] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, covetousness is idolatry according to Eph. 5:5. Now a
wife may be put away on account of idolatry. Therefore in like manner she
can be put away on account of covetousness, as also on account of other
sins graver than covetousness.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[6] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, the Master says this expressly (Sent. iv, D, 30).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[6] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, It is said (Mt. 5:32): "Whosoever shall put away his
wife, excepting for the cause of fornication, maketh her to commit
adultery."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[6] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, if this were true, divorces would be made all day long, since
it is rare to find a marriage wherein one of the parties does not fall
into sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[6] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Bodily fornication and unbelief have a special
contrariety to the goods of marriage, as stated above (A[3]). Hence they
are specially effective in dissolving marriages. Nevertheless it must be
observed that marriage is dissolved in two ways. In one way as to the
marriage tie, and thus marriage cannot be dissolved after it is ratified,
neither by unbelief nor by adultery. But if it be not ratified, the tie
is dissolved, if the one party remain in unbelief, and the other being
converted to the faith has married again. On the other hand the aforesaid
tie is not dissolved by adultery, else the unbeliever would be free to
give a bill of divorce to his adulterous wife, and having put her away,
could take another wife, which is false. In another way marriage is
dissolved as to the act, and thus it can be dissolved on account of
either unbelief or fornication. But marriage cannot be dissolved even as
to the act on account of other sins, unless perchance the husband wish to
cease from intercourse with his wife in order to punish her by depriving
her of the comfort of his presence.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[6] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Although adultery is opposed to marriage as fulfilling an
office of nature, more directly than unbelief, it is the other way about
if we consider marriage as a sacrament of the Church, from which source
it derives perfect stability, inasmuch as it signifies the indissoluble
union of Christ with the Church. Wherefore the marriage that is not
ratified can be dissolved as to the marriage tie on account of unbelief
rather than on account of adultery.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[6] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The primal union of the soul to God is by faith, and
consequently the soul is thereby espoused to God as it were, according to
Osee 2:20, "I will espouse thee to Me in faith." Hence in Holy Writ
idolatry and unbelief are specially designated by the name of
fornication: whereas other sins are called spiritual fornications by a
more remote signification.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[6] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: This applies to the case when the wife proves a notable
occasion of sin to her husband, so that he has reason to fear his being
in danger: for then the husband can withdraw from living with her, as
stated above (A[5]).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[6] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: Covetousness is said to be idolatry on account of a certain
likeness of bondage, because both the covetous and the idolater serve the
creature rather than the Creator; but not on account of likeness of
unbelief, since unbelief corrupts the intellect whereas covetousness
corrupts the affections.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[59] A[6] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: The words of the Master refer to betrothal, because a
betrothal can be rescinded on account of a subsequent crime. Or, if he is
speaking of marriage, they must be referred to the severing of mutual
companionship for a time, as stated above, or to the case when the wife
is unwilling to cohabit except on the condition of sinning, for instance,
if she were to say: "I will not remain your wife unless you amass wealth
for me by theft," for then he ought to leave her rather than thieve.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[60] Out. Para. 1/1
OF WIFE-MURDER (TWO ARTICLES)
We must now consider wife-murder, under which head there are two points
of inquiry:
(1) Whether in a certain case it is lawful to kill one's wife?
(2) Whether wife-murder is an impediment to marriage?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[60] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether it is lawful for a man to kill his wife if she be discovered in
the act of adultery?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[60] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem lawful for a man to kill his wife if she be
discovered in the act of adultery. For the Divine law commanded
adulterous wives to be stoned. Now it is not a sin to fulfill the Divine
law. Neither therefore is it a sin to kill one's own wife if she be an
adulteress.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[60] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, that which the law can rightly do, can be rightly done
by one whom the law has commissioned to do it. But the law can rightly
kill an adulterous wife or any other person deserving of death. Since
then the law has commissioned the husband to kill his wife if she be
discovered in the act of adultery, it would seem that he can rightly do
so.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[60] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, the husband has greater power over his adulterous wife
than over the man who committed adultery with her. Now if the husband
strike a cleric whom he found with his wife he is not excommunicated.
Therefore it would seem lawful for him even to kill his own wife if she
be discovered in adultery.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[60] A[1] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, the husband is bound to correct his wife. But correction
is given by inflicting a just punishment. Since then the just punishment
of adultery is death, because it is a capital sin, it would seem lawful
for a husband to kill his adulterous wife.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[60] A[1] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, It is stated in the text (Sent. iv, D, 37) that "the
Church of God is never bound by the laws of this world, for she has none
but a spiritual sword." Therefore it would seem that he who wishes to
belong to the Church cannot rightly take advantage of the law which
permits a man to kill his wife.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[60] A[1] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, husband and wife are judged on a par. But it is not lawful for
a wife to kill her husband if he be discovered in adultery. Neither
therefore may a husband kill his wife.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[60] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, It happens in two ways that a husband kills his wife.
