Path: senator-bedfellow.mit.edu!dreaderd!not-for-mail
Message-ID: <anarchy/theory/[email protected]>
Supersedes: <anarchy/theory/[email protected]>
Expires: 31 May 2004 11:22:46 GMT
X-Last-Updated: 1997/09/11
Organization: none
From: [email protected] (Bryan Caplan)
Newsgroups: alt.society.anarchy,alt.anarchism,talk.politics.theory,alt.politics.economics,alt.politics.libertarian,alt.individualism,alt.philosophy.objectivism,talk.politics.libertarian,alt.politics.radical-left,alt.fan.noam-chomsky,alt.answers,talk.answers,news.answers
Subject: Anarchist Theory FAQ Version 5.2
Followup-To: poster
Approved: [email protected]
Summary: This FAQ discusses anarchist theory, with a strong emphasis
upon the many Net controversies between left-anarchists and
anarcho-capitalists.
Originator: [email protected]
Date: 17 Apr 2004 11:27:22 GMT
Lines: 2708
NNTP-Posting-Host: penguin-lust.mit.edu
X-Trace: 1082201242 senator-bedfellow.mit.edu 568 18.181.0.29
Xref: senator-bedfellow.mit.edu alt.society.anarchy:177617 alt.anarchism:179220 talk.politics.theory:237492 alt.politics.economics:376803 alt.politics.libertarian:769391 alt.individualism:69909 alt.philosophy.objectivism:247608 talk.politics.libertarian:674010 alt.politics.radical-left:318195 alt.fan.noam-chomsky:171971 alt.answers:72476 talk.answers:7056 news.answers:269852

Archive-name: anarchy/theory/faq
Posting-Frequency: monthly

---------------------------------------------------------------------
This is a slightly revised version of my FAQ on anarchist theory. As
always, comments, criticisms, and corrections will be much appreciated. In
particular, if you think that any argument or viewpoint has been presented
weakly or inadequately, please write me at [email protected] to
discuss your preferred formulation.

To view the hypertext version of the FAQ (so the links work), go to
http://www.gmu.edu/departments/economics/bcaplan.

---------------------------------------------------------------------------


                           Anarchist Theory FAQ

                                    or

             Instead of a FAQ, by a Man Too Busy to Write One

                                    by

                               Bryan Caplan

                               Version 5.2

    I heartily accept the motto, - "That government is best which
    governs least;" and I should like to see it acted up to more
    rapidly and systematically.  Carried out, it finally amounts to
    this, which I also believe, - "That government is best which
    governs not at all;" and when men are prepared for it, that
    will be the kind of government which they will have.

            --Henry David Thoreau,
              "On the Duty of Civil Disobedience"

    Some writers have so confounded society with government, as to
    leave little or no distinction between them; whereas they are not
    only different, but have different origins ... Society is in
    every state a blessing, but Government, even in its best state,
    is but a necessary evil; in its worst state, an intolerable one.

            --Thomas Paine,
              Common Sense

    They [the Marxists] maintain that only a dictatorship -- their
    dictatorship, of course -- can create the will of the people,
    while our answer to this is: No dictatorship can have any other
    aim but that of self-perpetuation, and it can beget only slavery
    in the people tolerating it; freedom can be created only by
    freedom, that is, by a universal rebellion on the part of the
    people and free organization of the toiling masses from the
    bottom up.

            --Mikhail Bakunin,
              Statism and Anarchism

    In existing States a fresh law is looked upon as a remedy for
    evil. Instead of themselves altering what is bad, people begin by
    demanding a law to alter it. If the road between two villages is
    impassable, the peasant says, "There should be a law about parish
    roads." If a park-keeper takes advantage of the want of spirit in
    those who follow him with servile obedience and insults one of
    them, the insulted man says, "There should be a law to enjoin
    more politeness upon the park-keepers." If there is stagnation in
    agriculture or commerce, the husbandman, cattle-breeder, or corn-
    speculator argues, "It is protective legislation which we
    require." Down to the old clothesman there is not one who does
    not demand a law to protect his own little trade. If the employer
    lowers wages or increases the hours of labor, the politician in
    embryo explains, "We must have a law to put all that to rights."
    In short, a law everywhere and for everything! A law about
    fashions, a law about mad dogs, a law about virtue, a law to put
    a stop to all the vices and all the evils which result from human
    indolence and cowardice.

            --Peter Kropotkin,
              "Law and Authority"

    [W]hoever desires liberty, should understand these vital facts,
    viz.: 1. That every man who puts money into the hands of a
    "government" (so called) puts into its hands a sword which will
    be used against himself, to extort more money from him, and also
    to keep him in subjection to its arbitrary will. 2. That those
    who will take his money, without his consent, in the first place,
    will use it for his further robbery and enslavement, if he
    presumes to resist their demands in the future. 3. That it is a
    perfect absurdity to suppose that any body of men would ever take
    a man's money without his consent, for any such object as they
    profess to take it for, viz., that of protecting him; for why
    should they wish to protect him, if he does not wish them to do
    so?... 4. If a man wants "protection," he is competent to make
    his own bargains for it; and nobody has any occasion to rob him,
    in order to "protect" him against his will. 5. That the only
    security men can have for their political liberty, consists in
    their keeping their money in their own pockets, until they have
    assurances, perfectly satisfactory to themselves, that it will be
    used as they wish it to be used, for their benefit, and not for
    their injury. 6. That no government, so called, can reasonably be
    trusted for a moment, or reasonably be supposed to have honest
    purposes in view, any longer than it depends wholly upon
    voluntary support.

            --Lysander Spooner,
              No Treason: the Constitution of No Authority

    If we look at the black record of mass murder, exploitation, and
    tyranny levied on society by governments over the ages, we need
    not be loath to abandon the Leviathan State and ... try freedom.

            --Murray Rothbard,
              For a New Liberty

---------------------------------------------------------------------------

                            Table of Contents

 1. What is anarchism? What beliefs do anarchists share?
 2. Why should one consider anarchism in the first place?
 3. Don't anarchists favor chaos?
 4. Don't anarchists favor the abolition of the family, property,
    religion, and other social institutions besides the state?
 5. What major subdivisions may be made among anarchists?
 6. Is anarchism the same thing as libertarianism?
 7. Is anarchism the same thing as socialism?
 8. Who are the major anarchist thinkers?
 9. How would left-anarchy work?
10. How would anarcho-capitalism work?
11. What criticisms have been made of anarchism?
      a. "An anarchist society, lacking any central coercive authority,
         would quickly degenerate into violent chaos."
      b. The Marxist critique of left-anarchism
      c. The minarchists' attack on anarcho-capitalism
      d. The conservative critique of anarchism
      e. "We are already in a state of anarchy."
12. What other anarchist viewpoints are there?
13. What moral justifications have been offered for anarchism?
14. What are the major debates between anarchists? What are the recurring
    arguments?
      a. "X is not 'true anarchism.'"
      b. "Anarchism of variant X is unstable and will lead to the
         re-emergence of the state."
      c. "In an anarchist society in which both systems X and Y existed, X
         would inevitably outcompete Y."
      d. "Anarchism of type X would be worse than the state."
      e. Etc.
15. How would anarchists handle the "public goods" problem?
      a. The concept and uses of Pareto optimality in economics
      b. The public goods problem
16. Are anarchists pacifists?
      a. Tolstoyan absolute pacifism
      b. Pacifism as opposition to war
17. Have there been any historical examples of anarchist societies?
18. Isn't anarchism utopian?
19. Don't anarchists assume that all people are innately virtuous?
20. Aren't anarchists terrorists?
21. How might an anarchist society be achieved?
22. What are some addresses for anarchist World Wide Web sites?
23. What are some major anarchist writings?

    ----------------------------------------------------------------------

      1. What is anarchism? What beliefs do anarchists share?

         Anarchism is defined by The American Heritage College Dictionary
         as "The theory or doctrine that all forms of government are
         unnecessary, oppressive, and undesirable and should be
         abolished." Anarchism is a negative; it holds that one thing,
         namely government, is bad and should be abolished. Aside from
         this defining tenet, it would be difficult to list any belief
         that all anarchists hold. Just as atheists might support or
         oppose any viewpoint consistent with the non-existence of God,
         anarchists might and indeed do hold the entire range of
         viewpoints consistent with the non-existence of the state.

         As might be expected, different groups of anarchists are
         constantly trying to define anarchists with different views out
         of existence, just as many Christians say that their sect is the
         only "true" Christianity and many socialists say that their
         socialism is the only "true" socialism. This FAQ takes what seems
         to me to be the impartial view that such tactics are pointless
         and merely prevent the debate of substantive issues. (N.B. The
         preceding definition has been criticized a number of times. To
         view my appendix on Defining Anarchism, click here.)

      2. Why should one consider anarchism in the first place?

         Unlike many observers of history, anarchists see a common thread
         behind most of mankind's problems: the state. In the 20th-century
         alone, states have murdered well over 100,000,000 human beings,
         whether in war, concentration camps, or man-made famine. And this
         is merely a continuation of a seemingly endless historical
         pattern: almost from the beginning of recorded history,
         governments have existed. Once they arose, they allowed a ruling
         class to live off the labor of the mass of ordinary people; and
         these ruling classes have generally used their ill-gotten gains
         to build armies and wage war to extend their sphere of influence.
         At the same time, governments have always suppressed unpopular
         minorities, dissent, and the efforts of geniuses and innovators
         to raise humanity to new intellectual, moral, cultural, and
         economic heights. By transferring surplus wealth from producers
         to the state's ruling elite, the state has often strangled any
         incentive for long-run economic growth and thus stifled
         humanity's ascent from poverty; and at the same time the state
         has always used that surplus wealth to cement its power.

         If the state is the proximate cause of so much needless misery
         and cruelty, would it not be desirable to investigate the
         alternatives? Perhaps the state is a necessary evil which we
         cannot eliminate. But perhaps it is rather an unnecessary evil
         which we accept out of inertia when a totally different sort of
         society would be a great improvement.

      3. Don't anarchists favor chaos?

         By definition, anarchists oppose merely government, not order or
         society. "Liberty is the Mother, not the Daughter of Order" wrote
         Proudhon, and most anarchists would be inclined to agree.
         Normally, anarchists demand abolition of the state because they
         think that they have something better to offer, not out of a
         desire for rebellion as such. Or as Kropotkin put it, "No
         destruction of the existing order is possible, if at the time of
         the overthrow, or of the struggle leading to the overthrow, the
         idea of what is to take the place of what is to be destroyed is
         not always present in the mind. Even the theoretical criticism of
         the existing conditions is impossible, unless the critic has in
         mind a more or less distinct picture of what he would have in
         place of the existing state. Consciously or unconsciously, the
         ideal, the conception of something better is forming in the mind
         of everyone who criticizes social institutions."

         There is an anti-intellectual strain in anarchism which favors
         chaos and destruction as an end-in-itself. While possibly a
         majority among people who have called themselves anarchists, this
         is not a prominent strand of thought among those who have
         actually spent time thinking and writing about anarchist theory.

      4. Don't anarchists favor the abolition of the family, property,
         religion, and other social institutions besides the state?

         Some anarchists have favored the abolition of one or more of the
         above, while others have not. To some, all of these are merely
         other forms of oppression and domination. To others, they are the
         vital intermediary institutions which protect us from the state.
         To still others, some of the above are good and others are bad;
         or perhaps they are bad currently, but merit reform.

      5. What major subdivisions may be made among anarchists?

         As should become plain to the reader of alt.society.anarchy or
         alt.anarchism, there are two rather divergent lines of anarchist
         thought. The first is broadly known as "left-anarchism," and
         encompasses anarcho-socialists, anarcho-syndicalists, and
         anarcho-communists. These anarchists believe that in an anarchist
         society, people either would or should abandon or greatly reduce
         the role of private property rights. The economic system would be
         organized around cooperatives, worker-owned firms, and/or
         communes. A key value in this line of anarchist thought is
         egalitarianism, the view that inequalities, especially of wealth
         and power, are undesirable, immoral, and socially contingent.

         The second is broadly known as "anarcho-capitalism." These
         anarchists believe that in an anarchist society, people either
         would or should not only retain private property, but expand it
         to encompass the entire social realm. No anarcho-capitalist has
         ever denied the right of people to voluntarily pool their private
         property and form a cooperative, worker-owned firm, or commune;
         but they also believe that several property, including such
         organizations as corporations, are not only perfectly legitimate
         but likely to be the predominant form of economic organization
         under anarchism. Unlike the left-anarchists, anarcho-capitalists
         generally place little or no value on equality, believing that
         inequalities along all dimensions -- including income and wealth
         -- are not only perfectly legitimate so long as they "come about
         in the right way," but are the natural consequence of human
         freedom.

         A large segment of left-anarchists is extremely skeptical about
         the anarchist credentials of anarcho-capitalists, arguing that
         the anarchist movement has historically been clearly leftist. In
         my own view, it is necessary to re-write a great deal of history
         to maintain this claim. In Carl Landauer's European Socialism: A
         History of Ideas and Movements (published in 1959 before any
         important modern anarcho-capitalist works had been written), this
         great socialist historian notes that:

              To be sure, there is a difference between
              individualistic anarchism and collectivistic or
              communistic anarchism; Bakunin called himself a
              communist anarchist. But the communist anarchists also
              do not acknowledge any right to society to force the
              individual. They differ from the anarchistic
              individualists in their belief that men, if freed from
              coercion, will enter into voluntary associations of a
              communistic type, while the other wing believes that
              the free person will prefer a high degree of isolation.
              The communist anarchists repudiate the right of private
              property which is maintained through the power of the
              state. The individualist anarchists are inclined to
              maintain private property as a necessary condition of
              individual independence, without fully answering the
              question of how property could be maintained without
              courts and police.

         Actually, Tucker and Spooner both wrote about the free market's
         ability to provide legal and protection services, so Landauer's
         remark was not accurate even in 1959. But the interesting point
         is that before the emergence of modern anarcho-capitalism
         Landauer found it necessary to distinguish two strands of
         anarchism, only one of which he considered to be within the broad
         socialist tradition.

      6. Is anarchism the same thing as libertarianism?

         This is actually a complicated question, because the term
         "libertarianism" itself has two very different meanings. In
         Europe in the 19th-century, libertarianism was a popular
         euphemism for left-anarchism. However, the term did not really
         catch on in the United States.