First, by a civil judgment; and thus there is no doubt that a husband,
moved by zeal for justice and not by vindictive anger or hatred can,
without sin, bring a criminal accusation of adultery upon his wife before
a secular court, and demand that she receive capital punishment as
appointed by the law; just as it is lawful to accuse a person of murder
or any other crime. Such an accusation however cannot be made in an
ecclesiastical court, because, as stated in the text (Sent. iv, D, 37),
the Church does not wield a material sword. Secondly, a husband can kill
his wife himself without her being convicted in court, and thus to kill
her outside of the act of adultery is not lawful, neither according to
civil law nor according to the law of conscience, whatever evidence he
may have of her adultery. The civil law however considers it, as though
it were lawful, that he should kill her in the very act, not by
commanding him to do so, but by not inflicting on him the punishment for
murder, on account of the very great provocation which the husband
receives by such a deed to kill his wife. But the Church is not bound in
this matter by human laws, neither does she acquit him of the debt of
eternal punishment, nor of such punishment as may be awarded him by an
ecclesiastical tribunal for the reason that he is quit of any punishment
to be inflicted by a secular court. Therefore in no case is it lawful for
a husband to kill his wife on his own authority.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[60] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The law has committed the infliction of this punishment not
to private individuals, but to public persons, who are deputed to this by
their office. Now the husband is not his wife's judge: wherefore he may
not kill her, but may accuse her in the judge's presence.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[60] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The civil law has not commissioned the husband to kill his
wife by commanding him to do so, for thus he would not sin, just as the
judge's deputy does not sin by killing the thief condemned to death: but
it has permitted this by not punishing it. For which reason it has raised
certain obstacles to prevent the husband from killing his wife.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[60] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: This does not prove that it is lawful simply, but that it
is lawful as regards immunity from a particular kind of punishment, since
excommunication is also a kind of punishment.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[60] A[1] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: There are two kinds of community: the household, such as a
family; and the civil community, such as a city or kingdom. Accordingly,
he who presides over the latter kind of community, a king for instance,
can punish an individual both by correcting and by exterminating him, for
the betterment of the community with whose care he is charged. But he who
presides over a community of the first kind, can inflict only corrective
punishment, which does not extend beyond the limits of amendment, and
these are exceeded by the punishment of death. Wherefore the husband who
exercises this kind of control over his wife may not kill her, but he may
accuse or chastise her in some other way.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[60] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether wife-murder is an impediment to marriage?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[60] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that wife-murder is not an impediment to marriage.
For adultery is more directly opposed to marriage than murder is. Now
adultery is not an impediment to marriage. Neither therefore is
wife-murder.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[60] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, it is a more grievous sin to kill one's mother than
one's wife, for it is never lawful to strike one's mother, whereas it is
sometimes lawful to strike one's wife. But matricide is not an impediment
to marriage. Neither therefore is wife-murder.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[60] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, it is a greater sin for a man to kill another man's wife
on account of adultery than to kill his own wife, inasmuch as he has less
motive and is less concerned with her correction. But he who kills
another man's wife is not hindered from marrying. Neither therefore is he
who kills his own wife.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[60] A[2] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, if the cause be removed, the effect is removed. But the
sin of murder can be removed by repentance. Therefore the consequent
impediment to marriage can be removed also: and consequently it would
seem that after he has done penance he is not forbidden to marry.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[60] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, A canon (caus. xxxiii, qu. ii, can. Interfectores)
says: "The slayers of their own wives must be brought back to penance,
and they are absolutely forbidden to marry." Further, in whatsoever a man
sins, in that same must he be punished. But he who kills his wife sins
against marriage. Therefore he must be punished by being deprived of
marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[60] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, By the Church's decree wife-murder is an impediment to
marriage. Sometimes however it forbids the contracting of marriage
without voiding the contract, when to wit the husband kills his wife on
account of adultery or even through hatred; nevertheless if there be fear
lest he should prove incontinent, he may be dispensed by the Church so as
to marry lawfully. Sometimes it also voids the contract, as when a man
kills his wife in order to marry her with whom he has committed adultery,
for then the law declares him simply unfit to marry her, so that if he
actually marry her his marriage is void. He is not however hereby
rendered simply unfit by law in relation to other women: wherefore if he
should have married another, although he sin by disobeying the Church's
ordinance, the marriage is nevertheless not voided for this reason.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[60] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Murder and adultery in certain cases forbid the
contracting of marriage and void the contract, as we say here in regard
to wife-murder, and shall say further on (Sent. iv, Q[62], A[2]) in
regard to adultery. We may also reply that wife-murder is contrary to the
substance of wedlock, whereas adultery is contrary to the good of
fidelity due to marriage. Hence adultery is not more opposed to marriage
than wife-murder, and the argument is based on a false premiss.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[60] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Simply speaking it is a more grievous sin to kill one's
mother than one's wife, as also more opposed to nature, since a man
reveres his mother naturally. Consequently he is less inclined to
matricide and more prone to wife-murder; and it is to repress this
proneness that the Church has forbidden marriage to the man who has
murdered his wife.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[60] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Such a man does not sin against marriage as he does who
kills his own wife; wherefore the comparison fails.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[60] A[2] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: It does not follow that because guilt has been remitted
therefore the entire punishment is remitted, as evidenced by
irregularity. For repentance does not restore a man to his former
dignity, although it can restore him to his former state of grace, as
stated above (Q[38], A[1], ad 3).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[61] Out. Para. 1/1
OF THE IMPEDIMENT TO MARRIAGE, ARISING FROM A SOLEMN VOW (THREE ARTICLES)
We must next consider the impediments which supervene to marriage. We
shall consider (1) the impediment which affects an unconsummated
marriage, namely a solemn vow: (2) the impediment which affects a
consummated marriage, namely fornication. Under the first head there are
three points of inquiry:
(1) Whether either party after the marriage has been consummated can
enter religion without the other's consent?
(2) Whether they can enter religion before the consummation of the
marriage?
(3) Whether the wife can take another husband if her former husband has
entered religion before the consummation of the marriage?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[61] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether one party after the marriage has been consummated can enter
religion without the other's consent?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[61] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that even after the marriage has been consummated
one consort can enter religion without the other's consent. For the
Divine law ought to be more favorable to spiritual things than human law.
Now human law has allowed this. Therefore much more should the Divine law
permit it.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[61] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the lesser good does not hinder the greater. But the
married state is a lesser good than the religious state, according to 1
Cor. 7:38. Therefore marriage ought not to hinder a man from being able
to enter religion.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[61] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, in every form of religious life there is a kind of
spiritual marriage. Now it is lawful to pass from a less strict religious
order to one that is stricter. Therefore it is also allowable to pass
from a less strict---namely a carnal---marriage to a stricter marriage,
namely that of the religious life, even without the wife's consent.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[61] A[1] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, Married persons are forbidden (1 Cor. 7:5) to abstain
from the use of marriage even for a time without one another's consent,
in order to have time for prayer.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[61] A[1] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, no one can lawfully do that which is prejudicial to another
without the latter's consent. Now the religious vow taken by one consort
is prejudicial to the other, since the one has power over the other's
body. Therefore one of them cannot take a religious vow without the
other's consent.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[61] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, No one can make an offering to God of what belongs to
another. Wherefore since by a consummated marriage the husband's body
already belongs to his wife, he cannot by a vow of continence offer it to
God without her consent.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[61] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Human law considers marriage merely as fulfilling an office
of nature: whereas the Divine law considers it as a sacrament, by reason
of which it is altogether indissoluble. Hence the comparison fails.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[61] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: It is not unreasonable that a greater good be hindered by a
lesser which is contrary to it, just as good is hindered by evil.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[61] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: In every form of religious life marriage is contracted with
one person, namely Christ; to Whom, however, a person contracts more
obligations in one religious order than in another. But in carnal
marriage and religious marriage the contract is not with the same person:
wherefore that comparison fails.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[61] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether before the marriage has been consummated one consort can enter
religion without the other's consent?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[61] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that even before the marriage has been consummated
one consort cannot enter religion without the other's consent. For the
indissolubility of marriage belongs to the sacrament of matrimony,
inasmuch, namely, as it signifies the union of Christ with the Church.
Now marriage is a true sacrament before its consummation, and after
consent has been expressed in words of the present. Therefore it cannot
be dissolved by one of them entering religion.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[61] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, by virtue of the consent expressed in words of the
present, the one consort has given power over his body to the other.
Therefore the one can forthwith ask for the marriage debt, and the other
is bound to pay: and so the one cannot enter religion without the other's
consent.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[61] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, it is said (Mt. 19:6): "What God hath joined together
let no man put asunder." But the union which precedes marital intercourse
was made by God. Therefore it cannot be dissolved by the will of man.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[61] A[2] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, According to Jerome [*Prolog. in Joan.] our Lord called
John from his wedding.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[61] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Before marital intercourse there is only a spiritual bond
between husband and wife, but afterwards there is a carnal bond between
them. Wherefore, just as after marital intercourse marriage is dissolved
by carnal death, so by entering religion the bond which exists before the
consummation of the marriage is dissolved, because religious life is a
kind of spiritual death, whereby a man dies to the world and lives to God.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[61] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Before consummation marriage signifies the union of Christ
with the soul by grace, which is dissolved by a contrary spiritual
disposition, namely mortal sin. But after consummation it signifies the
union of Christ with the Church, as regards the assumption of human
nature into the unity of person, which union is altogether indissoluble.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[61] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Before consummation the body of one consort is not
absolutely delivered into the power of the other, but conditionally,
provided neither consort meanwhile seek the fruit of a better life. But
by marital intercourse the aforesaid delivery is completed, because then
each of them enters into bodily possession of the power transferred to
him. Wherefore also before consummation they are not bound to pay the
marriage debt forthwith after contracting marriage by words of the
present, but a space of two months is allowed them for three reasons.
First that they may deliberate meanwhile about entering religion;
secondly, to prepare what is necessary for the solemnization of the
wedding. thirdly, lest the husband think little of a gift he has not
longed to possess (cap. Institutum, caus. xxvi, qu. ii).