         After World War II, many American-based pro-free-market
         intellectuals opposed to traditional conservatism were seeking
         for a label to describe their position, and eventually picked
         "libertarianism." ("Classical liberalism" and "market liberalism"
         are alternative labels for the same essential position.) The
         result was that in two different political cultures which rarely
         communicated with one another, the term "libertarian" was used in
         two very different ways. At the current time, the American use
         has basically taken over completely in academic political theory
         (probably owing to Nozick's influence), but the European use is
         still popular among many left-anarchist activists in both Europe
         and the U.S.

         The semantic confusion was complicated further when some of the
         early post-war American libertarians determined that the logical
         implication of their view was, in fact, a variant of anarchism.
         They adopted the term "anarcho-capitalism" to differentiate
         themselves from more moderate libertarianism, but were still
         generally happy to identify themselves with the broader
         free-market libertarian movement.

      7. Is anarchism the same thing as socialism?

         If we accept one traditional definition of socialism -- "advocacy
         of government ownership of the means of production" -- it seems
         that anarchists are not socialists by definition. But if by
         socialism we mean something more inclusive, such as "advocacy of
         the strong restriction or abolition of private property," then
         the question becomes more complex.

         Under the second proffered definition, some anarchists are
         socialists, but others are not. Outside of the Anglo- American
         political culture, there has been a long and close historical
         relationship between the more orthodox socialists who advocate a
         socialist government, and the anarchist socialists who desire
         some sort of decentralized, voluntary socialism. The two groups
         both want to severely limit or abolish private property and thus
         both groups fit the second definition of socialism. However, the
         anarchists certainly do not want the government to own the means
         of production, for they don't want government to exist in the
         first place.

         The anarchists' dispute with the traditional socialists -- a
         dispute best illustrated by the bitter struggle between Karl Marx
         and Mikhail Bakunin for dominance in the 19th-century European
         workers' movement -- has often be described as a disagreement
         over "means." On this interpretation, the socialist anarchists
         and the state-socialists agree that a communal and egalitarian
         society is desirable, but accuse one another of proposing
         ineffective means of attaining it. However, this probably
         understates the conflict, which is also over more fundamental
         values: socialist anarchists emphasize the need for autonomy and
         the evils of authoritarianism, while traditional socialists have
         frequently belittled such concerns as "bourgeois."

         When we turn to the Anglo-American political culture, the
         story is quite different. Virulent anti-socialist
         anarchism is much more common there, and has been from the early
         19th-century. Great Britain was the home of many intensely
         anti-socialist quasi-anarchistic thinkers of the 19th-century
         such as Auberon Herbert and the early Herbert Spencer. The United
         States has been an even more fertile ground for individualist
         anarchism: during the 19th-century, such figures as Josiah
         Warren, Lysander Spooner , and Benjamin Tucker gained prominence
         for their vision of an anarchism based upon freedom of contract
         and private property. And in the 20th-century, thinkers residing
         within the United States have been the primary developers and
         exporters of anarcho-capitalist theory.

         Still, this geographic division should not be over-stated. The
         French anarchist Proudhon and the German Max Stirner both
         embraced modified forms of individualism; a number of
         left-anarchists (often European immigrants) attained prominence
         in the United States; and Noam Chomsky and Murray Bookchin, two
         of the most influential theorists of modern left-anarchism, both
         reside within the United States.

      8. Who are the major anarchist thinkers?

         The most famous left-anarchists have probably been
         Mikhail Bakunin and Peter Kropotkin. Pierre Proudhon is
         also often included although his ideas on the desirability of a
         modified form of private property would lead some to exclude him
         from the leftist camp altogether. (Some of Proudhon's other
         heterodoxies include his defense of the right of inheritance and
         his emphasis on the genuine antagonism between state power and
         property rights.) More recent left-anarchists include Emma
         Goldman, Murray Bookchin , and Noam Chomsky.

         Anarcho-capitalism has a much more recent origin in the latter
         half of the 20th century. The two most famous advocates of
         anarcho-capitalism are probably Murray Rothbard and David
         Friedman. There were however some interesting earlier precursors,
         notably the Belgian economist Gustave de Molinari. Two other
         19th-century anarchists who have been adopted by modern
         anarcho-capitalists with a few caveats are Benjamin Tucker and
         Lysander Spooner. (Some left-anarchists contest the adoption, but
         overall Tucker and Spooner probably have much more in
         common with anarcho-capitalists than with
         left-anarchists.)

         More comprehensive listings of anarchist figures may be found in
         a number of broad historical works listed later in the FAQ.

      9. How would left-anarchy work?

         There are many different views on this. Among left- anarchists,
         there are some who imagine returning to a much simpler, even
         pre-industrial, mode of social organization. Others seem to
         intend to maintain modern technology and civilization (perhaps in
         a more environmentally sound manner) but end private ownership of
         the means of production.

         To be replaced with what? Various suggestions have been made.
         Existing firms might simply be turned over to worker ownership,
         and then be subject to the democratic control of the workers.
         This is the anarcho-syndicalist picture: keeping an economy based
         upon a multitude of firms, but with firms owned and managed by
         the workers at each firm. Presumably firms would then strike
         deals with one another to secure needed materials; or perhaps
         firms would continue to pay money wages and sell products to
         consumers. It is unclear how the syndicalist intends to arrange
         for the egalitarian care of the needy, or the provision of
         necessary but unprofitable products. Perhaps it is supposed that
         syndicates would contribute out of social responsibility; others
         have suggested that firms would elect representatives for a
         larger meta-firm organization which would carry out the necessary
         tasks.

         It should be noted that Tom Wetzel disputes my characterization
         of anarcho-syndicalism; he argues that very few
         anarcho-syndicalists ever imagined that workers would simply take
         over their firms, while maintaining the basic features of the
         market economy. Rather, the goal has usually been the
         establishment of an overarching democratic structure, rather than
         a multitude of uncoordinated firm-centered democracies. Or at
         Wetzel states, "Anarcho-syndicalism advocates the development of
         a mass workers' movement based on direct democracy as the vehicle
         for reorganization of the society on the basis of direct workers'
         collective power over social production, thus eliminating the
         domination and exploitation of the producing class by an
         exploiting class. Workers cannot have collective power over the
         system of social production as isolated groups competing in a
         market economy; rather, workers self- management requires
         structures of democratic control over social production and
         public affairs generally. Workers' self- management thus refers,
         not just to self-management of the individual workplace, but of
         the whole system of social production. This requires grassroots
         bodies, such as workers' congresses or conventions, through which
         coordinated policies for the society can be developed in a
         democratic manner. This is proposed as a substitute or
         replacement for the historical nation-state." On this
         interpretation of anarcho-syndicalism, the revolutionary trade
         unions are a means for achieving an anarchist society, rather
         than a proposed basis for social organization under anarchy.

         Many would observe that there is nothing anarchistic about this
         proposal; indeed, names aside, it fits easily into the orthodox
         state-socialist tradition. Bakunin would have probably ridiculed
         such ideas as authoritarian Marxist socialism in disguise, and
         predicted that the leading anarchist revolutionaries would
         swiftly become the new despots. But Wetzel is perhaps right that
         many or even most historical anarcho-syndicalists were
         championing the system outlined in his preceding quotation. He
         goes on to add that "[I]f you look at the concept of 'state' in
         the very abstract way it often is in the social sciences, as in
         Weber's definition, then what the anarcho-syndicalists were
         proposing is not elimination of the state or government, but its
         radical democratization. That was not how anarchists themselves
         spoke about it, but it can be plausibly argued that this is a
         logical consequence of a certain major stream of left-anarchist
         thought."

         Ronald Fraser's discussion of the ideology of the Spanish
         Anarchists (historically the largest European anarchist movement)
         strongly undermines Wetzel's claim, however. There were two
         well-developed lines of thought, both of which favored the
         abolition of the State in the broad Weberian sense of the word,
         and which did indeed believe that the workers should literally
         have control over their workplaces. After distinguishing the
         rural and the urban tendencies among the Spanish ideologists,
         Fraser explains:

              Common to both tendencies was the idea that the working
              class 'simply' took over factories and workplaces and
              ran them collectively but otherwise as before...
              Underlying this vision of simple continuity was the
              anarcho-syndicalist concept of the revolution not as a
              rupture with, the destruction and replacement of, the
              bourgeois order but as the latter's displacement. The
              taking over of factories and workplaces, however
              violently carried out, was not the beginning of the
              revolution to create a new order but its final goal.
              This view, in turn was conditioned by a particular view
              of the state. Any state (bourgeois or working class)
              was considered an oppressive power tout court - not as
              the organization of a particular class's coercive
              power. The 'state' in consequence, rather than the
              existence of the capitalist mode of production which
              gave rise to its particular form, often appeared as the
              major enemy. The state did not have to be taken,
              crushed, and a new - revolutionary - power established.
              No. If it could be swept away, abolished, everything
              else, including oppression, disappeared. The capitalist
              order was simply displaced by the new-won workers'
              freedom to administer the workplaces they had taken
              over. Self-organized in autonomous communes or in
              all-powerful syndicates, the workers, as the primary
              factor in production, dispensed with the bourgeoisie.
              The consequences of this were seen in the 1936
              Barcelona revolution; capitalist production and market
              relations continued to exist within collectivized
              industry.

         Overall, the syndicalist is probably the best elaborated of the
         left-anarchist systems. But others in the broader tradition
         imagine individuals forming communes and cooperatives which would
         be less specialized and more self- sufficient than the typical
         one-product-line anarcho- syndicalist firm. These notions are
         often closely linked to the idea of creating a more
         environmentally sound society, in which small and decentralized
         collectives redirect their energies towards a Greener way of
         life.

         Many left-anarchists and anarchist sympathizers have also been
         attracted to Guild Socialism in one form or another. Economist
         Roger A. McCain thoughtfully explores Guild Socialism as an
         alternative to both capitalism and the state in "Guild Socialism
         Reconsidered," one of his working papers. To view it, click here.

         Kropotkin's lucid essay "Law and Authority" gives a
         thoughtful presentation of the left-anarchist's view of
         law. Primitive human societies, explains Kropotkin, live by what
         legal thinkers call "customary law": an unwritten but broadly
         understood body of rules and appropriate behavior backed up
         primarily by social pressure. Kropotkin considers this sort of
         behavioral regulation to be unobjectionable, and probably
         consistent with his envisaged anarchist society. But when
         centralized governments codified customary law, they mingled the
         sensible dictates of tribal conscience with governmental
         sanctions for exploitation and injustice. As Kropotkin writes,
         "[L]egislators confounded in one code the two currents of custom
         ... the maxims which represent principles of morality and social
         union wrought out as a result of life in common, and the mandates
         which are meant to ensure external existence to inequality.
         Customs, absolutely essential to the very being of society, are,
         in the code, cleverly intermingled with usages imposed by the
         ruling caste, and both claim equal respect from the crowd. 'Do
         not kill,' says the code, and hastens to add, 'And pay tithes to
         the priest.' 'Do not steal,' says the code, and immediately
         after, 'He who refuses to pay taxes, shall have his hand struck
         off.'"

         So perhaps Kropotkin's ideal society would live under the
         guidance of a reformed customary law stripped of the class
         legislation with which it is now so closely associated. But
         Kropotkin continues to give what appear to be arguments against
         even customary law prohibiting e.g. murder. Almost all violent
         crime is actually caused by poverty and inequality created by
         existing law. A small residual of violent crime might persist,
         but efforts to handle it by legal channels are futile. Why?
         Because punishment has no effect on crime, especially such crimes
         of passion as would survive the abolition of private property.
         Moreover, criminals should not be judged wicked, but rather
         treated as we now treat the sick and disadvantaged.

         Most left-anarchists probably hold to a mix of Kropotkin's fairly
         distinct positions on law and crime. Existing law should be
         replaced by sensible and communitarian customs; and the critic of
         anarchism underestimates the extent to which existing crime is in
         fact a product of the legal system's perpetuation of inequality
         and poverty. And since punishment is not an effective deterrent,
         and criminals are not ultimately responsible for their misdeeds,
         a strictly enforced legal code may be undesirable anyway.

         Some other crucial features of the left-anarchist society are
         quite unclear. Whether dissidents who despised all forms of
         communal living would be permitted to set up their own
         inegalitarian separatist societies is rarely touched upon.
         Occasionally left-anarchists have insisted that small farmers and
         the like would not be forcibly collectivized, but the limits of
         the right to refuse to adopt an egalitarian way of life are
         rarely specified.

     10. How would anarcho-capitalism work?

         Most of the prominent anarcho-capitalist writers have been
         academic economists, and as such have felt it necessary to spell
         out the workings of their preferred society in rather greater
         detail than the left-anarchists have. In order to best grasp the
         anarcho-capitalist position, it is helpful to realize that
         anarcho-capitalists have emerged almost entirely out of the
         modern American libertarian movement, and believe that their view
         is simply a slightly more extreme version of the libertarianism
         propounded by e.g. Robert Nozick.

         FAQs on the broader libertarian movement are widely
         available on the Net, so we will only give the necessary
         background here. So-called "minarchist" libertarians such as
         Nozick have argued that the largest justified government was one
         which was limited to the protection of individuals and their
         private property against physical invasion; accordingly, they
         favor a government limited to supplying police, courts, a legal
         code, and national defense. This normative theory is closely
         linked to laissez-faire economic theory, according to which
         private property and unregulated competition generally lead to
         both an efficient allocation of resources and (more importantly)
         a high rate of economic progress. While left-anarchists are often
         hostile to "bourgeois economics," anarcho-capitalists hold
         classical economists such as Adam Smith, David Hume, and
         Jean-Baptiste Say in high regard, as well as more modern
         economists such as Joseph Schumpeter, Ludwig von Mises, F.A.
         Hayek, Milton Friedman, George Stigler, and James Buchanan. The
         problem with free-market economists, say the anarcho-capitalists,
         is not that they defend the free market, but merely that their
         defense is too moderate and compromising.

         (Note however that the left-anarchists' low opinion of
         the famous "free-market economists" is not monolithic:
         Noam Chomsky in particular has repeatedly praised some of the
         political insights of Adam Smith. And Peter Kropotkin also had
         good things to say about Smith as both social scientist and
         moralist; Conal Smith explains that "In particular he approved of
         Smith's attempt to apply the scientific method to the study of
         morals and society, his critique of the state in The Wealth of
         Nations, and his theory of human sociability in The Theory of
         Moral Sentiments.")

         Now the anarcho-capitalist essentially turns the minarchist's own
         logic against him, and asks why the remaining functions of the
         state could not be turned over to the free market. And so, the
         anarcho-capitalist imagines that police services could be sold by
         freely competitive firms; that a court system would emerge to
         peacefully arbitrate disputes between firms; and that a sensible
         legal code could be developed through custom, precedent, and
         contract. And in fact, notes the anarcho-capitalist, a great deal
         of modern law (such as the Anglo-American common law) originated
         not in legislatures, but from the decentralized rulings of
         judges. (The anarcho-capitalist shares Kropotkin's interest in
         customary law, but normally believes that it requires extensive
         modernization and articulation.)