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[61] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: The marriage union, before consummation, is indeed perfect
as to its primary being, but is not finally perfect as to its second act
which is operation. It is like bodily possession and consequently is not
altogether indissoluble.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[61] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the wife may take another husband if her husband has entered
religion before the consummation of the marriage?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[61] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the wife may not take another husband, if her
husband has entered religion before the consummation of the marriage. For
that which is consistent with marriage does not dissolve the marriage
tie. Now the marriage tie still remains between those who equally take
religious vows. Therefore by the fact that one enters religion, the
other is not freed from the marriage tie. But as long as she remains tied
to one by marriage, she cannot marry another. Therefore, etc.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[61] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, after entering religion and before making his profession
the husband can return to the world. If then the wife can marry again
when her husband enters religion, he also can marry again when he returns
to the world: which is absurd.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[61] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, by a new decree (cap. Non solum, de regular. et
transeunt.) a profession, if made before the expiry of a year, is
accounted void. Therefore if he return to his wife after making such a
profession, she is bound to receive him. Therefore neither by her
husband's entry into religion, nor by his taking a vow, does the wife
receive the power to marry again.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[61] A[3] OTC Para. 1/1
On the contrary, No one can bind another to those things which belong to
perfection. Now continence is of those things that belong to perfection.
Therefore a wife is not bound to continence on account of her husband
entering religion, and consequently she can marry.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[61] A[3] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Just as bodily death of the husband dissolves the
marriage tie in such a way that the wife may marry whom she will,
according to the statement of the Apostle (1 Cor. 7:39); so too after the
husband's spiritual death by entering religion, she can marry whom she
will.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[61] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: When both consorts take a like vow of continence, neither
renounces the marriage tie, wherefore it still remains: but when only one
takes the vow, then for his own part he renounces the marriage tie,
wherefore the other is freed therefrom.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[61] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: A person is not accounted dead to the world by entering
religion until he makes his profession, and consequently his wife is
bound to wait for him until that time.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[61] A[3] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: We must judge of a profession thus made before the time
fixed by law, as of a simple vow. Wherefore just as when the husband has
taken a simple vow his wife is not bound to pay him the marriage debt,
and yet has not the power to marry again, so is it in this case.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] Out. Para. 1/1
OF THE IMPEDIMENT THAT SUPERVENES TO MARRIAGE AFTER ITS CONSUMMATION,
NAMELY FORNICATION (SIX ARTICLES)
We must now consider the impediment that supervenes upon marriage after
its consummation, namely fornication, which is an impediment to a
previous marriage as regards the act, although the marriage tie remains.
Under this head there are six points of inquiry:
(1) Whether it is lawful for a husband to put his wife away on account
of fornication?
(2) Whether he is bound to do so?
(3) Whether he may put her away at his own judgment?
(4) Whether in this matter husband and wife are of equal condition?
(5) Whether, after being divorced, they must remain unmarried?
(6) Whether they can be reconciled after being divorced?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[1] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether it is lawful for a husband to put away his wife on account of
fornication?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[1] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem unlawful for a husband to put away his wife on
account of fornication. For we must not return evil for evil. But the
husband, by putting away his wife on account of fornication, seemingly
returns evil for evil. Therefore this is not lawful.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[1] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, the sin is greater if both commit fornication, than if
one only commits it. But if both commit fornication, they cannot be
divorced on that account. Neither therefore can they be, if only one
commits fornication.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[1] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, spiritual fornication and certain other sins are more
grievous than carnal fornication. But separation from bed cannot be
motived by those sins. Neither therefore can it be done on account of
fornication.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[1] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, the unnatural vice is further removed from the marriage
goods than fornication is, the manner of which is natural. Therefore it
ought to have been a cause of separation rather than fornication.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[1] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, are the words of Mt. 5:32.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[1] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, one is not bound to keep faith with one who breaks his faith.
But a spouse by fornication breaks the faith due to the other spouse.
Therefore one can put the other away on account of fornication.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[1] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Our Lord permitted a man to put away his wife on account
of fornication, in punishment of the unfaithful party and in favor of the
faithful party, so that the latter is not bound to marital intercourse
with the unfaithful one. There are however seven cases to be excepted in
which it is not lawful to put away a wife who has committed fornication,
when either the wife is not to be blamed, or both parties are equally
blameworthy. The first is if the husband also has committed fornication;
the second is if he has prostituted his wife; the third is if the wife,
believing her husband dead on account of his long absence, has married
again; the fourth is if another man has fraudulently impersonated her
husband in the marriage-bed; the fifth is if she be overcome by force;
the sixth is if he has been reconciled to her by having carnal
intercourse with her after she has committed adultery; the seventh is if
both having been married in the state of unbelief, the husband has given
his wife a bill of divorce and she has married again; for then if both
be converted the husband is bound to receive her back again.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[1] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: A husband sins if through vindictive anger he puts away his
wife who has committed fornication, but he does not sin if he does so in
order to avoid losing his good name, lest he seem to share in her guilt,
or in order to correct his wife's sin, or in order to avoid the
uncertainty of her offspring.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[1] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Divorce on account of fornication is effected by the one
accusing the other. And since no one can accuse who is guilty of the same
crime, a divorce cannot be pronounced when both have committed
fornication, although marriage is more sinned against when both are
guilty of fornication that when only one is.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[1] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Fornication is directly opposed to the good of marriage,
since by it the certainty of offspring is destroyed, faith is broken, and
marriage ceases to have its signification when the body of one spouse is
given to several others. Wherefore other sins, though perhaps they be
more grievous than fornication, are not motives for a divorce. Since,
however, unbelief which is called spiritual fornication, is also opposed
to the good of marriage consisting in the rearing of the offspring to the
worship of God, it is also a motive for divorce, yet not in the same way
as bodily fornication. Because one may take steps for procuring a divorce
on account of one act of carnal fornication, not, however, on account of
one act of unbelief, but on account of inveterate unbelief which is a
proof of obstinacy wherein unbelief is perfected.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[1] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: Steps may be taken to procure a divorce on account also of
the unnatural vice: but this is not mentioned in the same way, both
because it is an unmentionable passion, and because it does not so affect
the certainty of offspring.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[2] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the husband is bound by precept to put away his wife when she is
guilty of fornication?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[2] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the husband is bound by precept to put away
his wife who is guilty of fornication. For since the husband is the head
of his wife, he is bound to correct his wife. Now separation from bed is
prescribed as a correction of the wife who is guilty of fornication.
Therefore he is bound to separate from her.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[2] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, he who consents with one who sins mortally, is also
guilty of mortal sin. Now the husband who retains a wife guilty of
fornication would seem to consent with her, as stated in the text (Sent.
iv, D, 35). Therefore he sins unless he puts her away.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[2] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, it is written (1 Cor. 6:16): "He who is joined to a
harlot is made one body." Now a man cannot at once be a member of a
harlot and a member of Christ (1 Cor. 6:15). Therefore the husband who
is joined to a wife guilty of fornication ceases to be a member of
Christ, and therefore sins mortally.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[2] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, just as relationship voids the marriage tie, so does
fornication dissolve the marriage-bed. Now after the husband becomes
cognizant of his consanguinity with his wife, he sins mortally if he has
carnal intercourse with her. Therefore he also sins mortally if he does
so after knowing her to be guilty of fornication.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[2] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: On the contrary, A gloss on 1 Cor. 7:11, "Let not the husband put
away his wife" says that "Our Lord permitted a wife to be put away on
account of fornication." Therefore it is not a matter of precept.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[2] Obj. 6 Para. 1/1
OBJ 6: Further, one can always pardon the sin that another has committed
against oneself. Now the wife, by committing fornication, sinned against
her husband. Therefore the husband may spare her by not putting her away.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[2] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, The putting away of a wife guilty of fornication was
prescribed in order that the wife might be corrected by means of that
punishment. Now a corrective punishment is not required when amendment
has already taken place. Wherefore, if the wife repent of her sin, her
husband is not bound to put her away: whereas if she repent not, he is
bound to do so, lest he seem to consent to her sin, by not having
recourse to her due correction.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[2] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The wife can be corrected for her sin of fornication not
only by this punishment but also by words and blows; wherefore if she be
ready to be corrected otherwise, her husband is not bound to have
recourse to the aforesaid punishment in order to correct her.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[2] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The husband seems to consent with her when he retains her,
notwithstanding that she persists in her past sin: if, however, she has
mended her ways, he does not consent with her.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[2] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: She can no longer be called a harlot since she has repented
of her sin. Wherefore her husband, by being joined to her, does not
become a member of a harlot. We might also reply that he is joined to her
not as a harlot but as his wife.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[2] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: There is no parallel, because the effect of consanguinity
is that there is no marriage tie between them, so that carnal intercourse
between them becomes unlawful. Whereas fornication does not remove the
said tie, so that the act remains, in itself, lawful, unless it become
accidentally unlawful, in so far as the husband seems to consent to his
wife's lewdness.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[2] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: This permission is to be understood as an absence of
prohibition: and thus it is not in contradistinction with a precept, for
that which is a matter of precept is also not forbidden.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[2] R.O. 6 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 6: The wife sins not only against her husband, but also
against herself and against God, wherefore her husband cannot entirely
remit the punishment, unless amendment has followed.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[3] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether the husband can on his own judgment put away his wife on account
of fornication?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[3] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that the husband can on his own judgment put away
his wife on account of fornication. For when sentence has been pronounced
by the judge, it is lawful to carry it out without any further judgment.
But God, the just Judge, has pronounced this judgment, that a husband may
put his wife away on account of fornication. Therefore no further
judgment is required for this.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[3] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, it is stated (Mt. 1:19) that Joseph . . . being a just
man . . . "was minded to put" Mary "away privately." Therefore it would
seem that a husband may privately pronounce a divorce without the
judgment of the Church.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[3] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, if after becoming cognizant of his wife's fornication a
husband has marital intercourse with his wife, he forfeits the action
which he had against the adulteress. Therefore the refusal of the
marriage debt, which pertains to a divorce, ought to precede the judgment
of the Church.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[3] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, that which cannot be proved ought not to be submitted to
the judgment of the Church. Now the crime of fornication cannot be
proved, since "the eye of the adulterer observeth darkness" (Job 24:15).