         The anarcho-capitalist typically hails modern society's
         increasing reliance on private security guards, gated
         communities, arbitration and mediation, and other demonstrations
         of the free market's ability to supply the defensive and legal
         services normally assumed to be of necessity a government
         monopoly. In his ideal society, these market alternatives to
         government services would take over all legitimate security
         services. One plausible market structure would involve
         individuals subscribing to one of a large number of competing
         police services; these police services would then set up
         contracts or networks for peacefully handling disputes between
         members of each others' agencies. Alternately, police services
         might be "bundled" with housing services, just as landlords often
         bundle water and power with rental housing, and gardening and
         security are today provided to residents in gated communities and
         apartment complexes.

         The underlying idea is that contrary to popular belief, private
         police would have strong incentives to be peaceful and respect
         individual rights. For first of all, failure to peacefully
         arbitrate will yield to jointly destructive warfare, which will
         be bad for profits. Second, firms will want to develop long- term
         business relationships, and hence be willing to negotiate in good
         faith to insure their long-term profitability. And third,
         aggressive firms would be likely to attract only high-risk
         clients and thus suffer from extraordinarily high costs (a
         problem parallel to the well-known "adverse selection problem" in
         e.g. medical insurance -- the problem being that high-risk people
         are especially likely to seek insurance, which drives up the
         price when riskiness is hard for the insurer to discern or if
         regulation requires a uniform price regardless of risk).
         Anarcho-capitalists generally give little credence to the view
         that their "private police agencies" would be equivalent to
         today's Mafia -- the cost advantages of open, legitimate business
         would make "criminal police" uncompetitive. As David Friedman
         explains in The Machinery of Freedom, "Perhaps the best way to
         see why anarcho-capitalism would be so much more peaceful than
         our present system is by analogy. Consider our world as it would
         be if the cost of moving from one country to another were zero.
         Everyone lives in a housetrailer and speaks the same language.
         One day, the president of France announces that because of
         troubles with neighboring countries, new military taxes are being
         levied and conscription will begin shortly. The next morning the
         president of France finds himself ruling a peaceful but empty
         landscape, the population having been reduced to himself, three
         generals, and twenty-seven war correspondents."

         (Moreover, anarcho-capitalists argue, the Mafia can only thrive
         in the artificial market niche created by the prohibition of
         alcohol, drugs, prostitution, gambling, and other victimless
         crimes. Mafia gangs might kill each other over turf, but
         liquor-store owners generally do not.)

         Unlike some left-anarchists, the anarcho-capitalist has no
         objection to punishing criminals; and he finds the former's claim
         that punishment does not deter crime to be the height of naivete.
         Traditional punishment might be meted out after a conviction by a
         neutral arbitrator; or a system of monetary restitution (probably
         in conjunction with a prison factory system) might exist instead.
         A convicted criminal would owe his victim compensation, and would
         be forced to work until he paid off his debt. Overall,
         anarcho-capitalists probably lean more towards the
         restitutionalist rather than the pure retributivist position.

         Probably the main division between the
         anarcho-capitalists stems from the apparent differences
         between Rothbard's natural-law anarchism, and David Friedman's
         more economistic approach. Rothbard puts more emphasis on the
         need for a generally recognized libertarian legal code (which he
         thinks could be developed fairly easily by purification of the
         Anglo-American common law), whereas Friedman focuses more
         intently on the possibility of plural legal systems co-existing
         and responding to the consumer demands of different elements of
         the population. The difference, however, is probably over-stated.
         Rothbard believes that it is legitimate for consumer demand to
         determine the philosophically neutral content of the law, such as
         legal procedure, as well as technical issues of property right
         definition such as water law, mining law, etc. And Friedman
         admits that "focal points" including prevalent norms are likely
         to circumscribe and somewhat standardize the menu of available
         legal codes.

         Critics of anarcho-capitalism sometimes assume that communal or
         worker-owned firms would be penalized or prohibited in an
         anarcho-capitalist society. It would be more accurate to state
         that while individuals would be free to voluntarily form
         communitarian organizations, the anarcho- capitalist simply
         doubts that they would be widespread or prevalent. However, in
         theory an "anarcho-capitalist" society might be filled with
         nothing but communes or worker- owned firms, so long as these
         associations were formed voluntarily (i.e., individuals joined
         voluntarily and capital was obtained with the consent of the
         owners) and individuals retained the right to exit and set up
         corporations or other profit-making, individualistic firms.

         On other issues, the anarcho-capitalist differs little if at all
         from the more moderate libertarian. Services should be privatized
         and opened to free competition; regulation of personal AND
         economic behavior should be done away with. Poverty would be
         handled by work and responsibility for those able to care for
         themselves, and voluntary charity for those who cannot.
         (Libertarians hasten to add that a deregulated economy would
         greatly increase the economic opportunities of the poor, and
         elimination of taxation would lead to a large increase in
         charitable giving.)

         For a detailed discussion of the economics of privatization of
         dispute resolution, rule creation, and enforcement, see my "The
         Economics of Non-State Legal Systems," which is archived with my
         other economics writings.

     11. What criticisms have been made of anarchism?

         Anarchism of various breeds has been criticized from an extremely
         wide range of perspectives. State-socialists, classical liberals,
         and conservatives have each on occasion examined anarchist
         theorists and found them wanting. After considering the unifying
         argument endorsed by virtually all of the critics of anarchism,
         we shall turn to the more specific attacks of Marxist, moderate
         libertarian, and conservative lineage.

           a. "An anarchist society, lacking any central coercive
              authority, would quickly degenerate into violent chaos."

              The most common criticism, shared by the entire
              range of critics, is basically that anarchism would
              swiftly degenerate into a chaotic Hobbesian war of
              all-against-all. Thus the communist Friedrich Engels wonders
              "[H]ow these people propose to run a factory, operate a
              railway or steer a ship without having in the last resort
              one deciding will, without single management, they of course
              do not tell us." He continues: "The authority of the
              majority over the minority also ceases. Every individual and
              every community is autonomous; but as to how society, even
              of only two people, is possible unless each gives up some of
              his autonomy, Bakunin again maintains silence." And
              his autonomy, Bakunin again maintains silence." And
              similarly, the classical liberal Ludwig von Mises
              states that "An anarchistic society would be exposed
              to the mercy of every individual. Society cannot exist if
              the majority is not ready to hinder, by the application or
              threat of violent action, minorities from destroying the
              social order. This power is vested in the state or
              government."

              Or to consider a perhaps less ideological writer,
              Thomas Hobbes implicitly criticizes anarchist theory
              when he explains that "Hereby it is manifest, that during
              the time men live without a common Power to keep them all in
              awe, they are in that condition which is called Warre; and
              such a warre, as is of every man, against every man." Hobbes
              goes on to add that "It may peradventure be thought, there
              was never such a time, nor condition of warre as this; and I
              believe it was never generally so, over all the world: but
              there are many places, where they live so now. For the
              savage people in many places of America, except the
              government of small Families, the concord whereof dependeth
              on naturall lust, have no government at all; and live at
              this day in that brutish manner, as I said before." Since it
              is in the interest of the strong to take what they want from
              the weak, the absence of government lead inexorably to
              widespread violence and the prevention or destruction of
              civilization itself.

              Anarchists of all varieties would reject this argument;
              sometimes claiming that the critic misunderstands their
              position, other times that the critic's assumptions are too
              pessimistic. Kropotkin, for example, would seriously dispute
              the claim that war is the natural state of ungoverned human
              beings; like many other species of animals, cooperation is
              more common, natural, and likely. Left- anarchists generally
              would normally object that these criticisms rest upon
              contingent cultural assumptions arising from a competitive
              scarcity economy. Replace these institutions with humane and
              egalitarian ones; then poverty, the cause of crime and
              aggression, would greatly decrease. Finally, many left-
              anarchists envisage cooperatives and communes adopting and
              enforcing rules of appropriate conduct for those who wish to
              join.

              The anarcho-capitalist would likely protest that the critic
              misunderstands his view: he does believe that police and
              laws are necessary and desirable, and merely holds that they
              could be supplied by the free market rather than government.
              More fundamentally, he doubts the game- theoretic
              underpinnings of Hobbes' argument, for it ignores the
              likelihood that aggressive individuals or firms will provoke
              retaliation. Just as territorial animals fight when
              defending their territory, but yield when confronted on the
              territory of another animal, rational self-interested
              individuals and firms would usually find aggression a
              dangerous and unprofitable practice. In terms of game
              theory, the anarcho-capitalist thinks that Hobbes' situation
              is a Hawk-Dove game rather than a Prisoners' Dilemma. (In
              the Prisoners' Dilemma, war/non-cooperation would be a
              strictly dominant strategy; in a Hawk-Dove game there is
              normally a mixed-strategy equilibrium in which
              cooperation/peace is the norm but a small percentage of
              players continue to play war/non-cooperation.) Self-
              interested police firms would gladly make long-term
              arbitration contracts with each other to avoid mutually
              destructive bloodshed.

              (To view an excellent short related essay on anarchism and
              game theory, click here.)

           b. The Marxist critique of left-anarchism

              One of the most famous attacks on anarchism was
              launched by Karl Marx during his battles with
              Proudhon and Bakunin. The ultimate result of this protracted
              battle of words was to split the 19th-century workers'
              movement into two distinct factions. In the 20th century,
              the war of words ended in blows: while Marxist-Leninists
              sometimes cooperated with anarchists during the early stages
              of the Russian and Spanish revolutions, violent struggle
              between them was the rule rather than the exception.
              between them was the rule rather than the exception.

              There were at least three distinct arguments that
              Marx aimed at his anarchist opponents.

              First: the development of socialism had to follow a
              particular historical course, whereas the anarchists
              mistakenly believed that it could be created by force of
              will alone. "A radical social revolution is connected with
              certain historical conditions of economic development; the
              latter are its presupposition. Therefore it is possible only
              where the industrial proletariat, together with capitalist
              production, occupies at least a substantial place in the
              mass of the people." Marx continues: "He [Bakunin]
              understands absolutely nothing about social revolution ...
              For him economic requisites do not exist...He wants a
              European social revolution, resting on the economic
              foundation of capitalist production, to take place on the
              level of the Russian or Slavic agricultural and pastoral
              peoples ... Will power and not economic conditions is the
              basis for his social revolution." Proudhon, according to
              Marx, suffered from the same ignorance of history and its
              laws: "M. Proudhon, incapable of following the real movement
              of history, produces a phantasmagoria which presumptuously
              claims to be dialectical ... From his point of view man is
              only the instrument of which the idea or the eternal reason
              makes use in order to unfold itself." This particular
              argument is probably of historical interest only, in light
              of the gross inaccuracy of Marx's prediction of the path of
              future civilization; although perhaps the general claim that
              social progression has material presuppositions retains some
              merit.

              Second, Marx ridiculed Bakunin's claim that a socialist
              government would become a new despotism by socialist
              intellectuals. In light of the prophetic accuracy of
              Bakunin's prediction in this area, Marx's reply is almost
              ironic: "Under collective ownership the so-called people's
              will disappears to make way for the real will of the
              cooperative." It is on this point that most left-anarchists
              reasonably claim complete vindication; just as Bakunin
              predicted, the Marxist "dictatorship of the proletariat"
              swiftly became a ruthless "dictatorship over the
              proletariat."

              Finally, Marx stated that the anarchists erroneously
              believed that the government supported the capitalist system
              rather than the other way around. In consequence, they were
              attacking the wrong target and diverting the workers'
              movement from its proper course. Engels delineated the
              Marxist and left-anarchist positions quite well: "Bakunin
              maintains that it is the state which has created capital,
              that the capitalist has his capital only by the grace of the
              state. As, therefore, the state is the chief evil, it is
              above all the state which must be done away with and then
              capitalism will go to blazes of itself. We, on the contrary,
              say: Do away with capital, the concentration of the means of
              production in the hands of the few, and the state will fall
              of itself." The left-anarchist would probably accept this as
              a fair assessment of their disagreement with the Marxists,
              but point out how in many historical cases since (and
              before) Marx's time governments have steered their countries
              towards very different aims and policies, whereas
              capitalists are often fairly adaptive and passive.

           c. The minarchists' attack on anarcho-capitalism

              Probably the earliest minarchist attack on anarcho-
              capitalism may be found in Ayn Rand's essay "The
              Nature of Government." ("Minarchism" designates the advocacy
              of a "minimal" or nightwatchman state, supplying only
              police, courts, a legal system, and national defense.) Her
              critique contained four essential arguments. The first
              essentially repeated Hobbes' view that society without
              government would collapse into violent chaos. The second was
              that anarcho-capitalist police firms would turn to war as
              soon as a dispute broke out between individuals employing
              different protection agencies: "[S]uppose Mr. Smith, a
              customer of Government A, suspects that his next-door
              neighbor, Mr. Jones, a customer of Government B, has robbed
              him; a squad of Police A proceeds to Mr. Jones' house and is
              met at the door by a squad of Police B, who declare that
              they do not recognize the authority of Government A. What
              happens then? You take it from there." Her third argument
              was that anarcho-capitalism was an expression of an
              irrational subjectivist epistemology which would allow each
              person to decide for himself or herself whether the use of
              physical force was justified. Finally, her fourth argument
              was that anarcho-capitalism would lack an objective legal
              code (meaning, presumably, both publicly known and morally
              valid).

              Rand's arguments were answered at length in Roy
              Childs' "Objectivism and the State: An Open Letter
              to Ayn Rand," which tried to convince her that only the
              anarcho-capitalist position was consistent with her view
              that the initiation of force was immoral. In brief, Childs
              argued that like other free-market institutions, private
              police would have economic incentives to perform their tasks
              peacefully and efficiently: police would negotiate
              arbitration agreements in advance precisely to avoid the
              kind of stand-off that Rand feared, and an objective legal
              code could be developed by free-market judges. Childs
              strongly contested Rand's claim that anarcho-capitalism had
              any relation to irrationalism; an individual could be
              rational or irrational in his judgment to use defensive
              violence, just as a government could be rational or
              irrational in its judgment to do so. As Childs queried, "By
              what epistemological criterion is an individual's action
              classified as 'arbitrary,' while that of a group of
              individuals is somehow 'objective'?"