Therefore the divorce in question ought not to be made on the judgment of
the Church.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[3] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, accusation should be preceded by inscription [*Cf. SS,
Q[33], A[7]], whereby a person binds himself under the pain of
retaliation, if he fails to bring proof. But this is impossible in this
matter, because then, in every event the husband would obtain his end,
whether he put his wife away, or his wife put him away. Therefore she
ought not to be summoned by accusation to receive the judgment of the
Church.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[3] Obj. 6 Para. 1/1
OBJ 6: Further, a man is more bound to his wife than to a stranger. Now
a man ought not to refer to the Church the crime of another, even though
he be a stranger, without previously admonishing him privately (Mt.
18:15). Much less therefore may the husband bring his wife's crime before
the Church, unless he has previously rebuked her in private.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[3] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, No one should avenge himself. But if a husband were by
his own judgment to put away his wife on account of fornication, he would
avenge himself. Therefore this should not be done.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[3] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, no man is prosecutor and judge in the same cause. But the
husband is the prosecutor by suing his wife for the offense she has
committed against him. Therefore he cannot be the judge, and consequently
he cannot put her away on his own judgment.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[3] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, A husband can put away his wife in two ways. First as to
bed only, and thus he may put her away on his own judgment, as soon as he
has evidence of her fornication: nor is he bound to pay her the marriage
debt at her demand, unless he be compelled by the Church, and by paying
it thus he nowise prejudices his own case. Secondly, as to bed and board,
and in this way she cannot be put away except at the judgment of the
Church; and if she has been put away otherwise, he must be compelled to
cohabit with her unless the husband can at once prove the wife's
fornication. Now this putting away is called a divorce: and consequently
it must be admitted that a divorce cannot be pronounced except at the
judgment of the Church.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[3] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The sentence is an application of the general law to a
particular fact. Wherefore God gave out the law according to which the
sentence of the court has to be pronounced.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[3] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: Joseph was minded to put away the Blessed Virgin not as
suspected of fornication, but because in reverence for her sanctity, he
feared to cohabit with her. Moreover there is no parallel, because then
the sentence at law was not only divorce but also stoning, but not now
when the case is brought to the Church for judgment. The Reply to the
Third Objection is clear from what has been said.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[3] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: Sometimes when the husband suspects his wife of adultery he
watches her secretly that together with witnesses he may discover her in
the sin of fornication, and so proceed to accusation. Moreover, if he has
no evidence of the fact, there may be strong suspicions of fornication,
which suspicions being proved the fornication seems to be proved: for
instance if they be found together alone, at a time and place which are
open to suspicion, or "nudas cum nuda."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[3] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: A husband may accuse his wife of adultery in two ways.
First, he may seek a separation from bed before a spiritual judge, and
then there is no need for an inscription to be made under the pain of
retaliation, since thus the husband would gain his end, as the objection
proves. Secondly, he may seek for the crime to be punished in a secular
court, and then it is necessary for inscription to precede, whereby he
binds himself under pain of retaliation if he fail to prove his case.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[3] R.O. 6 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 6: According to a Decretal (Extra, De Simonia, cap. Licet),
"there are three modes of procedure in criminal cases. First, by
inquisition, which should be preceded by notoriety; secondly, by
accusation, which should be preceded by inscription; [*Cf. SS, Q[33],
A[7]] thirdly, by denunciation, which should be preceded by fraternal
correction." Accordingly the saying of our Lord refers to the case where
the process is by way of denunciation, and not by accusation, because
then the end in view is not only the correction of the guilty party, but
also his punishment, for the safeguarding of the common good, which would
be destroyed if justice were lacking.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[4] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether in a case of divorce husband and wife should be judged on a par
with each other?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[4] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that, in a case of divorce, husband and wife ought
not to be judged on a par with each other. For divorce under the New Law
takes the place of the divorce [repudium] recognized by the Old Law (Mt.
5:31,32). Now in the "repudium" husband and wife were not judged on a par
with each other, since the husband could put away his wife, but not "vice
versa." Therefore neither in divorce ought they to be judged on a par
with each other.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[4] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, it is more opposed to the natural law that a wife have
several husbands than that a husband have several wives: wherefore the
latter has been sometimes lawful, but the former never. Therefore the
wife sins more grievously in adultery than the husband, and consequently
they ought not to be judged on a par with each other.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[4] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, where there is greater injury to one's neighbor, there
is a greater sin. Now the adulterous wife does a greater injury to her
husband, than does the adulterous husband to his wife, since a wife's
adultery involves uncertainty of the offspring, whereas the husband's
adultery does not. Therefore the wife's sin is the greater, and so they
ought not to be judged on a par with each other.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[4] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, divorce is prescribed in order to punish the crime of
adultery. Now it belongs to the husband who is the head of the wife (1
Cor. 11:3) to correct his wife, rather than "vice versa." Therefore they
should not be judged on a par with each other for the purpose of divorce,
but the husband ought to have the preference.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[4] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: On the contrary, It would seem in this matter the wife ought to
have the preference. For the more frail the sinner the more is his sin
deserving of pardon. Now there is greater frailty in women than in men,
for which reason Chrysostom [*Hom. xl in the Opus Imperfectum falsely
ascribed to St. John Chrysostom] says that "lust is a passion proper to
women," and the Philosopher says (Ethic. vii, 7) that "properly speaking
women are not said to be continent on account of their being easily
inclined to concupiscence," for neither can dumb animals be continent,
because they have nothing to stand in the way of their desires. Therefore
women are rather to be spared in the punishment of divorce.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[4] Obj. 6 Para. 1/1
OBJ 6: Further, the husband is placed as the head of the woman in order
to correct her. Therefore his sin is greater than the woman's and so he
should be punished the more.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[4] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, In a case of divorce husband and wife are judged on a par
with each other, in the sense that the same things are lawful or unlawful
to the one as to the other: but they are not judged on a par with each
other in reference to those things, since the reason for divorce is
greater in one spouse than in the other, although there is sufficient
reason for divorce in both. For divorce is a punishment of adultery, in
so far as it is opposed to the marriage goods. Now as regards the good of
fidelity to which husband and wife are equally bound towards each other,
the adultery of one is as great a sin against marriage as the adultery of
the other, and this is in either of them a sufficient reason for divorce.