              Robert Nozick launched the other famous attempt to
              refute the anarcho-capitalist on libertarian
              grounds. Basically, Nozick argued that the supply of police
              and legal services was a geographic natural monopoly, and
              that therefore a state would emerge by the "invisible hand"
              processes of the market itself. The details of his argument
              are rather complex: Nozick postulated a right, strongly
              contested by other libertarians, to prohibit activities
              which were exceptionally risky to others; he then added that
              the persons whose actions were so prohibited were entitled
              to compensation. Using these two principles, Nozick claimed
              that the dominant protection agency in a region could
              justifiably prohibit competition on the grounds that it was
              "too risky," and therefore become an "ultra-minimal state."
              But at this point, it would be obligated to compensate
              consumers who were prohibited from purchasing competitors'
              services, so it would do so in kind by giving them access to
              its own police and legal services -- thereby becoming a
              minimal state. And none of these steps, according to Nozick,
              violates libertarian rights.

              There have been literally dozens of anarchist attacks on
              Nozick's derivation of the minimal state. To begin with, no
              state arose in the manner Nozick describes, so all existing
              states are illegitimate and still merit abolition. Secondly,
              anarcho-capitalists dispute Nozick's assumption that defense
              is a natural monopoly, noting that the modern security guard
              and arbitration industries are extremely decentralized and
              competitive. Finally, they reject Nozick's principles of
              risk and compensation, charging that they lead directly to
              the despotism of preventive law.

           d. The conservative critique of anarchism

              The conservative critique of anarchism is much less
              developed, but can be teased out of the writings of
              such authors as Edmund Burke, Russell Kirk, and Ernest van
              den Haag. (Interestingly, Burke scholars are still debating
              whether the early Burke's quasi-anarchistic A Vindication of
              Natural Society was a serious work or a subtle satire.)

              Burke would probably say that, like other radical
              ideologues, the anarchists place far too much reliance on
              their imperfect reason and not enough on the accumulated
              wisdom of tradition. Society functions because we have
              gradually evolved a system of workable rules. It seems
              certain that Burke would apply his critique of the French
              revolutionaries with equal force to the anarchists: "They
              have no respect for the wisdom of others; but they pay it
              off by a very full measure of confidence in their own. With
              them it is a sufficient motive to destroy an old scheme of
              things, because it is an old one. As to the new, they are in
              no sort of fear with regard to the duration of a building
              run up in haste; because duration is no object to those who
              think little or nothing has been done before their time, and
              who place all their hopes in discovery." To attempt to
              replace the wisdom of the ages with a priori theories of
              justice is sure to lead to disaster, because functional
              policies must be judicious compromises between important
              competing ends. Or in Burke's words, "The science of
              constructing a commonwealth, or renovating it, or reforming
              it, is, like every other experimental science, not to be
              taught a priori. Nor is it a short experience that can
              instruct us in that practical science; because the real
              effects of moral causes are not always immediate." The
              probable result of any attempt to realize anarchist
              principles would be a brief period of revolutionary zeal,
              followed by chaos and social breakdown resulting from the
              impracticality of the revolutionary policies, and finally
              ending in a brutal dictator winning widespread support by
              simply restoring order and rebuilding the people's sense of
              social stability.

              Many anarchists would in fact accept Burke's critique of
              violent revolution, which is why they favor advancing their
              views gradually through education and nonviolent protest. In
              fact, Bakunin's analysis of Marxism as the ideology (i.e.,
              rationalization for the class interests of) middle-class
              intellectuals in fact differs little from Burke's analysis:
              Bakunin, like Burke, perceived that no matter how oppressive
              the current system may be, there are always power-hungry
              individuals who favor violent revolution as their most
              practical route to absolute power. Their protests against
              actual injustices must be seen in light of their ultimate
              aim of imposing even more ruthless despotism upon the
              people.

              On other issues, anarchists would disagree strongly with
              several of Burke's claims. Many forms of misery stem from
              the blind adherence to tradition; and rational thinking has
              sparked countless improvements in human society ever since
              the decline of traditional despotism. Moreover, anarchists
              do not propose to do away with valuable traditions, but
              simply request evidence that particular traditions are
              valuable before they lend them their support. And what is to
              be done when -- as is usually the case -- a society harbors
              a wide range of mutually incompatible traditions?

              Anarchists might also object that the Burkean analysis
              relies too heavily upon tradition as a result rather than a
              process. Cultural evolution may constantly weed out foolish
              ideas and practices, but it hardly follows that such follies
              have already perished; for the state to defend tradition is
              to strangle the competitive process which tends to make
              tradition sensible. As Vincent Cook explains: "[I]t is
              precisely because wisdom has to be accumulated in
              incremental steps that it cannot be centrally planned by any
              single political or religious authority, contrary to the
              aspirations of conservatives and collectivists alike. While
              the collectivists are indeed guilty of trying to
              rationalistically reconstruct society in defiance of
              tradition (a valid criticism of left-anarchists),
              conservatives on the other hand are guilty of trying to
              freeze old traditions in place. Conservatives have forgotten
              that the process of wisdom accumulation is an on-going one,
              and instead have opted for the notion that some existing
              body of traditions (usually Judeo-Christian) already
              represent social perfection."

              Russell Kirk, noted Burke scholar, has written a
              brief critique of the modern libertarian movement.
              (Another conservative, Ernest van den Haag, wrote a
              lengthier essay with a similar theme and perspective.) In
              all likelihood, Kirk would apply many (but not all) of the
              same arguments to left-anarchists.

              Kirk faults the libertarians (and when he discusses
              "libertarians" he usually seems to have the anarcho-
              capitalists in mind) on at least six counts. First, they
              deny the existence of a "transcendent moral order." Second,
              order is prior to liberty, and liberty is possible only
              after government establishes a constitutional order. Third,
              libertarians assume that self-interest is the only possible
              social bond, ignoring the broader communitarian vision of
              human nature found in both the Aristotelian and Judeo-
              Christian traditions. Fourth, libertarians erroneously
              assume that human beings are naturally good or at least
              perfectible. Fifth, the libertarian foolishly attacks the
              state as such, rather than merely its abuses. Sixth and
              last, the libertarian is an arrogant egoist who disregards
              valuable ancient beliefs and customs.

              Left-anarchists would perhaps agree with Kirk on points
              three and six. So if Kirk were to expand his attack on
              anarchism to encompass the left-anarchists as well, he might
              acquit them of these two charges. The remaining four,
              however, Kirk would probably apply equally to anarchists of
              both varieties.

              How would anarchists reply to Kirk's criticisms? On the
              "moral transcendence" issue, they would point out there have
              been religious as well as non-religious anarchists; and
              moreover, many non-religious anarchists still embrace moral
              objectivism (notably anarchists in the broader natural law
              tradition). Most anarchists would deny that they make self-
              interest the only possible social bond; and even those who
              would affirm this (such as anarcho-capitalists influenced by
              Ayn Rand) have a broad conception of self-interest
              consistent with the Aristotelian tradition.

              As to the priority of order over liberty, many anarchists
              influenced by e.g. Kropotkin would reply that as with other
              animal species, order and cooperation emerge as a result,
              not a consequence of freedom; while anarcho- capitalists
              would probably refer Kirk to the theorists of "spontaneous
              order" such as Hayek, Hume, Smith, and even Edmund Burke
              himself.

              The FAQ addresses the questions of human perfectibility and
              utopianism in sections 20 and 21. As for Kirk's final point,
              most anarchists would reply that they happily accept
              valuable customs and traditions, but believe that they have
              shown that some ancient practices and institutions -- above
              all, the state --have no value whatever.

           e. "We are already in a state of anarchy."

              Under anarchy, it is conceivable that e.g. a brutal gang
              might use its superior might to coerce everyone else to do
              as they wish. With nothing more powerful than the gang,
              there would (definitionally) be nothing to stop them. But
              how does this differ from what we have now? Governments rule
              because they have the might to maintain their power; in
              short, because there is no superior agency to restrain them.
              Hence, reason some critics of anarchism, the goal of
              anarchists is futile because we are already in a state of
              anarchy.

              This argument is confused on several levels.

              First, it covertly defines anarchy as unrestrained rule of
              the strongest, which is hardly what most anarchists have in
              mind. (Moreover, it overlooks the definitional differences
              between government and other forms of organized aggression;
              Weber in particular noted that governments claim a monopoly
              over the legitimate use of force in a given geographical
              region.) In fact, while anarchism is logically compatible
              with any viewpoint which rejects the existence of the state,
              there have been extremely few (perhaps no) anarchists who
              combined their advocacy of anarchism with support for
              domination by those most skilled in violence.

              Second, it seems to assume that all that particular
              anarchists advocate is the abolition of the state; but as we
              have seen, anarchism is normally combined with additional
              normative views about what ought to replace the state. Thus,
              most anarchist theorists believe more than merely that the
              state should not exist; they also believe that e.g. society
              should be based upon voluntary communes, or upon strict
              private property rights, etc.

              Third, the argument sometimes confuses a definitional with a
              causal claim. It is one thing to argue that anarchy would
              lead to the rule by the strongest; this is a causal claim
              about the likely results of the attempt to create an
              anarchist society. It is another thing entirely to argue
              that anarchy means rule by the strongest. This is simply a
              linguistic confusion, best illustrated by noting that under
              this definition anarchy and the state are logically
              compatible.

              A related but more sophisticated argument, generally leveled
              against anarcho- capitalists, runs as follows. If competing
              protection agencies could prevent the establishment of an
              abusive, dominant firm, while don't they do so now? In
              short, if market checks against the abuse of power actually
              worked, we wouldn't have a state in the first place.

              There are two basic replies to this argument. First of all,
              it completely ignores the ideological factor. Anarcho-
              capitalists are thinking of how competing firms would
              prevent the rise of abusive protection monopolists in a
              society where most people don't support the existence of
              such a monopolist. It is one thing to suppress a "criminal
              firm" when it stands condemned by public opinion and the
              values internalized by that firm's employees; it is another
              thing entirely to suppress our current "criminal firms"
              (i.e., governments) when qua institution enjoy the
              overwhelming support of the populace and the state's
              enforcers believe in their own cause. When a governing class
              loses confidence in its own legitimacy -- from the Ancien
              Regime in France to the Communist Party in the USSR -- it
              becomes vulnerable and weak. Market checks on government
              could indeed establish an anarchist society if the
              self-confidence of the governing class were severely eroded
              by anarchist ideas.

              Secondly, the critique ignores the possibility of multiple
              social equilibria. If everyone drives on the right side of
              the road, isolated attempts to switch to the left side will
              be dangerous and probably unsuccessful. But if everyone
              drives on the left side of the road, the same danger exists
              for those who believe that the right side is superior and
              plan to act on their believe. Similarly, it is quite
              possible that given that a government exists, the existence
              of government is a stable equilibrium; but if a system of
              competitive protection firms existed, that too would be a
              stable equilibrium. In short, just because one equilibrium
              exists and is stable doesn't mean that it is the only
              possible equilibrium. Why then is the state so pervasive if
              it is just one possible equilibrium? The superiority of this
              equilibrium is one possible explanation; but it could also
              be due to ideology, or an inheritance from our barbarous
              ancestors.

     12. What other anarchist viewpoints are there?

         There is definitely another strand of anarchist thought,
         although it is far vaguer and less propositional than the
         views thus far explicated. For some, "anarchist" is just a
         declaration of rebellion against rules and authority of any kind.
         There is little attempt made here to explain how society would
         work without government; and perhaps there is little conviction
         that it could do so. This sort of anarchism is more of an
         attitude or emotion -- a feeling that the corrupt world of today
         should go down in flames, without any definite view about what if
         anything would be preferable and possible. For want of a better
         term, I would call this "emotivist anarchism," whose most
         prominent exponent is almost certainly Max Stirner (although to
         be fair to Stirner he did briefly outline his vision for the
         replacement of existing society by a "Union of Egoists").

         For the emotivist anarchist, opposition to the state is just a
         special case of his or her opposition to almost everything: the
         family, traditional art, bourgeois culture, comfortable
         middle-aged people, the British monarchy, etc. This position,
         when articulated, is often difficult to understand, for it seems
         to seek destruction without any suggestion or argument that
         anything else would be preferable. Closely linked to emotivist
         anarchism, though sometimes a little more theoretical, is
         nihilist anarchism. The anarcho-nihilists combine the emotivist's
         opposition to virtually all forms of order with radical
         subjectivist moral and epistemological theory.

         To see Tracy Harms' criticism of my treatment of Stirner, egoism,
         and nihilism, click here.

         Related to emotivist anarchism is a second strand of less
         intellectual, more emotional anarchist thought. It has been
         called by some "moral anarchism." This view again feels that
         existing statist society is bad; but rather than lay out any
         comprehensive plans for its abolition, this sort of anarchist
         sticks to more immediate reforms. Anarchism of this sort is a
         kind of ideal dream, which is beautiful and inspiring to
         contemplate while we pursue more concrete aims.

         The emotivist anarchist often focuses on action and disdains
         theorizing. In contrast, another breed of anarchists, known as
         "philosophical anarchists," see few practical implications of
         their intellectual position. Best represented by Robert Paul
         Wolff, philosophical anarchism simply denies that the state's
         orders as such can confer any legitimacy whatever. Each
         individual must exercise his moral autonomy to judge right and
         wrong for himself, irrespective of the state's decrees. However,
         insofar as the state's decrees accord with one's private
         conscience, there is no need to change one's behavior. A position
         like Wolff's says, in essence, that the rational person cannot
         and must not offer the blind obedience to authority that
         governments often seem to demand; but this insight need not spark
         any political action if one's government's decrees are not
         unusually immoral.

         Yet another faction, strongly influenced by Leo Tolstoy, refer to
         themselves as "Christian anarchists." (Tolstoy avoided the term
         "anarchist," probably because of its association with violence
         and terrorism in the minds of contemporary Russians.) Drawing on
         the Gospels' themes of nonviolence and the equality of all human
         beings, these anarchists condemn government as contrary to
         Christian teaching. Tolstoy particularly emphasized the
         immorality of war, military service, and patriotism, challenging
         Christians to live up to the radical implications of their faith
         by withdrawing their support from all three of these evils.
         Tolstoy's essay "Patriotism, or Peace?" is particularly notable
         for its early attack upon nationalism and the bloodshed that
         usually accompanies it.