But as regards the good of the offspring the wife's adultery is a greater
sin against marriage than the husband's wherefore it is a greater reason
for divorce in the wife than in the husband: and thus they are under an
equal obligation, but not for equal reasons. Nor is this unjust for on
either hand there is sufficient reason for the punishment in question,
just as there is in two persons condemned to the punishment of death,
although one of them may have sinned more grievously than the other.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[4] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The only reason why divorce was permitted, was to avoid
murder. And since there was more danger of this in men than in women, the
husband was allowed to put away his wife by a bill of divorce, but not
"vice versa."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[4] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2 and 3: These arguments are based on the fact that in
comparison with the good of the offspring there is more reason for
divorce in an adulterous wife than in an adulterous husband. It does not
follow, however, that they are not judged on a par with each other.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[4] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: Although the husband is the head of the wife, he is her
pilot as it were, and is no more her judge than she is his. Consequently
in matters that have to be submitted to a judge, the husband has no more
power over his wife, than she over him.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[4] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: In adultery there is the same sinful character as in simple
fornication, and something more which aggravates it, namely the lesion to
marriage. Accordingly if we consider that which is common to adultery and
fornication, the sin of the husband and that of the wife are compared the
one to the other as that which exceeds to that which is exceeded, for in
women the humors are more abundant, wherefore they are more inclined to
be led by their concupiscences, whereas in man there is abundance of heat
which excites concupiscence. Simply speaking, however, other things being
equal, a man sins more grievously in simple fornication than a woman,
because he has more of the good of reason, which prevails over all
movements of bodily passions. But as regards the lesion to marriage which
adultery adds to fornication and for which reason it is an occasion for
divorce, the woman sins more grievously than the man, as appears from
what we have said above. And since it is more grievous than simple
fornication, it follows that, simply speaking, the adulterous wife sins
more grievously than the adulterous husband, other things being equal.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[4] R.O. 6 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 6: Although the control which the husband receives over his
wife is an aggravating circumstance, nevertheless the sin is yet more
aggravated by this circumstance which draws the sin to another species,
namely by the lesion to marriage, which lesion becomes a kind of
injustice, through the fraudulent substitution of another's child.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[5] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether a husband can marry again after having a divorce?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[5] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that a husband can marry again after having a
divorce. For no one is bound to perpetual continence. Now in some cases
the husband is bound to put away his wife forever on account of
fornication, as stated above (A[2]). Therefore seemingly at least in this
case he can marry again.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[5] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, a sinner should not be given a greater occasion of sin.
But if she who is put away on account of the sin of fornication is not
allowed to seek another marriage, she is given a greater occasion of sin:
for it is improbable that one who was not continent during marriage will
be able to be continent afterwards. Therefore it would seem lawful for
her to marry again.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[5] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, the wife is not bound to the husband save as regards the
payment of the marriage debt and cohabitation. But she is freed from both
obligations by divorce. Therefore "she is loosed from the law of her
husband" [*Rm. 7:2]. Therefore she can marry again; and the same applies
to her husband.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[5] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, it is said (Mt. 19:9): "Whosoever shall put away his
wife, except it be for fornication, and shall marry another committeth
adultery." Therefore seemingly he does not commit adultery if he marry
again after putting away his wife on account of fornication, and
consequently this will be a true marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[5] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, It is written (1 Cor. 7:10,11): "Not I, but the Lord,
commandeth that the wife depart not from her husband. and, if she depart,
that she remain unmarried."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[5] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, no one should gain advantage from sin. But the adulteress would
if she were allowed to contract another and more desired marriage; and an
occasion of adultery would be afforded those who wish to marry again.
Therefore it is unlawful both to the wife and to the husband to contract
a second marriage.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[5] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, Nothing supervenient to marriage can dissolve it:
wherefore adultery does not make a marriage cease to be valid. For,
according to Augustine (De Nup. et Concup. i, 10), "as long as they live
they are bound by the marriage tie, which neither divorce nor union with
another can destroy." Therefore it is unlawful for one, while the other
lives, to marry again.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[5] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: Although no one is absolutely bound to continence, he may
be bound accidentally; for instance, if his wife contract an incurable
disease that is incompatible with carnal intercourse. And it is the same
if she labor under a spiritual disease, namely fornication, so as to be
incorrigible.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[5] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The very shame of having been divorced ought to keep her
from sin: and if it cannot keep her from sin, it is a lesser evil that
she alone sin than that her husband take part in her sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[5] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: Although after divorce the wife is not bound to her husband
as regards paying him the marriage debt and cohabiting with him, the
marriage tie, whereby she was bound to this, remains, and consequently
she cannot marry again during her husband's lifetime. She can, however,
take a vow of continence, against her husband's will, unless it seem that
the Church has been deceived by false witnesses in pronouncing the
divorce; for in that case, even if she has made her vow of profession she
ought to be restored to her husband, and would be bound to pay the
marriage debt, but it would be unlawful for her to demand it.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[5] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: The exception expressed in our Lord's words refers to the
putting away of the wife. Hence the objection is based on a false
interpretation.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[6] Thes. Para. 1/1
Whether husband and wife may be reconciled after being divorced?
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[6] Obj. 1 Para. 1/1
OBJ 1: It would seem that husband and wife may not be reconciled after
being divorced. For the law contains the rule (Can. Quod bene semel,
Caus. vi, qu. iv): "That which has been once well decided must not be
subsequently withdrawn." Now it has been decided by the judgment of the
Church that they ought to be separated. Therefore they cannot
subsequently be reconciled.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[6] Obj. 2 Para. 1/1
OBJ 2: Further, if it were allowable for them to be reconciled, the
husband would seem bound to receive his wife, especially after she has
repented. But he is not bound, for the wife, in defending herself before
the judge, cannot allege her repentance against her husband's accusation
of fornication. Therefore in no way is reconciliation allowable.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[6] Obj. 3 Para. 1/1
OBJ 3: Further, if reconciliation were allowable, it would seem that the
adulterous wife is bound to return to her husband if her husband asks
her. But she is not bound, since they are separated by the Church.
Therefore, etc.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[6] Obj. 4 Para. 1/1
OBJ 4: Further, if it were lawful to be reconciled to an adulterous
wife, this would especially be the case when the husband is found to have
committed adultery after the divorce. But in this case the wife cannot
compel him to be reconciled, since the divorce has been justly
pronounced. Therefore she may nowise be reconciled.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[6] Obj. 5 Para. 1/1
OBJ 5: Further, if a husband whose adultery is unknown put away his
wife, who is convicted of adultery by the sentence of the Church, the
divorce would seem to have been pronounced unjustly. And yet the husband
is not bound to be reconciled to his wife, because she is unable to prove
his adultery in court. Much less, therefore, is reconciliation allowable
when the divorce has been granted justly.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[6] OTC Para. 1/2
On the contrary, It is written (1 Cor. 7:11): "And if she depart, that
she remain unmarried, or be reconciled to her husband."
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[6] OTC Para. 2/2
Further, it is allowable for the husband not to put her away after
fornication. Therefore, for the same reason, he can be reconciled to her
after divorce.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[6] Body Para. 1/1
I answer that, If the wife has mended her ways by repenting of her sin
after the divorce, her husband may become reconciled to her; but if she
remain incorrigible in her sin, he must not take her back, for the same
reason which forbade him to retain her while she refused to desist from
sin.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[6] R.O. 1 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 1: The sentence of the Church in pronouncing the divorce did
not bind them to separate, but allowed them to do so. Therefore
reconciliation may be effected or ensue without any withdrawal of the
previous sentence.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[6] R.O. 2 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 2: The wife's repentance should induce the husband not to
accuse or put away the wife who is guilty of fornication. He cannot,
however, be compelled to this course of action, nor can his wife oppose
her repentance to his accusation, because although she is no longer
guilty, neither in act nor in the stain of sin, there still remains
something of the debt of punishment, and though this has been taken away
in the sight of God, there still remains the debt of punishment to be
inflicted by the judgment of man, because man sees not the heart as God
does.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[6] R.O. 3 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 3: That which is done in a person's favor does him no
prejudice. Wherefore since the divorce has been granted in favor of the
husband, it does not deprive him of the right of asking for the marriage
debt, or of asking his wife to return to him. Hence his wife is bound to
pay the debt, and to return to him, if he ask her, unless with his
consent she has taken a vow of continence.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[6] R.O. 4 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 4: According to strict law, a husband who was previously
innocent should not be compelled to receive an adulterous wife on account
of his having committed adultery after the divorce. But according to
equity, the judge is bound by virtue of his office first of all to
admonish him to beware of imperiling his own soul and of scandalizing
others; although the wife may not herself seek reconciliation.
Aquin.: SMT XP Q[62] A[6] R.O. 5 Para. 1/1
Reply OBJ 5: If the husband's adultery is secret, this does not deprive
his adulterous wife of the right to allege it in self-defense, although
she cannot prove it. Wherefore the husband sins by seeking a divorce, and
if, after the sentence of divorce, his wife asks for the marriage debt or
for a reconciliation, the husband is bound to both.