         Finally, many leftist and progressive movements have an anarchist
         interpretation and anarchist advocates. For example, a faction of
         feminists, calling themselves "anarcha- feminists" exists. The
         feminists, calling themselves "anarcha- feminists" exists. The
         Green and environmentalist movements also have strong
         anarchist wings which blend opposition to the state and
         defense of the environment. Their primary theoretician is
         probably Murray Bookchin, who (lately) advocates a society of
         small and fairly autarchic localities. As Bookchin explains, "the
         anarchist concepts of a balanced community, a face-to-face
         democracy, a humanistic technology and a decentralized society --
         these rich libertarian concepts -- are not only desirable, they
         are also necessary." Institutions such as the town meeting of
         classical democratic theory point the way to a radical
         reorganization of society, in which small environmentally
         concerned townships regularly meet to discuss and vote upon their
         communities' production and broader aims. Doubtlessly there are
         many other fusions between anarchism and progressive causes, and
         more spring up as new concerns develop.

     13. What moral justifications have been offered for anarchism?

         Again, there are a great many answers which have been offered.
         Some anarchists, such as the emotivist and (paradoxically) the
         moral anarchists have little interest in high-level moral theory.
         But this has been of great interest to the more intellectual
         sorts of anarchists.

         One popular argument for anarchism is that it is the only way for
         true socialism to exist. State-socialism is unable to actually
         establish human equality; instead it simply creating a new ruling
         class. Bakunin prophetically predicted the results of socialists
         seizing control of the state when he wrote that the socialist
         elite would form a "new class" which would be "the most
         aristocratic, despotic, arrogant, and contemptuous of all
         regimes." Elsewhere Bakunin wrote that "[F]reedom without
         Socialism is privilege and injustice, ... Socialism without
         freedom is slavery and brutality." Of course, socialism itself
         has been defended on both deontological and utilitarian grounds,
         and there is no need to repeat these here.

         On the other hand, anarcho-capitalists have argued that only
         under anarchism can the Lockean rights to person and property so
         loudly championed by more moderate libertarians be fully
         respected. Any attempt to impose a monopolistic government
         necessarily prevents competing police and judicial services from
         providing a legitimate service; moreover, so long as government
         exists taxation will persist. The government's claim to defend
         private property is thus quite ironic, for the state, in
         Rothbard's words, is "an institution that presumes to 'defend'
         person and property by itself subsisting on the unilateral
         coercion against private property known as taxation." Other
         anarcho- capitalists such as David Friedman find these arguments
         from natural Lockean rights unconvincing, and instead take up the
         task of trying to show that Adam Smith's utilitarian case for
         free-market capitalism applies just as well to free markets in
         defense services, making the state useless as well as dangerous.

         Still other anarchists, such as Lysander Spooner and Benjamin
         Tucker as well as Proudhon, have argued that anarchism would
         abolish the exploitation inherent in interest and rent simply by
         means of free competition. In their view, only labor income is
         legitimate, and an important piece of the case for anarchism is
         that without government-imposed monopolies, non-labor income
         would be driven to zero by market forces. It is unclear, however,
         if they regard this as merely a desirable side effect, or if they
         would reject anarchism if they learned that the predicted
         economic effect thereof would not actually occur. (Other
         individualist anarchists have argued that contrary to Spooner and
         Tucker, free banking would lead to a much lower rate of inflation
         than we experience today; that rent and interest are not due to
         "monopoly" but to scarcity of land and loanable funds; and that
         there is no moral distinction between labor and rental or
         interest income, all of which depend upon a mixture of scarcity,
         demand, luck, and effort.)

         A basic moral intuition that probably anarchists of all varieties
         share is simply that no one has the right to rule another person.
         The interpretation of "rulership," however, varies: left
         anarchists tend to see the employer-employee relationship as one
         of rulership, and anarcho-capitalists are often dubious of the
         claim that envisaged anarchists communes would be democratic and
         hence voluntary. A closely related moral intuition, again widely
         shared by all sorts of anarchists, is that each person should
         exercise personal autonomy, or self-rule. One should question
         authority, and make up one's mind for oneself rather than simply
         following the herd. Again, the interpretation of "personal
         autonomy" varies: the left-anarchist sees the employer-employee
         relationship as inherently violating personal autonomy, whereas
         the anarcho-capitalist is more likely to see personal autonomy
         disappearing in the commune or collective, regardless of how
         democratically they run themselves.

     14. What are the major debates between anarchists? What are the
         recurring arguments?

         Without a doubt, the most repeated debate among modern anarchists
         is fought between the left-anarchists on one side and the
         anarcho-capitalists on the other. Of course, there are occasional
         debates between different left-anarchist factions, but probably
         most of them would be content with an anarchist society populated
         by some mixture of communes, worker-controlled firms, and
         cooperatives. And similarly there are a few internal debates
         between anarcho- capitalists, notably the tension between
         Rothbard's natural law anarcho-capitalism and David Friedman's
         more economistic anarcho-capitalism. But it is the debate between
         the left-anarchists and the anarcho-capitalists which is the most
         fundamental and the most acrimonious. There are many sub-debates
         within this wider genre, which we will now consider.

           a. "X is not 'true anarchism.'"

              One of the least fruitful of these sub-debates is the
              frequent attempt of one side to define the other out of
              existence ("You are not truly an anarchist, for anarchists
              must favor [abolition of private property, atheism,
              Christianity, etc.]") In addition to being a trivial issue,
              the factual supporting arguments are often incorrect. For
              example, despite a popular claim that socialism and
              anarchism have been inextricably linked since the inception
              of the anarchist movement, many 19th-century anarchists, not
              only Americans such as Tucker and Spooner, but even
              Europeans like Proudhon, were ardently in favor of private
              property (merely believing that some existing sorts of
              property were illegitimate, without opposing private
              property as such).

              As Benjamin Tucker wrote in 1887, "It will probably
              surprise many who know nothing of Proudhon save his
              declaration that 'property is robbery' to learn that he was
              perhaps the most vigorous hater of Communism that ever lived
              on this planet. But the apparent inconsistency vanishes when
              you read his book and find that by property he means simply
              legally privileged wealth or the power of usury, and not at
              all the possession by the laborer of his products."

              Nor did an ardent anarcho-communist like Kropotkin deny
              Proudhon or even Tucker the title of "anarchist." In his
              Modern Science and Anarchism, Kropotkin discusses not only
              Proudhon but "the American anarchist individualists who were
              represented in the fifties by S.P. Andrews and W. Greene,
              later on by Lysander Spooner, and now are represented by
              Benjamin Tucker, the well-known editor of the New York
              Liberty." Similarly in his article on anarchism for the 1910
              edition of the Encyclopedia Britannica, Kropotkin again
              freely mentions the American individualist anarchists,
              including "Benjamin Tucker, whose journal Liberty was
              started in 1881 and whose conceptions are a combination of
              those of Proudhon with those of Herbert Spencer."

           b. "Anarchism of variant X is unstable and will lead to the
              re-emergence of the state."

              A more substantive variation is to argue that the opposing
              anarchism would be unstable and lead to the swift re-
              emergence of government. Thus, the left-anarchists often
              argue that the defense corporations envisaged by anarcho-
              capitalists would war with one another until one came out as
              the new government; or else they would collude to establish
              themselves as the new capitalist oligarchs. As Noam Chomsky
              says in an interview with Ulrike Heider, "The predatory
              forces of the market would destroy society, would destroy
              community, and destroy the workforce. Nothing would be left
              except people hating each other and fighting each other."
              Anarcho-capitalists reply that this grossly underestimates
              the degree of competition likely to prevail in the defense
              industry; that war is likely to be very unprofitable and
              dangerous, and is more likely to be provoked by ideology
              than sober profit-maximization; and that economic theory and
              economic history show that collusion is quite difficult to
              maintain.

              Anarcho-capitalists for their part accuse the
              left-anarchists of intending to impose their communal vision
              upon everyone; since everyone will not go along voluntarily,
              a government will be needed to impose it. Lest we think that
              this argument is a recent invention, it is interesting to
              find that essentially this argument raged in the 19th-
              century anarchist movement as well. In John MacKay's The
              Anarchists, we see the essential dialogue between
              individualist and collectivist anarchism has a longer
              history than one might think:

                   "Would you, in the system of society which you
                   call 'free Communism' prevent individuals from
                   exchanging their labor among themselves by means
                   of their own medium of exchange? And further:
                   Would you prevent them from occupying land for the
                   purpose of personal use?"... [The] question was
                   not to be escaped. If he answered "Yes!" he
                   admitted that society had the right of control
                   over the individual and threw overboard the
                   autonomy of the individual which he had always
                   zealously defended; if on the other hand he
                   answered "No!" he admitted the right of private
                   property which he had just denied so emphatically
                   ... Then he answered "In Anarchy any number of men
                   must have the right of forming a voluntary
                   association, and so realizing their ideas in
                   practice. Nor can I understand how any one could
                   justly be driven from the land and house which he
                   uses and occupies ... [E]very serious man must
                   declare himself: for Socialism, and thereby for
                   force and against liberty, or for Anarchism, and
                   thereby for liberty and against force."

              There have been several left-anarchist replies. One is to
              readily agree that dissenters would have the right to not
              join a commune, with the proviso that they must not employ
              others or otherwise exploit them. Another is to claim that
              anarchism will change (or cease to warp) human attitudes so
              that they will be more communitarian and less
              individualistic. Finally, some argue that this is simply
              another sophistical argument for giving the rich and
              powerful the liberty to take away the liberty of everyone
              else.

           c. "In an anarchist society in which both systems X and Y
              existed, X would inevitably outcompete Y."

              Again, this argument has been made from several
              perspectives. Left-anarchists have argued that if workers
              had the genuine option to work for a capitalist employer, or
              else work for themselves in a worker cooperative, virtually
              all workers would choose the latter. Moreover, workers in a
              worker-managed firm would have higher morale and greater
              incentive to work hard compared with workers who just worked
              for the benefit of their employer. Hence, capitalists would
              be unable to pay their workers wages competitive with the
              wages of the labor-managed firm, and by force of competition
              would gradually vanish.

              Anarcho-capitalists find that the argument works in
              precisely the opposite direction. For what is a worker-owned
              firm if not a firm in which the workers jointly hold all of
              the stock? Now this is a peculiarly irrational portfolio to
              hold, because it means that workers would, in effect, put
              all their eggs in one basket; if their firm does well, they
              grow rich, but if their firm goes bankrupt, they lose
              everything. It would make much more sense for workers to
              exchange their shares in their own firm to buy shares in
              other firms in order to insure themselves against risk.
              Thus, the probable result of worker-owned firms with
              negotiable shares would be that workers would readily and
              advantageously sell off most of their shares in their own
              firm in order to diversify their portfolios. The end result
              is likely to be the standard form of capitalist
              organization, in which workers receive a fixed payment for
              their services and the owners of the firms' shares earn the
              variable profits. Of course, alienation of shares could be
              banned, but this appears to do nothing except force workers
              to live with enormous financial risk. None of this shows
              that worker-owned firms could not persist if the workers
              were so ideologically committed to worker control that their
              greater productivity outweighed the riskiness of the
              workers' situation; but anarcho-capitalists doubt very much
              that such intense ideology would prevail in more than a
              small portion of the population. Indeed, they expect that
              the egalitarian norms and security from dismissal that
              left-anarchists typically favor would grossly undermine
              everyone's incentive to work hard and kill abler workers'
              desire for advancement.

              Some anarcho-capitalists go further and argue that
              inequality would swiftly re-emerge in an anarcho-syndicalist
              economy. Workers would treat their jobs as a sort of
              property right, and would refuse to hire new workers on
              equal terms because doing so would dilute the current
              workers' shares in the firm's profits. The probable result
              would be that an elite class of workers in capital-intensive
              firms would exploit new entrants into the work force much as
              capitalists allegedly do today. As evidence, they point to
              existing "worker-controlled" firms such as law firms --
              normally they consist of two tiers of workers, one of which
              both works and owns the firm ("the partners"), while the
              remainder are simply employees ("the associates" as well as
              the secretaries, clerks, etc.)

           d. "Anarchism of type X would be worse than the state."

              To the left-anarchist, the society envisaged by the anarcho-
              capitalists often seems far worse than what we have now. For
              it is precisely to the inequality, exploitation, and tyranny
              of modern capitalism that they object, and rather than
              abolishing it the anarcho-capitalist proposes to unleash its
              worst features and destroy its safety net. Noam Chomsky, for
              instance, has suggested that anarcho-capitalists focus
              incorrectly on state domination, failing to recognize the
              underlying principle of opposition to all domination,
              including the employer-employee relationship. Overall, since
              anarcho-capitalism relies heavily on laissez-faire economic
              theory, and since left-anarchists see no validity to
              laissez-faire economic theory, it seems to the latter that
              anarcho-capitalism would be a practical disaster. Left-
              anarchists often equate anarcho-capitalism with social
              Darwinism and even fascism, arguing that the cruel idea of
              "survival of the fittest" underlies them all.

              The anarcho-capitalist, in turn, often suspects that the
              left- anarchist's world would be worse than the world of
              today. Under anarcho-capitalism, individuals would still
              have every right to voluntarily pool their property to form
              communes, worker-controlled firms, and cooperatives; they
              would simply be unable to force dissenters to join them.
              Since this fact rarely impresses the left-anarchist, the
              anarcho-capitalist often concludes that the left-anarchist
              will not be satisfied with freedom for his preferred
              lifestyle; he wants to force his communal lifestyle on
              everyone. Not only would this be a gross denial of human
              freedom, but it would (according to the anarcho-capitalist)
              be likely to have disastrous effects on economic incentives,
              and swiftly lead humanity into miserable poverty. The
              anarcho-capitalist is also frequently disturbed by the
              opposition to all order sometimes voiced by left-anarchists;
              for he feels that only coerced order is bad and welcomes the
              promotion of an orderly society by voluntary means.
              Similarly, the left-anarchists' occasional short time
              horizon, emphasis on immediate satisfaction, and low regard
              for work (which can be seen in a number of authors strongly
              influenced by emotivist anarchism) frighten the
              anarcho-capitalist considerably.

           e. Etc.

              A large number of arguments that go back and forth basically
              duplicate the standard socialist vs. capitalist debate. The
              need or lack thereof for incentives, security, equality,
              regulation, protection of the environment, and so on are
              debated extensively on other sources on the Net, and there
              are several FAQs which discuss these issues from a variety
              of viewpoints. FAQs on the broader libertarian movement are
              frequently posted on alt.individualism,
              alt.politics.libertarian, and talk.politics.libertarian.
              FAQs on socialism similarly appear from time to time on
              alt.politics.radical-left and alt.fan.noam-chomsky. Related
              FAQs sometimes appear on talk.politics.theory. Hence, we
              will spend no further space on these broader issues which
              are amply addressed elsewhere.

     15. How would anarchists handle the "public goods" problem?

         Modern neoclassical (or "mainstream") economists -- especially
         those associated with theoretical welfare economics -- have
         several important arguments for the necessity or desirability of
         government. Out of all of these, the so-called "public goods"
         problem is surely the most frequently voiced. In fact, many
         academics consider it a rigorous justification for the existence
         and limits of the state. Anarcho-capitalists are often very
         familiar with this line of thought and spend considerable time
         trying to refute it; left- anarchists are generally less
         interested, but it is still useful to see how the left-anarchist
         might respond.

         We will begin by explaining the concept of Pareto
         optimality, show how the Pareto criterion is used to
         justify state action, and then examine how anarchists might
         object to the underlying assumptions of these economic
         justifications for the state. After exploring the general
         critique, we will turn to the problem of public goods (and the
         closely related externalities issue). After showing how many
         economists believe that these problems necessitate government
         action, we will consider how left-anarchists and
         anarcho-capitalists might reply.

           a. The concept and uses of Pareto optimality in economics

              The most widely-used concept in theoretical welfare
              economics is "Pareto optimality" (also known as "Pareto
              efficiency"). An allocation is Pareto-optimal iff it is
              impossible to make at least one person better off without
              making anyone else worse off; a Pareto improvement is a
              change in an allocation which makes someone better off
              without making anyone else worse off. As Hal Varian's
              Microeconomic Analysis explains, "[A] Pareto efficient
              allocation is one for which each agent is as well off as
              possible, given the utilities of the other agents." "Better"
              and "worse" are based purely upon subjective preferences
              which can be summarized in a "utility function," or ordinal
              numerical index of preference satisfaction.

              While initially it might seem that every situation is
              necessarily Pareto optimal, this is not the case. True, if
              the only good is food, and each agent wants as much food as
              possible, then every distribution is Pareto optimal. But if
              half of the agents own food and the other half own clothes,
              the distribution will not necessarily be Pareto optimal,
              since each agent might prefer either more food and fewer
              clothes or vice versa.

              Normally, economists would expect agents to voluntarily
              trade in any situation which is not Pareto optimal; but
              neoclassical theorists have considered a number of
              situations in which trade would be a difficult route to
              Pareto optimality. For example, suppose that each agent is
              so afraid of the other that they avoid each other, even
              though they could both benefit from interaction. What they
              need is an independent and powerful organization to e.g.
              protect both agents from each other so that they can reach a
              Pareto-optimal allocation. What they need, in short, is the
              state. While economists' examples are usually more
              elaborate, the basic intuition is that government is
              necessary to satisfy the seemingly uncontroversial principle
              of Pareto optimality.

              Anarchists of all sorts would immediately object that the
              very existence of deontological anarchists shows that Pareto
              optimality can never justify state action. If even the
              slightest increase in the level of state activity
              incompensably harms the deontological anarchist, then
              obviously it is never true that state action can make some
              people better off without making any others worse off.
              Moreover, virtually all government action makes some people
              better off and other people worse off, so plainly the
              pursuit of Pareto improvements has little to do with what
              real governments do.

              Due to these difficulties, in practice economists
              must base their judgments upon the far more
              controversial judgments of cost-benefit analysis. (In the
              works of Richard Posner, this economistic cost-benefit
              approach to policy decisions is called
              "wealth-maximization"; a common synonym is "Kaldor-Hicks
              efficiency.") With cost-benefit analysis, there is no
              pretense made that government policy enjoys unanimous
              approval. Thus, it is open to the many objections frequently
              made to e.g. utilitarianism; moreover, since cost-benefit
              analysis is based upon agents' willingness to pay, rather
              than on agents' utility, it runs into even more moral
              paradoxes than utilitarianism typically does.

              In the final analysis, welfare economists' attempt to
              provide a value-free or at least value-minimal justification
              of the state fails quite badly. Nevertheless, economic
              analysis may still inform more substantive moral theories:
              Pareto optimality, for example, is a necessary but not
              sufficient condition for a utilitarian justification of the
              state.

           b. The public goods problem

              The "public goods" argument is certainly the most popular
              economic argument for the state. It allegedly shows that the
              existence of government can be Pareto optimal, and that the
              non-existence of the state cannot be Pareto optimal; or at
              least, it shows that the existence of government is
              justifiable on cost-benefit grounds. Supposedly, there exist
              important services, such as national defense, which benefit
              people whether they pay for them or not. The result is that
              selfish agents refuse to contribute, leading to disaster.
              The only way to solve this problem is to coerce the
              beneficiaries to raise the funds to supply the needed good.
              In order for this coercion to work, it needs to be
              monopolized by a single agency, the state.

              Public goods arguments have been made not only for national
              defense, but for police, roads, education, R&D, scientific
              research, and many other goods and services. The essential
              definitional feature of public goods is "non-
              excludability"; because the benefits cannot be limited to
              contributors, there is no incentive to contribute. (A second
              definitional characteristic often attributed to public goods
              is "non-rivalrousness"; my own view is that this second
              attribute just confuses the issue, since without the non-
              excludability problem, non-rivalrousness would merely be
              another instance of the ubiquitous practice of pricing above
              marginal cost.)

              The concept of externalities is very closely connected to
              the concept of public goods; the main difference is that
              economists usually think of externalities as being both
              "positive" (e.g. R&D spill-overs) and "negative" (e.g.
              pollution), whereas they usually don't discuss "public
              bads." In any case, again we have the problem that agents
              perform actions which harm or benefit other people, and the
              harm/benefit is "non-excludable." Victims of negative
              externalities can't feasibly charge polluters a fee for
              suffering, and beneficiaries of positive externalities can't
              feasibly be charged for their enjoyment. Government is
              supposed to be necessary to correct this inefficiency. (As
              usual, it is the inefficiency rather than the injustice that
              economists focus upon.)

              Left-anarchists and anarcho-capitalists would probably have
              remarkably similar replies to this argument, although
              doubtlessly the tone and emphasis would vary.

              Objection #1: The behavorial assumptions of public goods
              theory are false.

              It is simply not true that people always act in their narrow
              self-interest. Charity exists, and there is no reason to
              think that the charitable impulse might not be cultivated to
              handle public goods problems voluntarily on an adequate
              basis. Nor need charity as such be the only motive: in
              Social Contract, Free Ride, Anthony de Jasay lays out an
              "ethics turnpike" of possible voluntary solutions to serious
              public goods problems, moving from motivation from high
              moral principles, to "tribal" motivations, to economic
              motivations. As de Jasay writes, "On the map of the Ethics
              Turnpike ... three main segments are marked off according to
              the basic type of person most likely to find his congenial
              exit along it. The first segment is primarily for the type
              who fears God or acts as if he did. The second segment has
              exits to suit those who are not indifferent to how some or
              all their fellow men are faring, and who value only that
              (but not all that) which people want for themselves or for
              others. The third is for homo oeconomicus, maximizing a
              narrowly defined utility that varies only with the money's
              worth of his own payoffs."

              In short, much of the public goods problem is an artificial
              creation of economists' unrealistic assumptions about human
              nature. Anarchists would surely disagree among themselves
              about human nature, but almost all would agree that there is
              more to the human character than Hobbesian self-interest.
              Some people may be amoral, but most are not. Moreover,
              charitable impulses can even give incentives to uncharitable
              people to behave fairly. If the public boycotts products of
              polluters, the polluters may find that it is cheaper to
              clean up their act than lose the public's business.

              Interestingly, many economists have experimentally tested
              the predictions of public goods theory. (Typically, these
              experiments involve groups of human subjects playing for
              real money.) The almost universal result is that the central
              prediction of public goods theory (i.e., that no one will
              voluntarily contribute to the production of a public good)
              is totally false. While the level of contributions rarely
              equals the Pareto-optimal level, it never even approaches
              the zero- provision level that public goods theory predicts.
              Summarizing the experimental literature, Douglas Davis and
              Charles Holt write "[S]ubjects rather persistently
              contributed 40 to 60 percent of their token endowments to
              the group exchange, far in excess of the 0 percent
              contributions rate..." Subsequent experiments examined the
              conditions under which voluntary provision is most
              successful; see Davis and Holt's Experimental Economics for
              details.

              Objection #2: Government is not the only possible way to
              provide public goods.

              Even if individuals act in their narrow self-interest, it is
              not true that government is the only way to manage public
              goods and externalities problems. Why couldn't a left-
              anarchist commune or an anarcho-capitalist police firm do
              the job that the neoclassical economist assumes must be
              delegated to the government? The left-anarchist would
              probably be particularly insistent on this point, since most
              economists usually assume that government and the market are
              the only ways to do things. But thriving, voluntary
              communities might build roads, regulate pollution, and take
              over other important tasks now handled by government.

              Anarcho-capitalists, for their part, would happily agree:
              while they usually look to the market as a first solution,
              they appreciate other kinds of voluntary organizations too:
              fraternal societies, clubs, family, etc. But
              anarcho-capitalists would probably note that left-anarchists
              overlook the ways that the market might take over government
              services -- indeed, malls and gated communities show how
              roads, security, and externalities can be handled by
              contract rather than coercion.

              Objection #3: Public goods are rarer than you might think.

              Anarcho-capitalists would emphasize that a large number of
              alleged "public goods" and "externalities" could easily be
              handled privately by for-profit business if only the
              government would allow the definition of private property
              rights. If ranchers over-graze the commons, why not
              privatize the commons? If fishermen over-fish the oceans,
              why not parcel out large strips of the ocean by longitude
              and latitude to for profit-making aquaculture? And why is
              education supposed to create externalities any more than any
              other sort of investment? Similarly, many sorts of
              externalities are now handled with private property rights.
              Tort law, for example, can give people an incentive to take
              the lives and property of others into account when they take
              risks.

              Objection #4: Externalities are a result of the
              profit-oriented mentality which would be tamed in an
              anarchist society.

              Left-anarchists would emphasize that many externalities are
              caused by the profit-seeking system which the state
              supports. Firms pollute because it is cheaper than producing
              cleanly; but anarcho-syndicalist firms could pursue many
              aims besides profit. In a way, the state- capitalist system
              creates the problem of externalities by basing all decisions
              upon profit, and then claims that we need the state to
              protect us from the very results of this profit-oriented
              decision-making process.

              While few left-anarchists are familiar with the experimental
              economics literature, it offers some support for this
              general approach. In particular, many experiments have shown
              that subjects' concern for fairness weakens many of the
              harsh predictions of standard economic analysis of
              externalities and bargaining.

              Objection #5: The public goods problem is unavoidable.

              Perhaps most fundamentally: government is not a
              solution to the public goods problem, but rather the
              primary instance of the problem. If you create a government
              to solve your public goods problems, you merely create a new
              public goods problem: the public good of restraining and
              checking the government from abusing its power. "[I]t is
              wholly owing to the constitution of the people, and not to
              the constitution of the government, that the crown is not as
              oppressive in England as in Turkey," wrote Thomas Paine; but
              what material incentive is there for individuals to help
              develop a vigilant national character? After all, surely it
              is a rare individual who appreciably affects the national
              culture during his or her lifetime.

              To rely upon democracy as a counter-balance simply assumes
              away the public goods problem. After all, intelligent,
              informed voting is a public good; everyone benefits if the
              electorate reaches wise political judgments, but there is no
              personal, material incentive to "invest" in political
              information, since the same result will (almost certainly)
              happen whether you inform yourself or not. It should be no
              surprise that people know vastly more about their jobs than
              about their government. Many economists seem to be aware of
              this difficulty; in particular, public choice theory in
              economics emphasizes the externalities inherent in
              government action. But a double standard persists: while
              non-governmental externalities must be corrected by the
              state, we simply have to quietly endure the externalities
              inherent in political process.

              Since there is no incentive to monitor the government,
              democracies must rely upon voluntary donations of
              intelligence and virtue. Because good government depends
              upon these voluntary donations, the public goods argument
              for government falls apart. Either unpaid virtue can make
              government work, in which case government isn't necessary to
              solve the public goods problem; or unpaid virtue is
              insufficient to make government work, in which case the
              government cannot be trusted to solve the public goods
              problem.

              David Friedman has a particularly striking argument
              which goes one step further. Under governmental
              institutions, he explains, good law is a public good and bad
              law is a private good. That is, there is little direct
              personal incentive to lobby for laws that benefit everyone,
              but a strong personal incentive to lobby for laws that
              benefit special interests at the expense of everyone else.
              In contrast, under anarcho-capitalist institutions, good law
              is a private good and bad law is a public good. That is, by
              patronizing a firm which protects oneself, one reinforces
              the existence of socially beneficial law; but there is
              little incentive to "lobby" for the re-introduction of
              government. As Friedman explains, "Good law is still
              expensive - I must spend time and money determining which
              protection agency will best serve me - but having decided
              what I want, I get what I pay for. The benefit of my wise
              purchase goes to me, so I have an incentive to purchase
              wisely. It is now the person who wishes to reintroduce
              government who is caught in a public goods problem. He
              cannot abolish anarchy and reintroduce government for
              himself alone; he must do it for everyone or for no one. If
              he does it for everyone, he himself gets but a tiny fraction
              of the 'benefit' he expects the reintroduction of government
              to provide."

     16. Are anarchists pacifists?

         Again, this is a complicated question because "pacifism" has at
         least two distinct meanings. It may mean "opposition to all
         violence," or it may mean "opposition to all war (i.e., organized
         violent conflict between governments)." Some anarchists are
         pacifists in the first sense; a very large majority of anarchists
         are pacifists in the weaker, second sense.

           a. Tolstoyan absolute pacifism

              The primary anarchistic inspiration for pacifism in
              the first sense is probably Leo Tolstoy. Drawing his
              themes from the Gospels, Tolstoy argued that violence is
              always wrong, including defensive violence. This naturally
              leads Tolstoy to bitterly denounce warfare as well, but what
              is distinctive here is opposition to violence as such,
              whether offensive or defensive. Moreover, the stricture
              against defensive violence would appear to rule out not only
              retribution against criminals, but self-defense against an
              imminent attack.

              This Tolstoyan theme appears most strongly in the writings
              of Christian anarchists and pacifist anarchists, but it pops
              up quite frequently within the broader left-anarchist
              tradition. For example, Kropotkin looked upon criminals with
              pity rather than contempt, and argued that love and
              forgiveness rather than punishment was the only moral
              reaction to criminal behavior. With the self-described
              Christian and pacifist anarchists, the Tolstoyan position is
              a firm conviction; within the broader left-anarchist
              tradition, it would be better described as a tendency or
              general attitude.

              Some left-anarchists and virtually all anarcho-capitalists
              would strongly disagree with Tolstoy's absolute opposition
              to violence. (The only anarcho-capitalist to ever indicate
              agreement with the Tolstoyan position was probably Robert
              LeFevre.) Left-anarchist critics include the advocates of
              revolutionary terrorism or "propaganda by the deed"
              (discussed in section 22), as well as more moderate anti-
              Tolstoyans who merely uphold the right to use violence for
              self-defense. Of course, their definition of "self-defense"
              might very well include using violence to hinder immoral
              state actions or the functioning of the capitalist system.

              The anarcho-capitalist critique of Tolstoyan pacifism is

              distinguishes between initiatory force against person or
              property (which he views as wrong), and retaliatory force
              (which he views as acceptable and possibly meritorious). The
              anarcho-capitalist condemns the state precisely because it
              institutionalizes the initiation of force within society.
              Criminals do the same, differing only in their lack of
              perceived legitimacy. In principle, both "private" criminals
              and the "public" criminals who run the government may be
              both resisted and punished. While it may be imprudent or
              counter-productive to openly resist state authority (just as
              it might be foolish to resist a gang of well- armed
              mobsters), there is a right to do so.

           b. Pacifism as opposition to war

              Almost all anarchists, in contrast, would agree in their
              condemnation of warfare, i.e., violent conflict between
              governments. Left-anarchists and anarcho-capitalists both
              look upon wars as grotesque struggles between ruling elites
              who treat the lives of "their own" people as expendable and
              the lives of the "other side's" people as worthless. It is
              here that anarchism's strong distinction between society and
              the state becomes clearest: whereas most people see war as a
              struggle between societies, anarchists think that war is
              actually a battle between governments which greatly harms
              even the society whose government is victorious. What is
              most pernicious about nationalist ideology is that is makes
              the members of society identify their interests with those
              of their government, when in fact their interests are not
              merely different but in conflict. In short, anarchists of
              both sorts would readily accede to Randolph Bourne's remark
              that "War is the health of the state."

              Left-anarchists' opposition to war is quite similar
              to the general condemnation of war expressed by more
              mainstream international socialists. On this view, war is
              created by capitalism, in particular the struggle for access
              to markets in the Third World. "Workingmen have no country"
              and should refuse to support these intra-capitalist
              struggles; why should they pay the dire cost of war when
              victory will merely leave them more oppressed and exploited
              than before? Moreover, while Western democracies often
              advocate war in the name of justice and humanitarianism, the
              aim and/or end result is to defend traditional
              authoritarianism and destroy the lives of millions of
              innocent people. Within the Western democracies, the left-
              anarchist's hatred for war is often intensified by some
              sense of sympathy for indigenous revolutionary movements.
              While these movements are often state-socialist in intent,
              the left- anarchist often believes that these movements are
              less bad than the traditional authoritarianism against which
              they struggle. Moreover, the West's policy of propping up
              local dictators leads relatively non-authoritarian socialist
              movements to increasing degrees of totalitarianism. Noam
              Chomsky is almost certainly the most influential
              representative of the left-anarchist approach to foreign
              policy: He sees a consistent pattern of the United States
              proclaiming devotion to human rights while supporting
              dictatorships by any means necessary.

              The anarcho-capitalist critique of war is similar in many
              ways to e.g. Chomsky's analysis, but has a different lineage
              and emphasis. As can be seen particularly in Murray
              Rothbard's writings, the anarcho-capitalist view of war
              draws heavily upon both the anti-war classical liberals of
              the 18th and 19th centuries, and the long-standing American
              isolationist tradition. Early classical liberal theorists
              such as Adam Smith,Richard Cobden, and John Bright (and
              later Norman Angell) argued that warfare was caused by
              mercantilism, by the prevailing alliance between governments
              and their favored business elites. The solution, in their
              view, was to end the incestuous connection between business
              and government. The American isolationists were probably
              influenced by this broader classical liberal tradition, but
              placed more emphasis on the idea that foreign wars were at
              best a silly distraction, and at worst a rationalization for
              tyranny. Both views argued that "balance of power" politics
              lead inevitably to endless warfare and unrestrained military
              spending.

              Building upon these two interrelated traditions, anarcho-
              capitalists have built a multi-layered attack upon warfare.
              Firstly, modern war particularly deserves moral condemnation
              (according to libertarian rights theory) for the widespread
              murderous attacks upon innocent civilians -- whether by bomb
              or starvation blockade. Secondly, the wars waged by the
              Western democracies in the 20th- century had disastrous,
              unforeseen consequences: World War I paved the way for
              Communist, fascist, and Nazi totalitarianism; and World War
              II, by creating power vacuums in Europe and Asia, turned
              over a billion human beings to Stalinist despotism. The
              anarcho-capitalist sees these results as predictable rather
              than merely accidental: just as rulers' hubris leads them to
              try to improve the free- market economy, only to find that
              in their ignorance they have wrecked terrible harm, so too
              does the "fatal conceit" of the national security advisor
              lead Western democracies to spend billions of dollars and
              millions of lives before he finds that he has inadvertently
              paved the way for totalitarianism. The anarcho-capitalist's
              third point against war is that its only sure result is to
              aid the domestic expansion of state power; and predictably,
              when wars end, the state's power never contracts to its
              original limits.

     17. Have there been any historical examples of anarchist societies?

         There have probably been no societies which fully satisfy any
         anarchists' ethical ideals, but there have been a number of
         suggestive examples.

         Left-anarchists most often cite the anarchist communes of the
         Spanish Civil War as examples of viable anarchist societies. The
         role of the Spanish anarchists in the Spanish Civil War has
         perhaps generated more debate on alt.society.anarchy than any
         other historical issue. Since this FAQ is concerned primarily
         with theoretical rather than purely historical questions, the
         reader will have to search elsewhere for a detailed discussion.
         Suffice it to say that left-anarchists generally believe that:
         (a) The Spanish anarchist political organizations and unions
         began and remained democratic throughout the war; (b) That a
         majority of the citizenry in areas controlled by the anarchists
         was sympathetic to the anarchist movement; (c) That workers
         directly controlled factories and businesses that they
         expropriated, rather than being subject to strict control by
         anarchist leaders; and (d) That the farm collectives in the
         anarchist-controlled regions were largely voluntary, and rarely
         exerted coercive pressure against small farmers who refused to
         join. In contrast, anarcho-capitalist critics such as James
         Donald normally maintain that: (a) The Spanish anarchist
         political organizations and unions, even if they were initially
         democratic, quickly transformed into dictatorial oligarchies with
         democratic trappings once the war started; (b) That the Spanish
         anarchists, even if they initially enjoyed popular support,
         quickly forfeited it with their abuse of power; (c) That in many
         or most cases, "worker" control meant dictatorial control by the
         anarchist elite; and (d) That the farm collectivizations in
         anarchist-controlled regions were usually coercively formed,
         totalitarian for their duration, and marked by a purely nominal
         right to remain outside the collective (since non-joining farmers
         were seriously penalized in a number of ways). For a reply to
         James Donald's piece, click here.

         For my own account of the controversy regarding the Spanish
         Anarchists, see The Anarcho-Statists of Spain: An Historical,
         Economic, and Philosophical Analysis of Spanish Anarchism. For a
         reply to my piece, click here.

         Israeli kibbutzim have also been admired as working examples of
         voluntary socialism. Kropotkin and Bakunin held up the mir, the
         traditional communal farming system in rural Russia, as
         suggestive of the organization and values which would be
         expressed in an anarchist society. Various experimental
         communities have also laid claim to socialist anarchist
         credentials.

         Anarcho-capitalists' favorite example, in contrast, is medieval
         Iceland. David Friedman has written extensively on the
         competitive supply of defense services and anarchistic character
         of a much-neglected period of Iceland's history. Left-anarchists
         have occasionally criticized Friedman's work on medieval Iceland,
         but overall this debate is much sketchier than the debate over
         the Spanish Civil War. See Is Medieval Iceland an example of
         "anarcho"-capitalism working in practice?; for David Friedman's
         reply to an earlier draft of this piece , click here.

         A long stretch of medieval Irish history has also been claimed to
         have pronounced anarcho-capitalist features. Other
         anarcho-capitalists have argued that the American "Wild West"
         offers an excellent illustration of anarcho-capitalist
         institutions springing up only to be later suppressed and crowded
         out by government. Anarcho- capitalists also often note that
         while the United States has never been an anarchist society by
         any stretch of the imagination, that before the 20th-century the
         United States came closer to their pure laissez-faire ideals than
         any other society in history. America's colonial and
         revolutionary period especially interests them. Murray Rothbard
         in particular published a four-volume history of the colonial and
         revolutionary eras, finding delight in a brief period of
         Pennsylvania's history when the state government virtually
         dissolved itself due to lack of interest. (An unpublished fifth
         volume in the series defended the "weak" Articles of the
         Confederation against the strong, centralized state established
         by the U.S. Constitution.)

         One case that has inspired both sorts of anarchists is that of
         the free cities of medieval Europe. The first weak link in the
         chain of feudalism, these free cities became Europe's centers of
         economic development, trade, art, and culture. They provided a
         haven for runaway serfs, who could often legally gain their
         freedom if they avoided re-capture for a year and a day. And they
         offer many examples of how people can form mutual-aid
         associations for protection, insurance, and community. Of course,
         left-anarchists and anarcho-capitalists take a somewhat different
         perspective on the free cities: the former emphasize the
         communitarian and egalitarian concerns of the free cities, while
         the latter point to the relatively unregulated nature of their
         markets and the wide range of services (often including defense,
         security, and legal services) which were provided privately or
         semi-privately. Kropotkin's Mutual Aid contains an extensive
         discussion of the free cities of medieval Europe;
         anarcho-capitalists have written less on the subject, but
         strongly praise the historical treatments in Henri Pirenne's
         Medieval Cities and Harold Berman's Law and Revolution.

         The Enclopedia Brittanica article on Anarchism gives at best a
         cursory summary of anarchist theory, but does contain useful
         information on the history of left-anarchist political and labor
         movements. Click here to view the article.

     18. Isn't anarchism utopian?

         Utopianism is perhaps the most popular criticism made of
         anarchism. In an atypically uncharitable passage in his European
         Socialism, socialist historian Carl Landauer states:

              There is certainly one truth in anarchistic beliefs:
              Every large organization contains an element of veiled
              or open force, and every kind of force is an evil, if
              we consider its effects on the human character. But is
              it not the lesser evil? Can we dispense with force?
              When this question is clearly put, the case for
              anarchism seems extremely weak. It is true, that the
              experiment of an entirely forceless society have never
              been made. But such evidence as we have does not
              indicate that ill intentions will cease to exist if
              repressive force disappears, and it is clear enough
              that one ill-intentioned person can upset a large part
              of society if there is no repressive force. The fact
              that some intelligent and highly idealistic men and
              women have believed and still believe in anarchism
              shows that there is a type of sectarianism which
              accepts a belief in spite of, or perhaps because of,
              its apparent absurdity.

         As we have seen, however, virtually all anarcho-capitalists and
         many left-anarchists accept the use of force in some
         circumstances. Landauer's remark would be better directed at
         absolute pacifists rather than anarchists in general.

         Anarchists' supposed unwillingness to use force in any
         circumstance is only one reason why they have been widely
         perceived as utopian. Sometimes the utopian charge is trivial;
         if, for example, any radical change is labelled "utopian." If on
         the other hand "utopian" simply means that anarchism could work
         if and only if all people were virtuous, and thus in practice
         would lead to the imposition of new forms of oppression, then the
         question is more interesting. Interesting, because this is more
         or less the charge that different types of anarchists frequently
         bring against each other.

         To the left-anarchist, for example, anarcho-capitalism is based
         upon a truly fantastic picture of economics, in which free
         competition somehow leads to prosperity and freedom for all. To
         them, the anarcho-capitalists' vision of "economic harmonies" and
         the workings of the "invisible hand" are at best unlikely, and
         probably impossible. Hence, in a sense they accuse the
         anarcho-capitalists of utopianism.

         The anarcho-capitalists charge the left-anarchists similarly. For
         the latter imagine that somehow a communitarian society could
         exist without forcible repression of dissenting individualists;
         think that incentives for production would not be impaired by
         enforced equality; and confusedly equate local democracy with
         freedom. Moreover, they generally have no explanation for how
         crime would be prevented or what safeguards would prevent the
         rise of a new ruling elite. For the anarcho-capitalist, the
         left-anarchist is again hopelessly utopian.

         But in any case, probably most anarchists would offer a similar
         reply to the charge that they are utopians. Namely: what is truly
         utopian is to imagine that somehow the government can hold
         massive power without turning it to monstrous ends. As Rothbard
         succinctly puts it: "the man who puts all the guns and all the
         decision-making power into the hands of the central government
         and then says, 'Limit yourself'; it is he who is truly the
         impractical utopian." Is not the whole history of the 20th
         century an endless list of examples of governments easily
         breaking the weak bonds placed upon their ability to oppress and
         even murder as they see fit?

     19. Don't anarchists assume that all people are innately virtuous?

         This is a perfectly reasonable question, for it is indeed the
         case that some anarchists expect a remarkable change in human
         nature to follow (or precede?) the establishment of an anarchist
         society. This assumption partially explains the frequent lack of
         explanation of how an anarchist society would handle crime,
         dissenting individualists, and so on.

         The belief in innate human virtue is normally found only among
         left-anarchist thinkers, but of course it does not follow, nor is
         it true, that all left-anarchist thinkers believe in humanity's
         innate human virtue.

         Anarcho-capitalists have a very different picture of human
         nature. While they normally believe that people have a strong
         capacity for virtuous action (and it is to people's moral sense
         that they frequently appeal when they favor the abolition of the
         state), they believe that it is wise and necessary to cement
         moral virtue with material incentives. Capitalism's system of
         unequal wages, profits and losses, rent and interest, is not only
         morally justified but vitally necessary for the preservation and
         expansion of the economy. In short, anarcho-capitalists believe
         in and indeed must depend on some reasonable level of human
         morality, but prefer to rely on material incentives when
         feasible. (Similarly, they morally condemn crime and believe that
         most people have no desire to commit crimes, but strongly favor
         some sort of criminal justice system to deter the truly amoral.)

     20. Aren't anarchists terrorists?

         Aren't statists terrorists? Well, some of the them are; in fact,
         the overwhelming majority of non-governmental groups who murder
         and destroy property for political aims believe that government
         ought to exist (and that they ought to run it). And just as the
         existence of such statist terrorists is a poor argument for
         anarchism, the existence of anarchist terrorists is a poor
         argument against anarchism. For any idea whatever, there will
         always be those who advocate advancing it by violence.

         It is however true that around the turn of the century, a certain
         segment of anarchists advocated what they called "propaganda by
         the deed." Several heads of state were assassinated by
         anarchists, along with businessmen, industrialists,
         stock-brokers, and so on. One of the most famous instances was
         when the young Alexander Berkman tried to murder the steel
         industrialist Henry Frick. During this era, the left-anarchists
         were divided as to the permissibility of terrorism; but of course
         many strongly opposed it. And individualist anarchists such as
         Benjamin Tucker almost always saw terrorist activities as both
         counter-productive and immoral when innocents were injured (as
         they often were).

         The basic argument of the advocates of "propaganda by the deed"
         was that anarchist terrorism would provoke governments -- even
         avowedly liberal and democratic governments -- to resort to
         increasingly harsh measures to restore order. As governments'
         ruthlessness increased, their "true colors" would appear for all
         to see, leading to more immediate results than mere education and
         theorizing. As E.V. Zenker notes in his Anarchism: A Criticism
         and History of the Anarchist Theory, a number of Western
         governments were driven to adopt anti-terrorist laws as a result
         of anarchist terrorism. (Zenker goes on to note that Great
         Britain remained true to its liberal heritage by refusing to
         punish individuals merely for espousing anarchist ideas.) But as
         one might expect, contrary to the terrorists' hopes, it was the
         reputation of anarchism -- peaceful and violent alike -- which
         suffered rather than the reputation of the state.

         Undoubtedly the most famous modern terrorist in the tradition of
         "propaganda by the deed" is the so-called Unabomber, who
         explicitly labels himself an anarchist in his now-famous
         manifesto. In his manifesto, the Unabomber makes relatively
         little attempt to link himself to any particular figures in the
         anarchist tradition, but professes familiarity and general
         agreement with the anarchistic wing of the radical
         environmentalist movement. A large proportion of this
         wide-ranging manifesto criticizes environmentalists' cooperation
         with socialists, minority rights activists, and other broadly
         left-wing groups; the point of this criticism is not of course to
         propose an alliance with conservatives, but to reject alliance
         with people who fail to reject technology as such. The more
         positive portion of the manifesto argues that freedom and
         technology are inherently incompatible, and outlines a program
         for the destruction of both modern industry and the scientific
         knowledge necessary to sustain it.

         The large majority of anarchists -- especially in modern
         times -- fervently oppose the killing of innocents on
         purely moral grounds (just as most non-anarchists presumably do,
         though anarchists would often classify those killed in war as
         murder victims of the state). Nonviolence and pacifism now
         inspire far more anarchist thinkers than visions of random
         terror. Anarchists from many different perspectives have been
         inspired by the writings of the 16th-century Frenchman Etienne de
         la Boetie, whose quasi-anarchistic The Discourse of Voluntary
         Servitude spelled out a detailed theory of nonviolent revolution.
         La Boetie explained that since governments depend upon the
         widespread belief in their legitimacy in order to rule, despotism
         could be peacefully overthrown by refusing to cooperate with the
         state. Henry David Thoreau influenced many nonviolent protest
         movements with a similar theme in "On the Duty of Civil
         Disobedience." As Thoreau put it: "If the alternative is to keep
         all just men in prison, or give up war and slavery, the State
         will not hesitate which to choose." The success of the nonviolent
         anti-communist revolutions lends new support to the tactical
         insight of la Boetie and Thoreau.

         But anarchists have a more instrumental reason to oppose the use
         of violence. Terrorism has been very effective in establishing
         new and more oppressive regimes; but it is nearly impossible to
         find any instance where terrorism led to greater freedom. For the
         natural instinct of the populace is to rally to support its
         government when terrorism is on the rise; so terrorism normally
         leads to greater brutality and tighter regulation by the existing
         state. And when terrorism succeeds in destroying an existing
         government, it merely creates a power vacuum without
         fundamentally changing anyone's mind about the nature of power.
         The predictable result is that a new state, worse than its
         predecessor, will swiftly appear to fill the void. Thus, the
         importance of using nonviolent tactics to advance anarchist ideas
         is hard to overstate.

     21. How might an anarchist society be achieved?

         On one level, most modern anarchists agree fully that
         education and persuasion are the most effective way to
         move society towards their ultimate destination. There is the
         conviction that "ideas matter"; that the state exists because
         most people honestly and firmly believe that the state is just,
         necessary, and beneficial, despite a few drawbacks. Winston
         Churchill famously remarked that, "It has been said that
         democracy is the worst form of government, except all the others
         that have been tried." The anarchist's goal is to disprove
         Churchill's claim: to show that contrary to popular belief,
         Western democracy is not only bad but inferior to a very
         different but realistic alternative.

         Aside from this, the similarity between anarchist approaches
         breaks down. In particular, what should the "transitional" phase
         look like? Anarcho-capitalists generally see every reduction in
         government power and activity as a step in the right direction.
         In consequence, they usually support any measure to deregulate,
         repeal laws, and cut taxation and spending (naturally with the
         caveat that the cuts do not go nearly far enough). Similarly,
         they can only hail the spread of the underground economy or
         "black market," tax evasion, and other acts of defiance against
         unjust laws.

         The desirable transitional path for the left-anarchist is more
         problematic. It is hard to support expansion of the state when it
         is the state that one opposes so fervently. And yet, it is
         difficult to advocate the abolition of e.g. welfare programs when
         they are an important means of subsistence for the oppressed
         lower classes of capitalist society. Perhaps the most viable
         intermediate step would be to expand the voluntary alternatives
         to capitalist society: voluntary communes, cooperatives,
         worker-owned firms, or whatever else free people might establish
         to fulfill their own needs while they enlighten others.

     22. What are some addresses for anarchist World Wide Web sites?

         To begin with, there is my homepage at:
            + Bryan Caplan Archives
              http://www.gmu.edu/departments/economics/bcaplan

              I keep the list of addresses short because the sites
              provided allow easy access to a large number of related
              sites.

              Some starting points for discussion of left-anarchism are:

            + Anarchist Archives
              http://www.miyazaki-mic.ac.jp/
              faculty/dward/Anarchist_Archives/archivehome.html
              The best page of its type, in my view.

            + Prominent Anarchists and Left-Libertarians
              http://www.tigerden.com/~berios/libertarians.html

            + The Portland Anarchist Web Page
              http://www.ee.pdx.edu/~jason/

            + An Anarchy Page
              http://www.duke.edu/~eagle/anarchy/

            + Anarchist Yearbook -- Phoenix Press
              http://web.cs.city.ac.uk/homes/louise/yearbk.html

            + Spunk Press Catalog
              http://www.cwi.nl/cwi/people/Jack.Jansen/spunk/cat-us/Toplevel.html

            + Critiques of Libertarianism
              http://world.std.com/~mhuben/libindex.html

            + Burn
              http://burn.ucsd.edu/Welcome.html

            + All About Anarchism
              http://www.geocities.com/CapitolHill/2419/index.html

              Some starting points for discussion of anarcho-capitalism
              are:

            + Free-market.com
              http://www.free-market.com

            + James Donald's Liberty Page
              http://www.jim.com/jamesd/world.html

            + Institute for Humane Studies
              http://mason.gmu.edu/~ihs

            + Niels Buhl Homepage
              http://www.math.ku.dk/~buhl

            + Libertarian Web Page
              http://lw3.ag.uiuc.edu/liberty/libweb.html

            + International Society for Individual Liberty
              http://www.creative.net/~star/

            + Libertarian Alliance
              http://www.digiweb.com/igeldard/LA/

            + David Friedman Homepage
              http://www.best.com/~ddfr

              There are several other anarchism FAQs available on the web.
              None of them are to my complete satisfaction; among other
              failings, they normally either ignore anarcho-capitalism
              entirely, or attack a straw man version thereof, and thus do
              little to clarify the most heated of the net-related
              debates. On the positive side, these other FAQs often have
              much more historical information than mine does. See for
              yourself.

            + http://www.ibw.com.ni/~dlabs/anarquismo/every.html
            + http://tigerden.com/~berios/libsoc.html
            + http://www.art.net/Poets/Jennifer/anarchy/archyfaq2.html
            + http://www.vnet.net/users/goodag/birdo/ana.html
            + http://www.wam.umd.edu/~ctmunson/TEXT/sp000284.html

              There does exist a FAQ written by Roger McCain on
              libertarian socialism and left-anarchism of markedly higher
              quality than the preceding five. It is archived at:
            + http://william-king.www.drexel.edu/top/personal/LSfaq/faq_ToC.html

              A new, highly detailed FAQ from a left-anarchist perspective
              has recently been set up, ostensibly in celebration of the
              60th anniversary of the Spanish Revolution. It is available
              at:
            + http://www.geocities.com/CapitolHill/1931

              My FAQ is beginning to amass its share of critics who prefer
              to write full-length replies. Those that I am aware of are:
            + Rebuttal to the Anarchism FAQ of Bryan Caplan by Lamont
              Granquist

            + Replies to Some Errors and Distortions in Bryan Caplan's
              Anarchist Theory FAQ version 4.1.1

              My only comment is that it is simply untrue that I have
              ignored criticisms of my FAQ. There are numerous points I
              have altered or expanded it due to criticism I have
              received; and when I disagree with a critic's claim, I
              frequently ask permission to quote their reservations
              verbatim in the next revision. It is however true that I
              only respond to private e-mail criticisms; attacks simply
              posted to Usenet are unlikely to come to my attention.

         To my knowledge there is no page which contains a broad survey
         along the lines of this FAQ. However, these sources in
         combination should give a good picture of the wide range of
         anarchist opinion, along with more information on history and
         current events which I chose not to discuss in detail herein.
         Examination of these sites can also give a reasonable picture of
         how left-anarchism and anarcho- capitalism intellectually relate
         to the broader progressive and libertarian movements,
         respectively.

     23. What are some major anarchist writings?

         This list is by no means intended to be exhaustive; nor does
         inclusion here necessarily indicate that the work is of
         particularly high quality. In particular, both Heider's and
         Marshall's works contain a number of embarrassing factual errors.
         (Some of the more glaring errors from Marshall's Demanding the
         Impossible appear to have been corrected in this linked exerpt.)

         Particularly well-written and canonical expressions of different
         anarchist theories are noted with an asterisk (*). Broad surveys
         of anarchism are noted with a number sign (#).

            + Mihail Bakunin. God and the State
            + * Mikhail Bakunin. The Political Philosophy of Bakunin
            + Mikhail Bakunin. Statism and Anarchy
            + Bruce Benson. The Enterprise of Law: Justice without the
              State
            + Alexander Berkman. The ABC of Anarchism
            + Etienne de la Boetie. The Discourse of Voluntary Servitude
              (also published as The Politics of Obedience: the Discourse
              of Voluntary Servitude)
            + Burnett Bolloten. The Spanish Civil War: Revolution and
              Counterrevolution
            + Murray Bookchin. Post-Scarcity Anarchism
            + Frank Brooks, ed. The Individualist Anarchists: An Anthology
              of Liberty (1881-1908)
            + Roy Childs. Liberty Against Power
            + Frank Chodorov. Fugitive Essays
            + Noam Chomsky. American Power and the New Mandarins
            + Noam Chomsky. The Chomsky Reader
            + Tyler Cowen, ed. The Theory of Market Failure (also
              published as Public Goods and Market Failures)
            + Douglas Davis and Charles Holt. Experimental Economics
            + Ronald Fraser. Blood of Spain: An Oral History of the
              Spanish Civil War
            + * David Friedman. The Machinery of Freedom
            + William Godwin. The Anarchist Writings of William Godwin
            + Emma Goldman. Anarchism and Other Essays
            + *# Daniel Guerin. Anarchism: From Theory to Practice
            + # Ulrike Heider. Anarchism: Left, Right, and Green
            + Hans-Hermann Hoppe. A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism
            + Anthony de Jasay. Social Contract, Free Ride
            + Leonard Krimerman and Lewis Perry, eds. Patterns of Anarchy
            + * Peter Kropotkin. The Essential Kropotkin
            + Peter Kropotkin. Mutual Aid: A Factor in Evolution
            + * Carl Landauer. European Socialism: A History of Ideas and
              Movements
            + Bruno Leoni. Freedom and the Law
            + Wendy McElroy. Freedom, Feminism, and the State
            + # Peter Marshall. Demanding the Impossible: A History of
              Anarchism
            + James Martin. Men Against the State: The Expositors of
              Individualist Anarchism in America, 1827-1908
            + Gustave de Molinari. "The Production of Security"
            + Albert Jay Nock. Our Enemy the State
            + Albert Jay Nock. The State of the Union
            + Robert Nozick. Anarchy, State, and Utopia
            + Franz Oppenheimer. The State
            + David Osterfeld. Freedom, Society, and the State : An
              Investigation into the Possibility of Society without
              Government
            + *# J. Roland Pennock and John W. Chapman, eds. Anarchism,
              Nomos vol.19
            + Pierre-Joseph Proudhon. What is Property?
            + Murray Rothbard. Egalitarianism as a Revolt Against Nature
            + Murray Rothbard. The Ethics of Liberty
            + * Murray Rothbard. For a New Liberty
            + Murray Rothbard. Power and Market
            + David Schmidtz. The Limits of Government: An Essay on the
              Public Goods Argument
            + Lysander Spooner. The Lysander Spooner Reader
            + * Lysander Spooner. No Treason: The Constitution of No
              Authority
            + Max Stirner. The Ego and Its Own
            + Morris and Linda Tannehill. The Market for Liberty
            + Henry David Thoreau. The Portable Thoreau
            + Leo Tolstoy. Tolstoy on Civil Disobedience and Non- Violence
            + Benjamin Tucker. Instead of a Book, by a Man Too Busy to
              Write One
            + Gordon Tullock, ed. Further Explorations in the Theory of
              Anarchy
            + Robert Paul Wolff. In Defence of Anarchism
            + # George Woodcock. Anarchism: A History of Libertarian Ideas
              and Movements
            + # E.V. Zenker. Anarchism: A Criticism and History of the
              Anarchist Theory

    ----------------------------------------------------------------------

    For comments, suggestions, corrections, etc., write
    [email protected]. Thanks to Fabio Rojas, James Donald, David
    Friedman, Robert Vienneau, Ken Steube, Ben Haller, Vincent Cook, Bill
    Woolsey, Conal Smith, Jim Kalb, Chris Faatz, J. Shamlin, Keith Lynch,
    Rose Lucas, Bruce Baechler, Jim Cook, Jack Jansen, Tom Wetzel, Steve
    Koval, Brent Jass, Tracy Harms, Ian Goddard, and I.M. McKay for
    helpful advice or other assistance.

    Return to Bryan Caplan Homepage